Roots of Freedom
eBook - ePub

Roots of Freedom

A Primer on Modern Liberty

John W. Danford

Share book
  1. 226 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Roots of Freedom

A Primer on Modern Liberty

John W. Danford

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Roots of Freedom is a primer on the thinkers and ideas that, over many centuries, have laid the foundations of free societies. Concepts such as the rule of law, independent judiciary, limited government, free markets, and individual autonomy are traced in the writings of (among others) Luther, Machiavelli, Hobbes, Locke, Montesquieu, Hume, Adam Smith, the American founders, Alexis de Tocqueville, and John Stuart Mill.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Roots of Freedom an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Roots of Freedom by John W. Danford in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in History & World History. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2014
ISBN
9781497648906
Topic
History
Index
History
Chapter 1
ROOTS IN ANCIENT GREECE
image
Modern Western “democracies,” as they are usually called, are actually better described as liberal commercial societies. They rest on principles of individualism and individual rights—especially legal rights—which are more fundamental than democracy, and also much newer. Democracy, after all, is an ancient Greek word for “rule by the many,” and democracies have not until quite recently been regarded as very good or fair types of governments. The many can oppress the few quite as easily as the reverse, and the notion of individual rights actually has more to do with limiting the power of any government—whether by the many, or by a king, or by a party—to treat individuals unjustly.
In a very general way the core idea of liberal commercial societies is individualism. The view that has gained acceptance in the last three hundred years in the West is that society should be thought of as a collection of individuals whose needs and purposes lead them to constitute society, or to continue living in a society, as a way of furthering their individual needs and purposes. This individualism thus presumes that human beings should be understood primarily as individual organisms, who are what they are whether or not they live in some social order. More than that, it presumes that the needs and goals of human individuals—not just survival, but dignity, the active use of faculties, and a measure of security and comfort—are able to be understood in reference to individual men and women, with society but a means to achieve the goals or supply the needs more reliably or more easily.
This view of human beings as individuals “by nature” was advanced as a challenge to the view that rested at the core of classical political science, a mode of thinking which prevailed in the West (where it was invented in ancient Greece) for nearly two thousand years. The modern view can best be understood in comparison to the older view it replaced. The prevailing modern view was not unknown to ancient or classical thinkers, of course, but they rejected it in favor of an understanding more closely connected to their conception of the nature of all things.
The ancient Greek political philosophers taught that man is by nature a political being. By this they meant that human beings are suited naturally—by nature—for life in a particular sort of community, called a polis or city. Any human being not fortunate enough to live in a polis, they said, would not be capable of realizing his full humanity or “humanness.”
They also knew that many, if not most, men and women were cut off from the possibility of being fully human because they lived either outside cities (as nomads or shepherds, condemned to what Marx later disparaged as the “idiocy of rural life”), or in vast empires, far too large to have any taste of genuine political life. The special characteristic of a city or polis is that in a city human beings are able to exercise one of their highest, most human faculties, which the Greeks called logos or reasoned speech. This capacity is involved in all political deliberation, by which human beings exercise choice about how to live and how to constitute social life itself. According to Aristotle, the faculty of logos distinguishes men from all other animals. It is also what makes man the only being who is political by nature. Any man who lives outside a polis, he taught, must be either a beast or a god—either less than human (because falling short of the true human potential) or more than human (and hence self-sufficient).
The Greeks thought one should conceive the nature of anything by thinking about its perfection or completion, that is, what the thing is able to be in the best or most appropriate circumstances. This is an extraordinarily dynamic way of looking at things: each particular example of a thing (whether a man or an oak tree), since it falls short of perfection, could be said to point beyond itself to what it ought to be. This exciting idea led men to think about what a polis or city ought to be, or what the nature of political life would be in its full perfection. And this is where complexities began to develop. The lofty idea that man is a political being by nature seemed, on reflection, to have troubling consequences in at least two respects.
