Fashion | Sense
eBook - ePub

Fashion | Sense

On Philosophy and Fashion

Gwenda-lin Grewal

Share book
  1. 248 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Fashion | Sense

On Philosophy and Fashion

Gwenda-lin Grewal

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

"Deeply erudite but also playful and full of wit." Salman Rushdie Fashion | Sense is designed to explode "fashion, " and with it, the stigma in philosophy against fashion's superficiality. Fashion appears to be altogether differently occupied, disingenuous and insubstantial, even sophistic in its pretense to peddle surfaces as if they were something deep. But is fashion's apparent beguilement more philosophical than it seems? And is philosophy's longing for exposed depth concealing fashion in its anti-fashion stance? Using primarily ancient Greek texts, peppered with allusions to their echoes across the history of philosophy and contemporary fashion and pop culture, Gwenda-lin Grewal not only examines the rift between fashion and philosophy, but also challenges the claim that fashion is modern. Indeed, fashion's quarrel with philosophy may be at least as ancient as that infamous quarrel between philosophy and poetry alluded to in Plato's Republic. And the quest for fashion's origins, as if a quest for a neutrally-outfitted self, stripped of the self-awareness that comes with thinking, prompts questions about human agency and our immersion in time. The touch of reality's fabric bristles in our relationship to our looks, not simply through the structure of clothes but in the plot of our wearing them. Meanwhile, the fashion of our words sharpens our meaning like a cutting silhouette. Grewal's own writing is playfully and daringly self-conscious, aware of its style and the entrapment it arouses from the very first line. The reactions provoked by fashion's flair, not only among the philosophical set but also among those who would never deck themselves out in the title, "philosopher, " show it forth as perhaps philosophy's most important and underestimated doppelgÀnger.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Fashion | Sense an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Fashion | Sense by Gwenda-lin Grewal in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Aesthetics in Philosophy. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2022
ISBN
9781350201484
1
Fashion Sense
φ᜻σÎčς Îșρ᜻πτΔσΞαÎč φÎčλΔῖ1
—Heraclitus, Fragment B123 DK
It is time to come out of the closet. This is not an academic book in the traditional sense. It is written by an academic who is interested in the question: is there an academic “look,” particularly for so-called philosophers? Is there a look that says, “I’m good at looking?” And is it the only look with which one can address the truth? The question is partly motivated by another question: Why do most philosophers hate clothes—or rather, hate fashion? The majority rule seems to be to treat the outer surface with either ritual formality or complete derision, as if the less you comb your hair the closer you are to truth. For a philosopher in search of reality, any sort of keeping up appearances looks laced with madness. Those who appear interested in making fashion statements run the risk of being accused of wasting time on shallow things, and so, being slipshod thinkers. Smart people know you can’t judge a book by its cover. Things are not always what they seem. Caring about fashion for its own sake—or appearance for appearance’s sake—is surely the greatest of all sophistry. It is superficial, shallow, vain. But isn’t it strange to live a life of careful observation—you could say, a life that treats the world with kid gloves—and yet, to have no care for what you wear? Maybe it is simply that, in their longing not to be particular about being, philosophers hate putting themselves together. The very word “philosopher” is almost an insult—as if you could identify the person who is busy identifying everything else. Philosophers are anonymous, their appearances out of fashion.2
But philosophers are not alone in fearing being seen with too many flounces and frills. Many people swear by fashion’s insignificance: it is too contrived, too arbitrary, too much a sign of vanity. Fashion is excess, for changeability alone does not condemn it, but a surplus of changeability beyond perceived necessity. Fashion flits about after shiny things, like a magpie or jackdaw adorning a nest. At the same time, it teeters perilously close to extremes, unsure if one more pleat won’t push it over the edge from tasteful to trendy. But this reveals another feature of fashion. Installed within its very compass is the “sense” that to appear too preoccupied with itself would be unfashionable. Fashion is about judgment. Its gavel comes down with bristly adjectives: looking “good,” looking “right,” even looking “just right.”
