Kant and the Problem of Politics
eBook - ePub

Kant and the Problem of Politics

Rethinking the Contemporary World

Luigi Caranti, Alessandro Pinzani, Luigi Caranti, Alessandro Pinzani

Share book
  1. 170 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Kant and the Problem of Politics

Rethinking the Contemporary World

Luigi Caranti, Alessandro Pinzani, Luigi Caranti, Alessandro Pinzani

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This book examines the significance of Kant's political philosophy in the context of contemporary philosophical and political debates. In the last few decades, Kantian specialists have increasingly manifested a purely exegetic and philological interest in Kant's oeuvre, while contemporary philosophers and scientists tend to use Kant with scant hermeneutical care, thus misrepresenting or misunderstanding his positions. This volume countervails these tendencies by focusing more on specific themes of contemporary relevance in Kant's writings. It looks to Kant's political thought for insight on tackling issues such as freedom of speech, democracy and populism, intergenerational justice, economic inequality, money, poverty, international justice and gender/feminism.

Featuring readings by well-known Kant specialists and emerging scholars with unorthodox approaches to Kant's philosophy, the volume fills a significant gap in the existing scholarship on the philosopher and his works. It will be of great interest to scholars and researchers of philosophy, politics and ethics.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Kant and the Problem of Politics an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Kant and the Problem of Politics by Luigi Caranti, Alessandro Pinzani, Luigi Caranti, Alessandro Pinzani in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Epistemology in Philosophy. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2022
ISBN
9781000605457

1The practice of sovereignty Kant on the duties of national and international citizenship

Paul Guyer
DOI: 10.4324/9781003033837-2

Introduction

Kant is well known for his view that within a state, even one that falls short of the ideal of justice that is required by morality itself, there can be no constitutional right to forcible resistance against perceived injustices, only the freedom of citizens to criticize the government and petition for redress and a corresponding duty of the government to reform itself in the direction of a more fully just republic.1 Both together no doubt constitute an ongoing and never-ending process because of the imperfections of human beings, including those in positions of power. The ground for this position is his view that the purpose of a state is to make the rights and possessions of its citizens determinate and secure and that in order to accomplish the latter, there must be a monopoly of coercive power within an executive branch, even though in Kant’s view, sovereignty lies in the legislature, as the expression of the ultimate right of the people, and the executive is in principle only an agent of the legislature: a state that does not maintain a monopoly of coercion in its executive but allows another locus of potential coercion either within its legislature or in the people without parliamentary representation against all branches of government cannot accomplish the legitimate and morally necessary ends of the state and is thus not a genuine state at all – but we all stand under a duty to be part of a just state. In relations among sovereign2 territorial states, Kant holds that there is no room for the coercive enforcement of rights by the analogue of an international executive both for the a priori reason that the existence of such a coercive force would undermine the monopoly on coercion by the executives within the several states and for the empirical reason that a world-wide government could not remain a republic but would inevitably degenerate into a world-wide despotism. Opposite grounds, same outcome: because of the impossibility rather than the necessity of international coercion, the only legitimate way for different states to address disputes over their rights is through means similar to the only permissible means for the redress of injustices within states – through the rights of nations to address one another peacefully concerning their desires and disputes and the duties of nations to seek resolutions for their disputes and progress toward greater international justice peaceably rather than through force. Neither intranationally nor internationally can justice ultimately be enforced through anything except good will, at least on the part of rulers within states and between states. Within states, what we might call the mechanism of juridical and penal institutions that is designed to ensure compliance with law through aversive incentives rather than sheer respect for the moral law must in the end be operated by individuals who themselves cannot be coerced into doing the right thing so must be motivated by morality itself, while at the international level, the institutions of conflict resolution do not have enforcement powers so can ultimately be enforced only by the good will of the sovereign states involved, however that is achieved.
My interpretation of the first part of Kant’s position will not be controversial, although Kant does not emphasize the duty of rulers to reform their states as much as he emphasizes the right of subjects to petition for reform. My interpretation of its second part may be more controversial. Many have held that, under the rubric of international law, Kant argues for the necessity of a single world-state with the power to enforce its laws coercively and that Kant’s additional discussion of “cosmopolitan right” concerns only the right of individuals of one nation to approach those of another for purposes of commerce. Kant has not been seen as insisting on a general right of nations to make diplomatic representations to one another and a corresponding duty of nations to respond to such representations even in the absence of a supranational authority for the coercive enforcement of their agreements. So to sustain the interpretation of Kant’s conception of intra- and international justice that I have sketched, I will have to show that Kant does not argue for an international state (Völkerstaat) rather than a league or forum of nations (Völkerbund) and will also have to show that his explicit argument for the right to approach other nations peaceably for purposes of commerce, whether as nations under the rubric of international law or as individuals under the rubric of cosmopolitan right, presupposes a more general obligation toward peaceable international diplomacy that Kant does not make explicit.

