Great Philosophers Volume One
eBook - ePub

Great Philosophers Volume One

The Road to Inner Freedom, The Art of Philosophizing, and Pilgrimage to Humanity

Baruch Spinoza, Bertrand Russell, Albert Schweitzer

Share book
  1. 470 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Great Philosophers Volume One

The Road to Inner Freedom, The Art of Philosophizing, and Pilgrimage to Humanity

Baruch Spinoza, Bertrand Russell, Albert Schweitzer

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Essential teachings, brilliant musings, and provocative theories from three of history's greatest thinkers. The Road to Inner Freedom: The seventeenth-century Dutch philosopher Baruch Spinoza views the ability to experience rational love of God as the key to mastering the contradictory and violent human emotions. The Art of Philosophizing: These groundbreaking essays by Bertrand Russell deal with "the art of reckoning" in the fields of mathematics, logic, and philosophy. With great clarity and simple exposition, Russell gets to the core of philosophical inquiry and analysis. Pilgrimage to Humanity: Albert Schweitzer discusses his philosophy of culture, the course of his life, his ministry to human needs in Africa, the idea of reverence for life, the ideal of world peace, the significance of liberal Christianity, and the lives, world-views, and contributions of Johann Goethe, Johann Sebastian Bach, and Jesus of Nazareth.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Great Philosophers Volume One an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Great Philosophers Volume One by Baruch Spinoza, Bertrand Russell, Albert Schweitzer in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Philosophers. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2018
ISBN
9781504054898
image
The Art of Philosophizing
And Other Essays
Publisher’s Preface
The essays in this little volume, published here for the first time in book form, were written by Bertrand Russell during the second World War.
In those years the author was teaching philosophy at American universities, exercising a growing influence on America’s student population.
The essays assembled here are fundamentally concerned with “the art of reckoning” in the fields of mathematics, logic and philosophy.
The simplicity of Russell’s exposition is astonishing, as is his ability to get to the core of the great philosophical issues and to skillfully probe the depth of philosophical analysis.
The Art of Rational Conjecture
Let us begin with a few words as to what philosophy is. It is not definite knowledge, for that is science. Nor is it groundless credulity, such as that of savages. It is something between these two extremes; perhaps it might be called “The art of rational conjecture.” According to this definition, philosophy tells us how to proceed when we want to find out what may be true, or is most likely to be true, where it is impossible to know with certainty what is true. The art of rational conjecture is very useful in two different ways. First: often the most difficult step in the discovery of what is true is thinking of a hypothesis which may be true; when once the hypothesis has been thought of, it can be tested, but it may require a man of genius to think of it. Second: we often have to act in spite of uncertainty, because delay would be dangerous or fatal; in such a case, it is useful to possess an art by which we can judge what is probable. This art, so far as very general hypotheses are concerned, is philosophy. Particular questions, such as “will it rain tomorrow?” do not belong to philosophy; philosophy is concerned with general questions, such as: “Is the world governed by mechanical laws, or has it a cosmic purpose, or has it both characteristics at once?” Philosophy examines whether anything can be said on such general questions.
The first thing to realize, if you wish to become a philosopher, is that most people go through life with a whole world of beliefs that have no sort of rational justification, and that one man’s world of beliefs is apt to be incompatible with another man’s, so that they cannot both be right. People’s opinions are mainly designed to make them feel comfortable; truth, for most people is a secondary consideration. You, dear readers, have of course no prejudices; but you will admit that in this you are different from most people. I shall suppose that you are a Baptist from Tennessee. It is obvious to you that America is the greatest country in the world, that Tennessee is the most distinguished of the States, and that the Baptists are the sole repositories of theological truth. Let us suppose that I concede all this. What am I to say to a man from another State or another country? How can I persuade a French Canadian Catholic of the truths which are so luminously evident to you? There are still a good many points about which you and he will agree, but how if you have to argue with a Turk or a Hindu or a Confucian? You will find them questioning most of what you have accepted as unquestionable, and if you are to argue profitably with them you will have to find common ground beneath your respective assumptions.
You will still find some things about which you can agree with the Turk. Are men descended from monkeys? Perish the thought! Is man the supreme glory of the universe? Of course. On such matters your common humanity makes you see eye to eye. But if one day an intelligent being were to arrive from Mars, he might turn out to be as superior to men as men are to monkeys; he might think the difference between men and monkeys very slight, and consider it obvious that they had a common ancestry. He would assert the claims of Mars (unless he were a philosopher) as confidently as you had asserted the claims of Tennessee. And what could you do about it?
