On the Ethical Imperatives of the Interregnum
eBook - ePub

On the Ethical Imperatives of the Interregnum

Essays in Loving Strife from Soren Kierkegaard to Cornel West

William V. Spanos

Share book
  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

On the Ethical Imperatives of the Interregnum

Essays in Loving Strife from Soren Kierkegaard to Cornel West

William V. Spanos

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This book is an autobiographical meditation on the way in which the world's population has been transformed into a society of refugees and émigrés seeking –indeed, demanding– an alternative way of political belonging. Focusing on the interregnum we have precariously occupied since the end of World War II—and especially after 9/11— it constitutes a series of genealogical chapters that trace the author's journey from his experience as a prisoner of war in Nazi Germany to the horrific fire-bombing of Dresden in February 1945. In doing so, it explores his search for an intellectual vocation adequate to the dislocating epiphany he experienced in bearing witness to these traumatising events. Having subsequently lost faith in the logic of belonging perpetuated by the nation-state, Spanos charts how he began to look in the rubble of that zero zone for an alternative way of belonging: one in which the old binary —whose imperative was based on the violence of the Friend/enemy opposition— wasreplaced by a paradoxical loving strife that enriched rather than negated the potential of each side. The chapters in this book trace this errant vocational itinerary, from the author's early undergraduate engagement with Kierkegaard and Heidegger to Cornel West, moving from that disclosive occasion in the zero zone to this present moment.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is On the Ethical Imperatives of the Interregnum an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access On the Ethical Imperatives of the Interregnum by William V. Spanos in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Literature & Literary Criticism for Comparative Literature. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Š The Author(s) 2016
William V. SpanosOn the Ethical Imperatives of the InterregnumPivotal Studies in the Global American Literary Imagination10.1007/978-3-319-47871-5_1
Begin Abstract

1. Retrieving Kierkegaard for the Post-9/11 Occasion

A Late Meditation on the Secular
William V. Spanos1
(1)
English Department, Binghamton University, Binghamton, New York, USA
Abstract
In the case of Søren Kierkegaard, what compelled my profound interest was his revolutionary rejection of the panoptic perspective of the Christian Church that rendered its “faithful” subjects servants of a Higher Cause in favor of a vocation that assigned the individual to his/her radically finite self. Equally important, it was the recognition that such an existential perspective was dependent on the need for a constant awareness of that easier transcendental domain that one had to give up to accept such an agonizing assignment to oneself.
Keywords
RecollectionRepetitionDread (angest)Interest (interesse)Mastered ironyChristian existentialismRevocation
End Abstract
Reflection is the possibility of relationship. This can be stated thus: Reflection is disinterested. Consciousness is relationship, and it brings with it interest or concern; a quality which is perfectly expressed with pregnant double meaning by the word “interest” (Latin interesse, meaning (i) “to be between,” (ii) “to be a matter of concern”).
Søren Kierkegaard, Johannes Climacus or De Omnibus Dubitandum Est
As anyone familiar with my scholarship and criticism is aware, the idea of the secular has been, increasingly, its supreme theme from virtually the beginning of my intellectual life. The questions my work have insistently posed and struggled to articulate have invariably been as follows: (1) What does being a secular intellectual entail for his/her interpretation of being? (2) What does being secular imply about his/her subjectivity? And, not least, (3) what does it demand about his/her interpretation of and cultural, social, economic, and political comportment toward the world? In this, I have been in solidarity with the “worldly” initiative inaugurated by Edward W. Said’s uncompromising commitment to the secular world and to the “worldly criticism” that commitment entails. As a consequence, no doubt, of “time’s winged chariot” and the imperatives of this lateness to resist all transcendental props, however, I have come, at this late point of my intellectual life, to realize—with Said, if not his “worldly” followers—that commitment to the “secular” or “worldly” as such is inadequate to our liminal occasion (what I have been calling the “interregnum”) insofar as the real meaning of the secular depends on the transcendental (the paradisiacal) it opposes; that, in other words, in this world, eternity and time belong together in unending strife. The secular as such, devoid of its antithesis, tends, in its appeal to the laws of nature, to reproduce the world in the teleological image of the orderly Creation: the world in this secular dispensation, as Max Weber made decisively clear, becomes the object of mastery, and the calling of human beings—their vocation—the rationalization of the earth according to the imperial dictates of the “capitalist spirit.” The “worldliness” of these late worldly intellectuals—their human condition, which calls for unending engagement with the transience of time—becomes an unworldly worldliness. My late realization of the inadequacy of the term “secular” to characterize the liminality of the interregnum has precipitated a retrieval (Wiederholung, in Heidegger’s term) of a major early influence in my intellectual life that, in the process of my intellectual career, I had virtually forgotten, but which has haunted my thinking about the secular from the beginning. I am referring to the great Christian existentialist Søren Kierkegaard, whose works I began reading as an undergraduate at Wesleyan University in 1948, soon after returning to “the world” from dislocating captivity in Germany during World War II.