One troubling implication was brought out by Aristotle himself, the greatest classical political scientist. He began by examining the claim that man’s political nature is only fully developed when human beings live in a community and rule themselves, that is, when they speak, deliberate, and choose. If ruling is a noble and challenging occupation, one which develops and displays man’s highest faculties, it would seem obvious that anyone seeking to develop his capacities and test himself to the fullest would seek to rule, and seek to rule in the most challenging circumstances. If this is so, then to rule a larger territory or more people—which is more difficult—must be better, and to rule on a larger scale would show a man to be more fully human than someone who rules a smaller city or fewer people. Thus the notion that political rule is the most human or noble calling seems to lead to the consequence that just as a man will seek to extend his rule, a fully developed polis will seek to rule over others. Such a polis will be, in short, imperialistic in its inclinations. For Aristotle this logic suggested the need to reexamine the notion of political activity as choiceworthy for its own sake.
A second troubling consequence was harder for Aristotle to see, because it challenged the very notion that man is political by nature, an idea he accepted. But in the long run it was a more powerful objection, and played a decisive role in the modern rejection of the classical notion that man is political by nature. If man is political by nature, a man can only become fully human if he is fortunate enough to live in a political community, and indeed in one which permits or even encourages the full flowering of his most human capacities. If we understand human nature this way, we must conclude that what a human being becomes depends on the polis or city where that human being grows up. Thus he would be indebted to the city for his very humanness, for those capacities that set him apart as fully human. On such an understanding, a man’s primary relation to the city or polis is one of obligation. The duties of citizenship, which can be very burdensome, would have the greatest claim on a man’s time and attention because the individual is in principle subordinate to the polis or city.
But is there then any limit to what the city can ask of the citizens or subject them to? Does the city’s claim on the citizen cover not merely his time and loyalty but his property? Does it extend even to his children? Must everything be understood as belonging in principle to the polis first? And what of those who are not rulers in the city—since not all can be rulers? Is there anything valuable in their lives? Are there any human capacities they can display or enjoy or take pride in? Doesn’t the elevation of the political realm in such an understanding mean at the same time the denigration of all other human endeavors, of the other parts of human life?
In many ancient cities—even republics—the individual was entirely subordinate to the city. In ancient Sparta or early Rome, it was the citizen’s duty—indeed crowning glory—to produce children for the republic’s armies, and at the merest request of his authorities to sacrifice his own life for the city. And the most “political” of these communities, which understood men as political being, were indeed devoted largely to war and conquest, just as Aristotle suggested that they must or would be, based on the internal logic that exalted ruling and political life.
But if there were two troubling consequences to the lofty idea that man is a political being, there were also two suggestions for avoiding the troubling consequences. One was theoretical, the other practical. Aristotle’s theoretical attempt to resolve the problem was based on the suggestion that while man is a political being by nature, he is also potentially more than that. The idea that political activity is the highest way of exercising the distinctly human virtues is, according to Aristotle, based on a mistaken understanding of “activity.” It is agreed, he said, that “the best way of life both separately for each individual and in common for cities is that accompanied by virtue.”1 But while some believe virtue is displayed only in political life and ruling, others say another kind of activity exists which is not political, though it does involve the highest faculties. This other kind of active life involves the life of the mind, and points to the philosophic life as the highest or best, rather than that of political rule. But surely a city cannot be devoted to philosophy, the province of only a few rare and gifted minds? Aristotle’s compromise between these two notions is to say that, while it is not possible for a city to lead the philosophic life, a sort of approximation to or echo of the philosophic life can be found in a life devoted to education and the arts. These, he said, are proper concerns for a city. The best possible city, then, would be one not devoted to ruling, war, and tyranny over others, but to the “internal activities” of education, drama, and the other arts.
Of course Aristotle never expected to see such a city. He was aware of the fragility and difficulty of sustaining even a decent city, let alone the best city one could imagine. Yet in the generation before Aristotle’s birth, a city had existed which, in some respects, hinted at or anticipated his idea of the best city. Athens, the great polis which was finally to be defeated by the astonishing military prowess of Sparta, enjoyed in her greatest days a way of life that was self-consciously “balanced” in the way it viewed politics. Thucydides, the great historian of the war between Athens and Sparta (and himself an admirer of the regime of the Spartans) reported on a speech given by Pericles, the great Athenian leader. The speech is called the funeral oration of Pericles. Its words (perhaps composed by Thucydides) have been celebrated for more than two thousand years, because they offered, in tribute to the Athenians who had died in the war, a moving and impressive account of the Athenian way of life.