So strong is the impulse of sartorial morality that it is difficult in praising clothes not to use such adjectives as “right,” “good,” “correct,” “unimpeachable,” or “faultless,” which belong properly to the discussion of conduct, while in discussing moral shortcomings we tend very naturally to fall into the language of dress and speak of a person’s behaviour as being shabby, shoddy, threadbare, down at heel, botched, or slipshod.
(Bell 1948: 14)
Fashion operates according to weather and essence. It speaks of seasons, occasions, essentials, and basics, as if the cogent wearer would be a master of contingency or a conqueror of fortune.3 Still, if the variety or number of clothes in excess is all we mean when we utter the word “fashion” in its profane sense, why do we persist in keeping our options open when we dress ourselves? Are philosophers, in their scorn for the endless permutations that fashion represents, resistant to freedom? Or is it the specific sort of freedom that fashion’s excessive options signify, over and against the tasteful refinement of the literary elite? Is fashion too vulgar, too demotic for the thoughtful? But again, fashion itself is compelled not to transgress certain unwritten limits. Firstly, everything cannot be worn at once. In the distinction between fast fashion and haute couture or runway and ready-to-wear lies the equivalent of those distinctions in philosophy between philosophy and political philosophy or metaphysics and physics.
Yet, what if, regardless of social or economic status, regardless of political or professional affiliation, regardless of cultural background, religion, or identity—what if something powerful lurks in the experience of taking off and putting on clothes? I do not yet mean to enter or exit Eden. I mean by “clothes” something that may well prove evanescent—something more or less like an awareness of our presence in some skin—signified, too, by body paint, piercings, tattoos, haircuts, or even simple gestures. The flourish of a pen fashions as does the tip of a finger pointing. When these flourishes—these clothes—touch us with even the slightest bit of excess, we are made aware of our “bodies” as a surface, and by extension, of the appearance of our “selves.” The self, understood as an appearance, like an ill-fitting word or split seam, comes along with an awareness of being in space and time. And so, I hesitate to say, fashion and philosophy enter the scene at the same moment. Clothes, insofar as they make us aware of our appearances, are requisite for the experience of self-examination. They are an alienated contact with the self, gained through the strange shell of fabricated “not-us” that gives birth to the Cartesian doubt that “we” are other than it. But the question of this book, which will remain in between the lines for some time, is how this experience of ourselves as contingently clothed, and so necessarily present, begins.
Touch of Clothes and Sense of Self
In Aristotle’s De Anima, flesh emerges as the medium through which the sense of touch produces its effect.4 Touch is in a way the most confused of the senses, and so, emblematic of the source of “feeling” which is present in them all. Aristotle immediately encounters the difficulty of wresting the medium of touch from the sense of touch. When we touch an object, we not only seem to touch it, but we also feel the touch of ourselves touching.5 The object presses back on us at the same time as the feeling of the otherness of our own touch touching us, as if from the outside. We “grasp” the thought of our own perception through the act of touching; “grasp” is as ambiguous in English as it is in Greek.6 In a similar account in De Rerum Natura, Lucretius describes a link between touch and sight. For touch, he uses the Latin word tangere, which has the double sense of physical and psychical contact: you can touch something literally or be “touched” by it or “touch” on it figuratively. For Lucretius, the seeming immediacy of touch already implies a longing to “see” inside an object, and so a desire to know. He uses as an example reaching out to touch something even in the dark, where we imagine we are peering into its interior.7 So, too, we touch the pages of a book to go beyond just feeling their outer edges. In touching the pages, we feel both the pages themselves and our own curiosity about their insides. The analogue to clothes might be that when they are on us and when they touch us, we experience the “touch” of ourselves. Perhaps this is as simple as putting on a bathrobe or brushing your teeth—dressing and addressing yourself in even a minimal way so as to make yourself feel as if you are “in” the world. Does this ritual illustrate the whimsy or the tyranny of clothes as convention? Or in confronting the image of the self, do we confront a reflection on its absence from the image, and so, the thought of its presence?