1

Opened by my degrading experience as a prisoner of war and, not least, by bearing witness to the horrendous Allied fire-bombing of Dresden, which killed over a hundred thousand civilians in one night and day raid, to this first self-de-struction of modern Western civilization, I was deeply receptive to its severe criticism by the humanist existentialists such as Jean-Paul Sartre, Simon De Beauvoir, Albert Camus, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and others, who attributed its ultimate justification of violence to the metaphysical principle that “essence precedes [is ontologically prior to] existence.” And in the throes of that trauma, I read these radically revisiononist thinkers, particularly Sartre’s novels, avidly. And, in the process, I, as a student, disrupted many of the highly popular classes in the humanities I took at Wesleyan, which at that time were being taught by and large under the aegis of the traditional humanism, on the one hand, and the (antihumanist) New Criticism, on the other. But it was not until my sophomore year that I was enabled to feel/think the full impact of this intellectual retrieval of existence from the dominance of essence: temporality from its dependence on universality, be-ing on Being. That was, paradoxically, when, out of the clear blue, a fellow maverick student friend from Missouri, David Mize, attuned to my fraught intellectual confusions, offered me his copy of The Journals of Søren Kierkegaard, a selection edited by Alexander Dru published by Oxford University Press under the auspices of the Christian novelist/editor, Charles Williams, in 1939, the first translation of the Danish thinker’s works into English.
As I recall, I was profoundly struck by the first words of these journal entries: something like, “We think backwards, but live forward,” an existential assertion pointing in a shockingly irreversible way to the Western separation of mind and body, essence and existence—and the urgent need to reunify this debilitating separation by way of understanding human life as a form of being that is simultaneously outside (a limited consciousness) and inside nature—an ex-sistent in-sistent being unlike stones and animals. In another even more startling formulation of this same memorable insight, I encountered the following statement (quoted as the epigraph for this chapter) in Kierkegaard’s pseudonymous novel Johannes Climacus, or De Omnibus Dubitanduim Est shortly after my introduction to The Journals. It was a statement categorically rejecting disinterested inquiry and its (objective) Truth as a lie:
This can also be stated thus: Reflection is disinterested. Consciousness [“human life”] is relationship, and it brings with it interest or concern; a duality which is perfectly expressed with pregnant double meaning by the word “interest” (Latin interesse, meaning (i) “to be between,” (ii) “to be a matter of concern.”) (Søren Kierkegaard, Johannes Climacus, [Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press,] pp. 151–152)
As I noted a long time ago, “interest” is the difference that being-in-the midst-of-time makes and the differences it always already disseminates. It was only when I encountered this Kierkegaardian Christian existentialist characterization of the human condition that I realized the full scope and depth—the ontological and political meaning—of Heidegger’s central but undeveloped assertion that care (Sorge) is the foundational element of Dasein, human being as being-in-the-world. It did not simply mean a burdened sense of responsibility for the rest of the being of being, one devoid of transcendental guidance. It also meant the dread incumbent on this fundamental condition—the absence of a God on which to rely for difficult decisions about being in the world. It meant freedom in the radical sense of word, as in Sartre’s memorable Kierkegaardian phrase “Man is condemned to be free.” This paradoxical meaning of Kierkegaard’s “interest” took on seismic proportions when, in the process of reading the Journals, I came across the entry recalling a day in his early life in the company of his aging father. They are walking in the overcast mountainous moors of Denmark toward some unknown destination, the father, silent, dour, self-absorbed, leading the way, and the boy struggling to keep up with him. Suddenly, the father halts, looks up, and, in an astonishing gesture of defiance, raises his clenched fist and shakes it against the skies. Kierkegaard, as I recall, does not say anything more about this apocalyptic moment, but clearly it was life-transforming for the young boy. On this occasion, his familiar, everyday world is suddenly shattered, and he is prematurely unhomed, as it were—thrown into the realm of the in-between. And, to me, his experience was something analogous to the night and day in Dresden when, as a young prisoner of war, I experienced an event that shattered whatever previous certainties about life I had derived from above, as it were. In that brief but terrible moment of unimaginable violence I was plunged, like it or not, into what I then identified as the zero zone—and later, because of its historically resonant etymology, as my “occasion”: from the Latin cadere, “to die,” “to perish,” from which occidere: “to go down, to set,” as in the “setting of the sun,” derives, to become the origin of the word “Occident” (German Abendland, “evening land”) that the West coined to distinguish it from the Orient (from oriens, participle of oriri; “rising,” “rising sun,” “east”). By this term I meant pretty much what Kierkegaard, no doubt recalling that time with his father in the Danish moors, by “interesse,” the realm of the in-between, where all the reference points fell away and he, having previously taken his vocation from the dictates of a Higher Cause, was henceforth “assigned to himself.” To put this apocalyptic beginning alternatively, that intense moment in the moors with his father initiated Søren to the dread (Danish, angest) that, as he put it in The Concept of Dread, “reveals the nothing” that is ontologically prior to Being.
