The Metaphysics of Action
eBook - ePub

The Metaphysics of Action

Trying, Doing, Causing

David-Hillel Ruben

Share book
  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

The Metaphysics of Action

Trying, Doing, Causing

David-Hillel Ruben

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

In this book, the author provides an account of three central ideas in the philosophy of action: trying to act, acting or doing, and one's action causing further consequences. In all three cases, novel theories of these phenomena are offered: trying to act is not a particular mental or physical act but can be explained using conditionals; that action is not the same as causing something to happen; and in the case of a special but important subset of actions, for example the opening of a window, the action is identical to the event of the window's opening. A result of this last account is that it places actions out in the world, sometimes far removed in time and space from the actor's body. The world is full of action; actions do not just exist in the many little islands of space and time that all of our bodies inhabit. In the final chapter, Ruben describes and discusses a skeptical challenge to the idea that we can ever know whether or not someone else has acted, rather than just passive events having happened to that person.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is The Metaphysics of Action an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access The Metaphysics of Action by David-Hillel Ruben in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Philosophical Metaphysics. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2018
ISBN
9783319903477
© The Author(s) 2018
David-Hillel RubenThe Metaphysics of Actionhttps://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-90347-7_1
Begin Abstract

1. Introduction

David-Hillel Ruben1
(1)
Department of Philosophy, University of London, London, UK
David-Hillel Ruben
End Abstract
I intend to use this introduction as a vehicle for situating the topics discussed in this book within a wider philosophical context, and to describe the main ideas in each chapter. This introduction contains no arguments defending or justifying that context or the presuppositions of my discussion (there will be arguments aplenty about other matters in the following chapters). In theology, a distinction is sometimes drawn between apologetic and confessional theological literature. Apologetic literature seeks to defend a point of view to an audience that is outside the circle of believers; it attempts to convince them of something. Confessional theological literature accepts a point of view as given, but then explains and develops it for those inside the tradition, those who have already ‘bought in’ to the basic assumptions. This Introduction might be thought of as a piece of confessional philosophy, making explicit some of the doxological presuppositions of the book to the already-believers.
Here is that to which I confess: there is something called analytic metaphysics, a philosophical project of establishing both what exists and what it is like. Further, my confession includes the belief that there is a significant role for analytic metaphysics to play in its application to the theory of action (and to the philosophy of social science more generally). I have long held this belief about analytic metaphysics and its applications to other areas of philosophy, a belief evidenced by my first book, Marxism and Materialism (1977, 1979), by The Metaphysics of the Social World (1985) and finally by an earlier book in action theory, Action and Its Explanation (2003). Not all philosophers think that there is such a project. I think that there is such a philosophical project and that it is, in the main, an a priori exercise. I’m hardly alone in the belief that it can be applied in action theory. There are many examples of other philosophers who have worked similarly in a more metaphysical tradition in the philosophy of action.1 Whether I agree with their views or not, I recognise that they are doing, in whole or in part, what I am also trying to do in this book. I admire much of their work.
I can identify at least two stands to the project of analytic metaphysics; the dividing line between them is not sharp. (I’m a big fan of both strands.) The first strand is ‘ontological’: are there objects independent of minds, simples, complex objects, mereological sums, tropes, universals, sense data, abstract objects, or four-dimensional objects? The main tool of this strand is what we might call ‘ratiocination’. Typically, such items are shown to exist or not to exist by a priori argument. It makes no difference that The Man on the Clapham Omnibus has never heard of such things, and so doesn’t talk or think thoughts about them. That bus-rider will have heard of tables, chairs, and the like, but a trope, or the mereological sum of two arbitrary objects, will come as news. By that, it might be meant that they do not accord with pre-analytic ontology. If so, the criticism does not move me much. I suppose that other things being equal, such accord would be desirable. But things are never equal, or anyway hardly ever. I believe that philosophy often comes to truths about what exists that are strange to the ears of the uninitiated.
A second strand (call it ‘metaphysics proper’) attempts to uncover what the entities that we admit into our ontology are like. The aforementioned bus-rider will certainly have heard of action, but he won’t necessarily have a view about what an action is. He will also have heard that people try to do various things, and that agents cause things to happen, but he won’t necessarily have a view about what is involved by what he hears. One reaction that I have encountered to the three main theses of the book, one on trying, one on the nature of action, and one on causing, is that they are ‘implausible’. Again, the criticism does not move me much, unless that charge can be supported by arguments that show that the views are either internally inconsistent or have consequences that are patently false. I can’t help but think of Hamlet to Horatio: ‘There are more things in heaven and earth, Horatio, than are dreamt of in your philosophy’ (Hamlet, 1.5.167–168). That may be true of poor Horatio’s philosophy, but evidently not of Hamlet’s, nor of mine.
