Philosophical Foundations of Probability Theory
eBook - ePub

Philosophical Foundations of Probability Theory

Roy Weatherford

Share book
  1. 292 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Philosophical Foundations of Probability Theory

Roy Weatherford

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

First published in 1982, Philosophical Foundations of Probability Theory starts with the uses we make of the concept in everyday life and then examines the rival theories that seek to account for these applications. It offers a critical exposition of the major philosophical theories of probability, with special attention given to the metaphysical and epistemological assumptions and implications of each. The Classical Theory suggests probability is simply the ratio of favorable cases to all equi-possible cases: it is this theory that is relied on by gamblers and by most non-specialists. The A Priori Theory, on the other hand, describes probability as a logical relation between statements based on evidence. The Relative Frequency theories locate it not in logic but among empirical rates of occurrence in the real world, while the Subjectivist Theory identifies probability with the degree of a person's belief in a proposition. Each of these types of theory is examined in turn, and the treatment is unified by the use of running examples and parallel analyses of each theory. The final chapter includes a summary and the author's conclusions. This book is an essential read for scholars and researchers of Philosophy.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Philosophical Foundations of Probability Theory an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Philosophical Foundations of Probability Theory by Roy Weatherford in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophie & Dissertations philosophiques. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2022
ISBN
9781000626094

IIIA PRIORI THEORIES OF PROBABILITY


DOI: 10.4324/9781003306993-3
In this chapter we will discuss a priori (AP) theories in general, with exemplary excursions into particular theories. We will be concerned with (1) basic ideas of AP theories, (2) chief criticisms of such theories, and, finally, to end on a positive note, (3) chief virtues of AP theories. We will deal primarily with the theories of Keynes and Carnap, but, in the main, our remarks are applicable to most other AP or ‘logical’ theories (Jeffreys, Koopman, Kemeny, Hintikka, etc.) as well.

1 BASIC IDEAS OF A PRIORI THEORIES

It seems to me that the basic ideas which all AP theories of probability share are chiefly three:
  1. Probabilities are known (or determined) a priori, not by (purely) empirical means.
  2. Probability is a logical relation between sentences (propositions, events, properties, predicates).
  3. A probability is always relative to given evidence only.
The first point is of course the most important characteristic of a priori theories and the one which gives them their name. It is what distinguishes them most strongly from the relative frequency or ‘empirical’ school.1 It is also what occasions the single greatest objection to them: How can a priori principles do probability theory’s practical work of predicting the future in the real world? Again, it is the source of their greatest single advantage – they can establish probabilities without the necessity of waiting for a very (infinitely?) long sequence of repetitive empirical events.
The second of our basic ideas, like the first, is so central to AP theories that it has generated a name for them: ‘Logical Theories of Probability.’ As interest has grown in the inductive logics of Carnap, Kemeny, Hintikka, et al, this term has been more and more commonly used for such theories. I agree that it is a suitable, descriptive name for this sub-class of a priori theories. I object, however, to its extension to theories of the Keynesian variety, because there the initial probabilities are not obtained from quantitative logistic systems but from a priori intuition aided by the Principle of Indifference.2 My objection is not fervid, however, and if the philosophical tide continues to flow towards empiricism in general but away from the dogmas of logical positivism, I foresee a time when ‘a priori’ will become a general pejorative and I too shall abandon it. Of course the important point here is that these theories do define probability as a logical relation – not whether that fact is sufficient to warrant a label.
This concern with logic was motivated in Carnap’s case, apparently, by a conscious desire for an inductive logic (more than by a need to account for the probability calculus, for example). He had earlier accepted RF theories as adequate for scientific probability –not until he engaged in logical research did he shift his allegiance to AP theories (or, rather, divide it between the two). Keynes, on the other hand, seems to have set out looking for the nature of probability and then ‘discovered’ that it is a matter of logic.
The two also disagreed on the relation between deductive logic and probability. Carnap took the (normal) position that probability theory results from adding probability rules (c-functions) to the ordinary deductive logic, thereby increasing its power and range. Keynes, however, thought probability theory was the basic theory of inference – deductive logic is merely that degenerate case where all probabilities are 1 or 0.
Our third basic idea is that AP theories recognize probabilities relative to given evidence only. Many RF theorists consider this to be a grave defect in AP theories, rendering a probability subordinate to the state of our knowledge and therefore odiously ‘subjective’. Their theories, they maintain, deal with the real probability, which is objectively determined and not relative to anything. There is a sense in which this claim for RF theories is true and a sense in which it is false – we shall discuss this problem in the chapter on Relative Frequency theories below. Our present concern is with the AP theories, and in this context evidence-dependence is seen as a virtue rather than a defect. It is a necessary consequence of the fact that probability is defined as a relation between a proposition and some evidence for that proposition.

2 CHIEF PROPONENTS

There are many people who have proposed or are still proposing theories of this general type. I have chosen to concentrate on Keynes and Carnap because they are the intellectual giants of the group and their theories are the most seminal, philosophical, wide-ranging, and fully developed.
John Maynard Keynes (1883-1946), British economist and man of letters, was ‘one of the creators of the modern world.’3 His theoretical contributions to political economy are familiar to everyone as an important part of the rationale for the ever-increasing government intervention in non-communist economies. His practical contributions to the British Treasury and to international monetary conferences such as Bretton Woods are well known to at least economists and historians. What is less well known is that philosophy was Keynes’s earliest love. He studied it under G. E. Moore and Bertrand Russell as an undergraduate at Cambridge while earning his degree in mathematics. During his subsequent employment with the India Company, Keynes combined these fields in a thorough review of probability and induction. This resulted in a dissertation which earned Keynes a fellowship in King’s College and allowed him to return to Cambridge as a philosopher. He was persuaded to teach in the Economics faculty instead, and subsequently made that field his chief intellectual interest, so his brief career as a philosopher culminated in the publication of an expanded version of his dissertation as A Treatise on Probability.4 This one work established Keynes as the authority of his time on probability theory, and maintains his reputation today as a leading spokesman for the a priori (AP) interpretation of probability.
Keynes was the first self-conscious apriorist in probability theory. He asserted emphatically that probability is a logical relation between propositions and, according to Carnap, was the first to perceive and emphasize the fact that such probabilities are inherently relative to given evidence and to nothing else.5
Such assertions, and the philosophical argumentation which supports them, constitute Keynes’s most famous and significant contributions to the development of probability theory. His derivation of theorems in the probability calculus represented at best a mild improvement over his predecessors and is not historically important. His attempted revision of the Principle of Indifference is frequently referred to and generally considered to be an improvement, but it does not attack the fundamental question whether any such principle can be a legitimate source of initial probabilities. Thus Keynes is seldom cited for these achievements. Instead, he finds his place as the pre-eminent representative of a priori probability theory, and when he is discussed by philosophers it is usually in this role as the embodiment and spokesman of a priori probability rather than as the source of some particular argument or theorem (in contrast to Bernoulli or Bayes, for example).
Rudolf Carnap (1891-1970) was ‘the most prominent representative of the logical empiricist, or logical positivist, school in the philosophy of science and logic.’6 His early training in physics led him to accept the relative frequency (RF) theory of probability,7 but his name is now more associated with his later development of AP probability theory as a form of quantitative inductive logic.
Carnap’s AP theory is of a piece with his notable work in the related fields of logic, syntax, semantics, and formal languages. It is impossible to convey fully the nature of his system of a priori probability without requiring or providing some grounding in the concepts and formalizations he employs. At least a hundred pages of his Logical Foundations of Probability8 are devoted to just this preliminary spadework – the task is ...

Table of contents