If you wish to become a philosopher, you must try, as far as you can, to get rid of beliefs which depend solely upon the place and time of your education, and upon what your parents and schoolmasters told you. No one can do this completely, and no one can be a perfect philosopher, but up to a point we can all achieve it if we wish to. “But why should we wish to?” you may ask. There are several reasons. One of them is that irrational opinions have a great deal to do with war and other forms of violent strife. The only way in which a society can live for any length of time without violent strife is by establishing social justice, and social justice appears to each man to be injustice if he is persuaded that he is superior to his neighbors. Justice between classes is difficult where there is a class that believes itself to have a right to more than a proportionate share of power or wealth. Justice between nations is only possible through the power of neutrals, because each nation believes in its own superior excellence. Justice between creeds is even more difficult, since each creed is convinced that it has a monopoly of the truth of the most important of all subjects. It would be increasingly easier than it is to arrange disputes amicably and justly if the philosophic outlook were more wide-spread.
A second reason for wishing to be philosophic is that mistaken beliefs do not, as a rule, enable you to realize good purposes. In the middle ages, when there was an epidemic of plague, people crowded into the churches to pray, thinking that their piety would move God to take pity on them; in fact, the crowds in ill-ventilated buildings provided ideal conditions for the spread of the infection. If your means are to be adequate to your ends, you must have knowledge, not merely superstition or prejudice.
A third reason is that truth is better than falsehood. There is something ignominious in going about sustained by comfortable lies. The deceived husband is traditionally ludicrous, and there is something of the same laughable or pitiable quality about all happiness that depends upon being deceived or deluded.
If you wish to become a philosopher, you must train both the intellect and the emotions. The two sorts of training are intimately interconnected, but they must be to some extent separated in discussion. I shall begin with the training of the intellect.
The training of the intellect has both a positive and a negative aspect: you have to learn what to believe, and what not to believe. Let us begin with the positive aspect.
Although, in the last analysis, everything may be more or less doubtful, yet some things are so nearly certain that for all practical purposes the element of doubt may be ignored. The would-be philosopher will ask himself what kinds of knowledge seem least open to question, and why. He may, in starting this inquiry, reasonably assume that the most certain kinds of knowledge are those about which there is least dispute. He will soon find that these are not the kinds of knowledge, or supposed knowledge, that are asserted with most vehemence. Everyone is agreed about the multiplication table, but no one goes about proclaiming that it contains Sacred Truth. If anyone were to deny its truth, he would not be burnt at the stake or imprisoned as a fifth columnist. A sensible man, if he fell among arithmetical heretics, and were asked to recant his belief in the multiplication table, would do so, conscious that his recantation could do the multiplication table no harm. These are the characteristics of a belief about which there is no reasonable doubt.
Whoever wishes to become a philosopher will do well to acquire a considerable knowledge of mathematics. In the course of this study he will get to know what sorts of truths can be discovered by mere thinking, without the help of observation. He will also acquire familiarity with exact reasoning, and with the sort of mistakes to which even very expert reasoners are prone. For this last purpose, he will do well to study mathematics historically. For example: before Einstein, everybody thought it had been proved mathematically that gravitation is propagated instantaneously, but Einstein’s theory required that it should be propagated with the velocity of light. Sure enough, the mathematicians found a mistake in the argument which had satisfied them for generations, and now, unless they are Nazis, they are all agreed that Einstein was right about the velocity of gravitation. This, however, was a very advanced and difficult question; it would be a mistake to be led by this instance into a general skepticism about mathematics. What it is right to infer is that, where questions are concerned that are both more complex and more nearly related to our passions than the questions of mathematics, the chance of errors in reasoning becomes very great. This applies especially to social and religious questions.
Logic is useful to the philosopher in its modern form, not in the musty medieval form that the schoolmen produced out of Aristotle. It is useful chiefly as teaching caution in inference. Those who are not trained in logic are prone to inferences that have no validity. For example, if one class or nation is oppressed by another, and you think this oppression ought to cease, they will expect you to regard the oppressed class or nation as possessed of superior virtue, and will be surprised if you do not feel a personal liking for each and every one of them. There is here no logical connection, although to an untrained mind there seems to be one. The more expert you become in logic, the fewer will be the inferences that you allow to be valid, and the seldomer will you regard it as inconsistent to hold two opinions at once. This is important practically, since it allows necessary compromise, and prevents acceptance of some rigid bloc of opinions. Blocs of opinions, such as Catholicism, Communism, or Nazism, tend to be persecuting, and are practically certain to be at least partly false. Practice in logical analysis makes it harder to be satisfied with such ready-made mental clothing.
Logic and mathematics, useful as they are, are only intellectual training for the philosopher. They help him to know how to study the world, but they give him no actual information about it. They are the alphabet of the book of nature, not the book itself.