Still, we put our faces on, then forget we did. We want to be and to look “comfortable.” In American fashion, “comfort” indicates not only feeling that clothes do not constrain, bind, or provoke us, but also not seeing clothes as manifestly constraining, binding, or provoking. And if to feel is in some way to see, it will be difficult to separate how we experience ourselves in clothes and how we experience others experiencing ourselves in clothes. Beauty is associated with vanity and pain, even in the form of an imagined empathy for a person whose clothes look uncomfortable. Comfort must be executed properly, lest it make others around you squirm. American comfort looks elegant only to a point, stopping short of attractiveness: athleisure and sweatpants perhaps, or soft, flowing garments.8 Comfort is a non-triggering safe space in which to enter freely into an experience of other clothed selves—not appearing to have been chained by those antiquated legislators of girdles and corsets (or more recently, Spanx), which sell the look of control. We comfortable people let go of the need for control. Yet the constraints on comfort’s visage tell onlookers that even this novel freedom is governed by Draconian laws, defined as what appears appropriate or comfortable to others.
This uniform is designed to telegraph to others what to see so that they will not be made uncomfortable and probably hostile by being forced to look on another human being. The uniform must suggest a certain setting and it must dictate a certain air and it must also convey, however subtly, a dormant aggressiveness, like the power of a sleeping lion. It is necessary to make anyone on the streets think twice before attempting to vent his despair on you.
(Baldwin 1964/2008: 57)
The uniform of which James Baldwin speaks is being able to pass among others by being perceived to be one of them, and so subtly suggesting to the same others, don’t look. “Dormant aggressiveness” seems to lurk in clothing by default, while behind it glimmers the possibility of getting personal, as if clothes were at once the image of a window to the soul, like the eyes, and also a set of drapes to prevent unwanted peeping.
The appearance of comfort, of course, varies, and a new dialect of comfort must be learned in different settings in order to continually go unnoticed. Working from both the outside in and the inside out, the ultimate goal is a state in which clothes no longer seem to exert their impression on you. Because the more effortlessly you can forget the “feeling” of clothes, the more you can cast away the outer image of yourself grating on you. Thanks to clothes, you can then be free not to care about clothes. We enter the comfort zone, wrapped in a security blanket of ineffectual clothing. The lure of this zone seems to be the meshing of clothes with persons. Clothing functions almost as if a second skin, and in the absence of other information, it leads to assumptions about who people are on the basis of how they look.
This is one way in which we find clothes uncomfortable: they are connected to biases and stereotypes. Such fraudulent signals are not felt or sensed to belong on the person. We say: we are so much more than our looks. We are not solely aesthetic objects. And yet, the desire for comfortable clothes suggests that the experience of the binding of the body in clothes is a metaphor for how we experience the feeling of our “selves” more generally. We forget the question of ourselves in comfortable clothes, as we do in comfortable patterns of thought. Is it the mere presence of clothes that discomforts us? To imagine a time when there was no thought of fashion would be like a time in which time ceases to exert a visible effect. Perhaps a desire to distance yourself from fashion—to be comfortable—is also a longing to stop the clock?
But what if assumptions—really, prejudices—have to be worn in order to be overturned? The democratic ideal within the Western fashion stereotype hopes for a liberation from such authoritarian constraints. The plethora of options is a new nudity, in which we are apparently now able to express ourselves without needing to do so as an act of defense. Comfort seems to be the illusion of—the desire for—nature’s clothes. This may be the dream implicit in all clothing. But its fruition would be a world of phantoms. On one level, having freedom in fashion seems to mean having a diversity of options from a diversity of designers, where there is no conventional backdrop against which “standard” persons are defined. Yet the image for this is a line-up of designs and individuals that once depicted can only become stereotypes—let’s call them “models.”9 How does one liberate oneself not just from the assumptions of clothes but from their inability to sufficiently express our individuality? Is the only route to display the self to build into clothes our very imperfection: a frayed hem, a sweep of blush, “distressed” fabric?