It was, above all, this Jobian occasion—this sudden disclosure of the belongingness in strife of heaven and earth—in the process of my encounter with Kierkegaard as an undergraduate at Wesleyan and as a graduate student at Columbia, that suddenly and irrevocably infused my memory of the Allied firebombing of Dresden with the affective—and political—resonance that I was to bring to my reading of Heidegger’s more abstract ontological appropriation of Kierkegaard’s concept of dread. (It was no accident that throughout the years between 1958, when I began writing my Ph. D. dissertation, The Christian Tradition Modern British Verse Drama: The Poetics of Sacramental Time, to 1993, when I published Heidegger and Criticism: Retrieving the Cultural Politics of Destruction, I was always uneasy about having to use the far less affective English translation of the German word Angst—“anxiety” rather than “dread,” which the English translators of Kierkegaard invariably use to render his Danish angest).
But the immediacy with Kierkegaard to which David Mize introduced me at Wesleyan did not terminate at that point. After a year of graduate study at Columbia, I took a teaching position at Mount Hermon, a college preparatory school in Northfield, Massachusetts, founded by prominent Protestant evangelists in the nineteenth century, with close ties to Union Theological Seminary, where under the influence of the Christian existentialist movement, particularly the German expatriate from Nazi Germany Paul Tillich and the American theologian Reinhold Niebuhr, Kierkegaard’s thought had become central to a curriculum that was oriented by the radical anti-authoritative political initiatives of that time, not least the civil rights movements. It was not long after arriving at Mount Hermon that I met three recent graduates of Union, David Jewell, John Angevin, and the school’s chaplain James Whyte, all of whom in some degree or another were deeply influenced by Kierkegaard’s existentialist thought, not least, that engagement in the world that was the difficult imperative of being assigned to oneself.
As I have recalled elsewhere, I, like Edward Said, who was a student at Mount Hermon during my two-year stay there, found the school’s institutionalization of the Protestant work ethic difficult to tolerate. But unlike Said, my two years were redeemed by friendship with the extraordinary Union seminarians. And that was precisely because they were extending Kierkegaardian Christian existentialism into the sites of the ethical and the political, an extension that in the next decade was to render their unique kind of passive active Christian existentialism one of the primary agents of resisting America’s paranoid intervention in Vietnam in the name of its exceptionalist—God’s or History’s ordained—“errand.”
This Kierkegaardian phase of my early intellectual life—this intense sense of having been assigned irrevocably to myself to confront the either/or of the in-between in the wake of the firebombing of Dresden—continued beyond my two years at Mount Hermon, when I was a graduate student at the University of Wisconsin. There, under the influence of Kierkegaard, I became profoundly interested in T.S. Eliot’s poetry, particularly its patent indebtedness to the so-called “Metaphysical Poets,” John Donne and Andrew Marvell, who, in their agonized obsession with the paradoxical tension between the transcendental and the finite—I think of Donne’s meditation on lying in a coffin—struck me as being remarkably proleptic of Kierkegaard’s Christian existentialism. My initial proposal to my academic advisor, Paul Wiley, was to write a dissertation on Eliot’s poetry from this Kierkegaardian perspective. But Professor Wiley, a scholar of modern Irish literature with little knowledge of the emergent existentialist initiative and resistant to another dissertation on T.S. Eliot and the Metaphysical poets, strongly advised me against pursuing that overdone project. So, in the end, following my abiding interest in Kierkegaard, I decided, as the next best option, to write on the modern British Christian verse drama, focusing, against the prevailing New Critical/Modernist approach, primarily on the Kierkegaardian existential element (inflected by Erich Auerbach’s parallel emphasis on the earthly perspective of early Christianity: the figural or typological (as opposed to allegorical) interpretation of history) of these remarkably earth-oriented, if not political, Christian verse plays. The result was a book, mainly on the plays of T.S. Eliot, that, in taking its interpretive directives from Kierkegaard’s radical reorientation of the Christian perspective from the transcendental to earthly temporality, reversed the New Critical perspective that represented Eliot’s poetry and verse drama as unworldly formal constructs. The dissertation, to my surprise, was eventually published as The Christian Tradition in Modern British Verse Drama: The Poetics of Sacramental Time and was awarded a prize as the best book on Christian literature of that year for its radical worlding of the Christian world.
In the meantime, and by way of both Christian and humanist existentialism, I had embarked on my life-long reading of Heidegger. What was distinctive—and paradoxical—about that initiative from the prevailing interpretations of Heidegger is that it was my Kierkegaardian existentialist perspective that, from the beginning, enabled me to radicalize Heidegger’s overdetermination of the ontological site on the continuum of being at the expense of the more political sites—to perceive the indissolubly related connection between his destruction of the Western ontotheological tradition—his disclosure of the will to power intrinsic to the metaphysical thinking privileged by the West—and the possible de-struction (Destruktion) of the hierarchical binarist logic of belonging of the modern Western nation-state system and its imperial imperatives.