The knowledge that is needed above all, if you wish to become a philosopher, is knowledge of science—not in its minute detail, but in its general results, its history, and especially its method. It is science that makes the difference between the modern world and the world before the 17th Century. It is science that has destroyed the belief in witchcraft, magic and sorcery. It is science that has made the old creeds and the old superstitions impossible for intelligent men to accept. It is science that has made it laughable to suppose the earth the center of the universe and man the supreme purpose of the creation. It is science that is showing the falsehood of the old dualisms of soul and body, mind and matter, which have their origin in religion. It is science that is beginning to make us understand ourselves, and to enable us, up to a point, to see ourselves from without as curious mechanisms. It is science that has taught us the way to substitute tentative truth for cocksure error. The scientific spirit, the scientific method, the framework of the scientific world, must be absorbed by any one who wishes to have a philosophic outlook belonging to our time, not a literary antiquarian philosophy fetched out of old books. Assuredly Plato was a man of great genius, and Aristotle was comprehensively encyclopedic; but in their modern disciples they can inspire only error. An hour with Galileo or Newton will give you more help towards a sound philosophy than a year with Plato and Aristotle. But if you go to a university, this will not be the opinion of your professors.
Science, we said, is important to the philosopher in its results and in its method. Let us say something about each of those in turn.
As regards results: the first thing of importance to the philosopher is the history of the universe, past and future. The earlier and later parts are conjectural, but there is a long stretch in the middle about which there is not much doubt. It seems that, a good while ago, there was a diffused nebula, something like a very thin mist; some parts were not quite so thin as others, and these gradually became stars. Our star, the sun, either because another star passed near it or for some different reason, gave birth to a number of planets, which, at first, were as hot as their parent, but being smaller they presently cooled. One of them, when it reached a suitable temperature, generated certain chemically complex structures having the property of being able to confer their own composition and structure on suitable neighboring matter. This property is called life. Living structures became gradually more complex as they evolved through the animal and vegetable kingdoms; one of the most complex is man. The existence of life depends upon a number of conditions, chemical and thermal. For countless ages the weather was too hot for life; perhaps in the end it will be too cold. But some astronomers, for instance Sir James Jeans, tell us that before it grows too cold the sun will burst, which will cause the earth and all the other planets to become gaseous. In one way or in another, it is pretty certain that life on earth will presently cease.
The universe is on a large scale, both in time and space. The sun is almost 93 million miles from the earth, and its light reaches us in eight minutes. The nearest of the stars are so distant that their light takes several years to reach us. All the stars we see with the naked eye are part of the milky way, which is one of a vast number of star-clusters. In addition to star-clusters there are nebulae—something like a million of them—which are incredibly remote, so remote that their light takes many hundreds of thousands of years to reach us, although it travels at the rate of 180,000 miles a second. As for the time-scale, the earth has existed for millions of years, but its beginning is recent as compared to the beginnings of the sun. When Sir James Jeans speaks of the possibility of the sun bursting, one gets at first an impression that this catastrophe is imminent, but in the end he consolingly suggests that it will not happen for a million years. The universe, we are told, is steadily tending towards a state in which energy will be uniformly distributed, and therefore useless for all the purposes which it serves at present. When that time comes, and probably long before it, life will be extinct everywhere, and only a miracle could restore it. Even the most religious men of science, unless they are Catholics, agree that these are the most probable conclusions on the present evidence.
Let us contrast this picture of the universe with that presented in the Bible and the Fathers, which was generally accepted throughout Christendom until science caused men to question it. According to the Bible and the Fathers, the universe was created in six days by God’s fiat; the date of the creation can be computed from the data in Genesis, and has been estimated at B.C. 4004. The earth is the center of the universe, and the creation of Adam and Eve was the last act in God’s work. God told them not to eat of the fruit of a certain tree, and when they nevertheless did so, He was very angry, although He had always known that they would disobey Him. He was so angry that He decided on an infinite punishment: they and all their progeny deserved to burn eternally in an everlasting fire. But God the Son took upon himself the punishment due to a certain portion of mankind, by suffering crucifixion and spending three days in hell. In virtue of His suffering, those who hold correct theological opinions and undergo certain ceremonies will go to heaven instead of hell. The visible world will pass away at Christ’s second coming, the date of which is uncertain. The first disciples believed it to be imminent; then it was expected in 1000 A.D. Some Protestant sects still think that it will come within a few years. After that there will be only heaven and hell—and purgatory for a while, according to the Catholics.