I also intend my discussion in the book to be metaphysical in the following sense. I want to know about actions, causing, and trying, not about the concepts of action, causing, and trying, or about action-, causing-, and trying- sentences, although of course access to knowledge about them must commence with language, commence with thinking about those sentences and concepts, knowing what we say, when and why. I want to explain what I am doing in a somewhat minimalist way in this Introduction, since this question raises profound questions about philosophical method, analysis, logical form, and how analysis and logical form relate. That would be the subject of another book, one that I am not capable of writing.
If one looks at earlier examples of metaphysical analysis-say, what a physical object is or what a social whole is-it is true that philosophers, especially those writing in the middle of the last century, often wrote as if the object of interest is language or concepts. Two striking examples of this are the Appendix to Roderick Chisholm’s 1957 Perceiving, in which he undertakes to refute phenomenalism, and a well-known article on the relation between the social and the individual by Maurice Mandelbaum (1955). Chisholm’s discussion is framed in terms of the logical relations between appearance statements on the one hand and our ‘ordinary statements about physical things’ on the other (190). Mandelbaum’s discussion is framed as being about the reducibility of societal concepts to individual concepts ‘without remainder’ (223). Mandelbaum speaks interchangeably about concepts and facts. It may be that such writers were influenced by the doctrine of semantic ascent, and that this is reflected by their choice of method and the terms in which they set their metaphysical discussion, but it certainly should not have changed their objectives. After all, there could be two sets of statements, S1 and S2, such that, although there were no ‘translations’ of any statement from one set into statements solely from the other set, S1 and S2 were still about the same things. And there can surely be two distinct concepts, C1 and C2, with the same extension or even necessarily with the same extension (the concepts of trilaterality and triangularity are such an example). So irreducibility of concepts and untranslatability of discourses do not tell us all that we want to know about the metaphysical nature of the world.
But what was really of interest to these and other philosophers who discussed ontological issues, rightly or wrongly, in terms of statements or sentences or concepts, was the question of whether there are such things as, e.g., mind-independent physical objects or social wholes, in addition to appearances or individual entities, and their choice of terminology, in terms of statements and concepts, was only the vehicle with which they thought best to get at those ontological issues. It was perhaps part of the philosophical method of that era to pose such questions in the formal rather than in the material mode, as an accompaniment to the idea of semantic ascent. That is speculation on my part. But whether my speculation is sound or not, I have posed the questions as far as I could in the material mode.
So, since this book is about the METAPHYSICS of action (and NOT about the SEMANTICS of action sentences or the CONCEPT of action), I intend that what I am doing to be about trying, acting, and causing, not about the concepts of trying, acting, and causing, nor about any discourse about them. My goal is to reach results about trying and causing (the phenomena) and about acting (the real-life occurrences), about what these ‘things’ really are.
It is important to stress this, because the extent to which I do discuss issues about sentences, language, grammar, and so on might strike the reader as somehow at odds with what I have just said. It is part of the tradition in which I work to approach metaphysical and ontological questions often by looking at language, but the goal is not the analysis of the assertions or sentences or concepts, but an understanding of the metaphysics and ontology of the human world to which such discourse commits us. In spite of his talking about ‘definitions’ of knowledge, Gettier (1963) wasn’t interested in knowledge-talk or even the concept of knowledge; he wanted to describe what has to be the case in order for someone to know some proposition p. The objective of the analyses in the book (in Chaps. 4, 5 and 6, for example) are not sentences or statements or discourse or concepts, but what these things are about or true of, even though such discovery typically comes through a careful consideration of the ontic commitments embedded in the sentence. For instance, in Chap. 4, I argue that P tries to F iff (if a certain set of conditions are fulfilled, P acts). (Note that one can say this without switching away from the material to the formal mode.) I have certainly adopted the method of looking at language as a way to uncovering metaphysical truths; two good examples are the attention I have paid to questions about imperfective aspect and to the topic of causative alternation. But method is one thing, but goal is another. I spend a fair amount of space and energy thinking about imperfectivity, but my interests are not narrowly linguistic insofar as I do this. Behind the contrast of perfective and imperfective verb aspect lies a distinction between actions-in-progress and actions-as-completed, and that latter contrast is a metaphysical one.
The metaphysics or ontology of action (including trying and agent causing) is a very large area. There are many issues with which I do not deal, so I make no claim about the book’s completeness and comprehensiveness. For example, I have only a little to say about intentions, and nothing to say about beliefs, desires, and reasons, topics that are mainstays in theories of action. Instead I have selected three ideas on which to focus: trying, doing, and causing, and the m...

Table of contents