2

For a long time after this turn to Heidegger’s de-struction of the Western philosophical tradition—from the Romans’ reduction of the Greek a-lethéia (truth as unconcealment) to adequaetio intellecttus et rei (the adequation on mind and thing, i.e. truth as correctness) to the triumph of empiricism in modernity—and pursuing its worldly political implications, I felt that I had achieved a comportment toward being that satisfied the imperatives of being-in-the-world. It was during the early stages of this Heideggerian period that I discovered what seemed to me the parallel work of Michel Foucault and of Edward W. Said, particularly the latter’s insistent commitment to the secular. Along the way, however, I began to feel uneasy about the way the secular was being represented by all too many of those “worldly” critics whom Said influenced. More specifically, I was troubled by the bland abstractness of their “worldly” criticism. It seemed to me that this word (and, not incidentally, its correlate, “humanism”), which Said had deliberately chosen because of it subjective and historical resonance—its affiliation with its transcendental antithesis—had become routinized. It was, that is, lacking in the very existential force that led Said to adopt the term against the systematization intrinsic to “religious” criticism in the first place. Indeed, one got the impression from its usage by these worldly critics that the word had been divested of its original intensive belongingness with the transcendental, and in the process, as Said warned against in Orientalism, was rendered as “naturalized supernaturalism.” In order to forestall this possible reading of the secular, in fact, Aamir Mufti, one of Said’s most able and articulate students, points out the recuperative theological implications of the normal reduction:
Secular criticism in Said’...

Table of contents