Let us note some of the differences between these two conceptions of the universe. There is first the difference of scale: the Christian universe was small and of brief duration (apart from heaven and hell), while the scientific universe is not known to have a beginning or end in either time or space, and is certainly of unimaginable extent in both. In the Christian universe, everything had a purpose and everything had its place; it was neat and tidy. like a good housewife’s kitchen. Another difference is that the Christian universe centered about the earth, while the scientific universe has no center; in the Christian universe, the earth was fixed, and the celestial spheres revolved about it, while in the scientific universe everything is in motion. The Christian universe was made for man, while the scientific universe, if it is made to serve any end, is made to serve one which we cannot imagine. Indeed the whole conception of purpose, which dominated pseudo-scientific thought during the 2,000 years from Aristotle to the 17th Century, has disappeared from modern scientific explanations. Why the laws of nature are what they are is a question which science has ceased to ask, because there is no reason to suppose that it has an answer. Moral conceptions, such as sin and punishment, dominated the Christian scheme, which in the scientific scheme have no place. The Christian universe was such as uninstructed men might expect the universe to be, while the scientific universe blandly ignores our prejudices and our hopes, our loves and our hates.
Above all these differences, there is the difference of evidence. The evidence for the Christian scheme of things is the Bible; the evidence for the scientific world is observation and induction. Science asks on what ground the Bible account should be accepted. Were the authors of the Pentateuch present at the Creation? Obviously not. Can we believe that God revealed the truth to them? There are great difficulties in this view. The Bible is not the only Sacred Book; other religions have different cosmologies. How is an impartial inquirer to know which to believe? The Bible sometimes contradicts itself; it gives two quite inconsistent accounts of the creation of Adam and Eve, and in one place it says there were two sheep in the ark while in another it says there were seven. Then there are other difficulties. The Jesuit Acosta, who lived in South America, was puzzled by the animals only to be found there, though all must have come from Mount Ararat. This was especially puzzling in the case of the sloth, which is so dilatory in its motions that it could hardly have reached South America in the time since the flood. Sailors might, of course, have brought the various queer beasts from the old world, but the worthy Father thinks this unlikely, especially in the case of the filthy Acacias, of which the smell is unendurable. Then there were troubles about fossils, which seemed to prove the world older than it could be if Genesis were true. Gradually belief in the literal truth of Genesis came to be very generally abandoned, and the way was left clear for acceptance of the scientific account.
What science has to say about very distant times and places is said with hesitation; it is set forth as what is most probable on the existing evidence, but any day new evidence may lead to new conclusions on this point or that. It is unlikely, however, that the general picture will be very much changed. What theology had to say, before science had weakened its authority, was said with a very different accent: what it pronounced was truth eternal, unalterable, unquestionable. Those who questioned it deserved to be burnt here on earth, as Giordano Bruno was burnt, and they would certainly burn hereafter to the end of time. No theologian would say this now, but that is because even infallible dogmas have had to be surreptitiously modified to meet the onslaught of science.
Whoever wishes to become a philosopher will do well to pay attention to the history of science, and particularly to its warfare with theology. With the exception of pure mathematics, every science has had to begin by fighting to establish its right to exist. Astronomy was condemned in the person of Galileo, geology in the person of Buffon. Scientific medicine was, for a long time, made almost impossible by the opposition of the Church to the dissection of dead bodies. Darwin came too late to suffer penalties, but Catholics and the Legislature of Tennessee still regard evolution with abhorrence. Each step has been won with difficulty, and each new step is still opposed, as if nothing were to be learnt from past defeats.
In our day, it is the newest science, psychology, that encounters opposition, particularly when it seems in danger of interfering with the doctrine of “sin.” In any human community, some people act in ways inimical to the interests of the community; if social life is to continue, it is necessary to find ways of preventing such anti-social behavior. The conception of “sin” was the Church’s wav of effecting this object. If the police failed, the sinner could not congratulate himself on his escape, for God would punish him. This method had a certain efficacy in certain kinds of cases. But we now know that much anti-social behavior has deep psychological causes, and will not cease until those causes are removed by psychological curative treatment. Much of what used to be indiscriminately labelled “sin” turns out to be more of the nature of disease, amenable perhaps to medical treatment, but not to punishment. Those who take this attitude are accused by the orthodox of advocating whatever “sins” should, in their opinion, be treated medically rather than penally. This is simply the old opposition to science, taking courage from the fact that psychology, the science in question, is still young and immature. In ethics, equally, the old obscurantism continues. No one is injured when a man marries his d...

Table of contents