Our constitution, is called a democracy because power is in the hands not of a minority but of the many. When it is a question of settling private disputes, everyone is equal before the law; when it is a question of putting one person before another in positions of public responsibility, what counts is not membership of a particular class, but the actual ability which the man possesses. No one, so long as he has it in him to be of service to that state, is kept in political obscurity because of poverty. And, just as our political life is free and open, so is our day-to-day life in our relations with each other. We do not get into a state with our next-door neighbour if he enjoys himself in his own way, nor do we give him the kind of black looks which, though they do no real harm, still do hurt people’s feelings. We are free and tolerant in our private lives; but in public affairs we keep to the law. This is because it commands our deep respect.”2
Pericles drew an explicit contrast with Sparta with regard to the overwhelming emphasis placed by the Spartans on war, on defense and military training—all the things that required total subordination of the individual to the polis in Sparta. As Pericles put it, “there is a great difference between us and our opponents, in our attitude towards military security. Here are some examples: Our city is open to the world, and we have no periodical deportations in order to prevent people observing or finding our secrets which might be of military advantage to the enemy. This is because we rely, not on secret weapons, but on our own real courage and loyalty. There is a difference, too, in our educational systems. The Spartans, from their earliest boyhood, are submitted to the most laborious training in courage; we pass our lives without all these restrictions, and yet are just as ready to face the same dangers as they are.”3
As these words suggest, the ancient Greeks were aware, however dimly, of the possibilities of individualism. For at least a brief time, in at least one ancient polis, men and women took seriously the idea that not everything should be subordinated to the requirements of the community—at least in normal times, when the city was at peace. While Athenian individualism was a far cry from the individualism of modern liberal societies, its brief existence and quick demise teach an important lesson about the fragility of any social order willing to emphasize or tolerate the idea that an individual has dignity in his own right and not merely as a cog in the larger machine of political life.
But individualism—notwithstanding its appearance in the ancient world, Christian as well as pagan—never attained prominence in that world. What we have glimpsed briefly in long-ago Athens soon disappeared, and many centuries were to pass before a genuine individualism was to appear again, on more solid foundations. In the following chapters we will explore those foundations. Our goal is to trace the development of this idea and of other key ideas about man, about nature, law, society, and the goals of life, which eventually allowed societies of free individuals to emerge. Such societies have existed for a very brief span, considered against the background of human history in general, and their existence may depend, more than most people think, on the ideas men and women hold dear.
1 Aristotle, The Politics, translated by Carnes Lord (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 7.1, 1323b40-41. References are to the Bekker numbers.
2 Thucydides, History of the Peloponnesian War, translated by Rex Warner (London: Penguin, 1954), p. 145.
3Ibid., p. 146.
Chapter 2
ROOTS IN PREMODERN CHRISTIANITY
image
Before we move to the modern period, when the most important of the roots of free society begin to grow, it is worthwhile to glance briefly at the contributions of the ancient Christian understanding of man and the cosmos. It should be emphasized, however, that the ideas we will consider—as with those of the Greeks—are more properly seen as glimpses or anticipations of the principles that are the real bedrock of a free society.
There are four ways in which the early Christian understanding of man, and of man’s place in “the scheme of things,” offer us a glimpse of the foundations of freedom. At the time of Jesus, the distinctive feature of the ancient Mediterranean world was the enormous power and authority of Rome and the Roman Empire. Roman legions occupied vast portions of the known world and enforced what is called the Pax Romana, the peace and order under Roman imperial rule, backed up by the often ruthless use of arms. In this world, as in most of the ancient communities, the individual counted for nothing. The life of a particular man, woman, or child was of little value, because it was measured in relation to the importance of Rome itself, the Imperial City.
A story from Plutarch, related by the modern author Jean-Jacques Rousseau, tells us something important about the way the world was understood by people in ancient times. The story concerns a Spartan woman, and it brings out the attitude of genuine citizenship that was the goal of the ancient republics. The woman had five sons in the Spartan army, and she anxiously awaited news of the battle in which they fought. A messenger arrives, and, “trembling, she asks him for news. ‘Your five sons were killed.’ ‘Base slave, did I ask you that?’ ‘We won the victory.’ The mother runs to the temple and gives thanks to the gods. This is the female citizen,” Rousseau tells us.1 The lesson of the story is the insignificance of individuals—even loved ones, even five sons!—in relation to the city or political community.
What was true of the Greek city of Sparta was true also of Rome in her days of greatness as a republic. And under the terrible power of the Roman emperors, even though the grandeur of personal sacrifice had probably lost much of its luster, the individual counted for even less. A particular individual was of no consequence when measured against the glory and stability of the empire. The imperial Pax Romana was a time of very little freedom. Yet it is just at this time that the life and teachings of Jesus, who was in human terms an insignificant carpenter from a backward province of the...

Table of contents