In Se questo ù un uomo (If This Is a Man), Primo Levi describes his experience in Auschwitz during the Second World War. His clothes are stripped, his body shaved, and all of his possessions are taken away. The meaning is clear: Levi’s freedom and identity have been removed. His clothes are then replaced with dehumanizing clothes: a striped uniform (for the Jewish people, sewn with a yellow Star of David) and a pair of wooden shoes. “Death begins with the shoes,” writes Levi, for they become instruments of torture in the camp (1947/2008: 24). They are designed not to fit the foot, so as to more quickly cause injury, and with it, infection, which is left untreated and leads to death. The shoes predict and deliver Levi’s fate. The Nazis used this dress code to divide prisoners into those who would live and those who would die.
Imagine now a man who is deprived of everyone he loves, and at the same time of his house, his habits, his clothes, in short, of everything he possesses: he will be a hollow man, reduced to suffering and needs, forgetful of dignity and restraint, for he who loses all often easily loses himself. He will be a man whose life or death can be lightly decided with no sense of human affinity, in the most fortunate of cases, on the basis of a pure judgment of utility. It is in this way that one can understand the double sense of the term “extermination camp,” and it is now clear what we seek to express with the phrase: “to lie on the bottom.”
(15–6)
Levi is stripped and redefined. This is the first meaning of “extermination,” as the privation of life’s signifiers. In having his clothes taken away and replaced is the thought of his life being taken away and his lot recast. Clothes seem capable of both expressing the freedom to define who you are and also compromising agency, when they cease to give you the “room” to be who you are, and so, constrain you by explicit or implicit compulsion. The complexity of comfortable fashion is already in the term itself, for fashion is not just about an abundance of surface but the fitting surface. In this, the life of the individual is at stake.
If we throw our clothes aside and say, this is not me, we again notice our discomfort in and with clothes. This seems to be the thing we must take for granted the more comfortable we are; that is, we cease to recall the presence of ourselves in distinction from the way we are outfitted. And if comfort is not merely some belated reaction to rib-crushing corsets, it may be the mere presence of clothes that seems to rub us the wrong way. After a long day, the body rebels against material limits. Now increasingly uncomfortable, we gravitate toward a less literal comfort: a trusty shirt that feels or looks good to us, or a favorite pair of slippers, which, though worn, seem familiar, as if an afterlife of a more comfortable self. Our skin too, unwillingly worn, seems an outfit in which we can feel more or less at ease, so that even in the thinnest cloth, if we begin to focus on the touch of the fabric on the body, we begin to feel estranged.
What shroud is this within which I am ensconced? By comparison to me, clothes seem profoundly surface level, and yet, through them it is possible to experience the depth of the self, whether in its rejection or liberation. Is the body, too, a shroud? Nudity seems insufficient after experiencing the touch of clothes. You would have to be flayed to experience the skin from all sides—the “supernudity”10 that reveals the body as somehow not quite what we thought body was, because touch blurs the lines between self and other. We launder the surface of our skin as if it were fabric, as if personal hygiene were an outfit needed for admission into the world. On entering into a jacket by Sonia Rykiel, HĂ©lĂšne Cixous remarks, “I go inside, eyes closed. With my hands, with my eyes in my hands, with my eyes groping like hands, I see—touch the body hidden in the body” (1994: 96).
Do we only know of body’s estrangement because of our estrangement in clothes? What if what we feel when we experience the touch of ourselves by way of clothes is really something like our own act of becoming aware of ourselves? Through clothes we experience blind self-reflection, for the touch of clothes allows us to experience their fabrication, and this is connected to our feeling of a “reality” beyond them.11 We long to be ourselves in clothes (as if to approximate a perfectly naked selfhood, or at least not to have to worry so much about the surface self), and yet we sense ourselves in clothes precisely because our clothes are not us.
The reader may object here. Couldn’t one sense the “self” in a similar fashion, and maybe more powerfully, through another human’s touch, as one sees recognition in another’s eyes?12 But clothes touch us the whole day. If we live naked, our skin folds on itself as if a garment; if we sleep naked, the fabric of sheets touches us at night. Gravity makes it impossible for us not to be touching the surface of a ground. And clothes embellish that experience—they enrobe us, and cause us to feel our existing in a world all the more potently. It is not that we must be aware of our literal clothes to be aware of ourselves; it is more that the “inevitability” of clothes alre...

Table of contents