1. Justice within nations

The foundation of Kant’s theory of both national and international justice is of course the Universal Principle of Right. Although stated in the form of a definition, this principle expresses the imperative that each agent must be allowed as much scope for freedom of action as is compatible with an equal scope for freedom for any agent with whom the former might interact: “Any action is right if it can coexist with everyone’s freedom in accordance with a universal law, or if on its maxim the freedom of choice of each can coexist with everyone’s freedom in accordance with a universal law” (MS, RL Introduction, section C, 006:230).3 This principle might seem to be a strictly a priori principle, derived either from the universal law formulation of the categorical imperative or directly from the concept of freedom itself as the foundation of morality,4 but it presupposes the empirical assumption that the freedom of action by any human agent as the expression of her freedom of choice can limit the freedom of choice in her freedom of action by any other through the interaction of their bodies; such interactions can limit not merely the expression of an agent’s choice in external action but also constrain their ability even to set ends, since an agent cannot rationally set an end for herself for which she does not believe she has adequate means given the choices made by others, among other possible factual conditions.5 That human beings have bodies that can interfere with each other in this way is not something that is known a priori. Rather than consisting solely of a priori principles valid for all rational beings, as does Kant’s groundwork for morals, Kant’s metaphysics of morals, including the metaphysical foundations of right, explores the implications of the a priori principle of morality for rational beings in our embodied condition, something of which we have only empirical knowledge, just as Kant’s metaphysics of nature explores the implications of the foundational principles of theoretical philosophy for creatures who can only detect matter by motion.6 Other empirical facts on which Kant’s doctrine of right depends, or more precisely the more concrete facts that constitute the general fact that the freely chosen actions of human beings can limit the freedom of each other, are that human bodies need a place on the earth to occupy, that their subsistence depends on the use and consumption of objects other than their own bodies that can only be produced on a piece of the earth and that the ground that human beings have to occupy is finite, the surface of a sphere any part of which is in principle accessible from any other, with no natural division of this surface into determinate parts antecedently assigned to particular individuals. A further empirical assumption that Kant makes throughout his practical philosophy – it is already assumed in the transition from the fundamental principle of morality to the categorical imperative as the presentation of the moral law to human beings in the form of an imperative, that is, a constraint – is that human beings are not always naturally impelled to adhere faithfully to all the dictates of morality and can thus reasonably assume that neither they themselves nor their fellows will always conform to the requirements of justice out of respect for the moral law alone. All of these assumptions, it is safe to say, although contingent and only empirically known, are incontrovertible.
The central tenets of Kant’s theory of justice follow from the application of the moral law to us as creatures in these empirical circumstances. In Kant’s view, we have an innate right to freedom from interference with our person, that is, the right to our bodily integrity. Thus, as long as one is “irreproachable”, that is, not performing any act that threatens or injures the rights of others, others have no right to attack one physically, for example, to wrest something out of one’s hand. But the innate right to freedom also includes the right to use our bodies in any way that does not infringe upon the freedom of others, including the right to speak freely to others as long “it is entirely up to them whether they want to believe” what one tells them (MS, RL, Division, 06:238); this is just part of what it means to allow each the greatest sphere of freedom compatible with the equal freedom of others. Further, however, human beings also need a place to put their bodies, to stand or rest, as well as a place to cultivate food and materials for warmth and clothing or, in more complex economies, to perform other sorts of work, as well as to store and exchange the products of these labors, and for this reason, they must be allowed to acquire rights to property, both to land and the products of and improvements upon the land, but also to temporary (contractual) or enduring (familial and household) relations with each other. One may say that human beings have an innate right to acquire rights to land and goods and services.7 Yet since the land of the earth is not naturally divided into determinate parcels, human beings must so divide it before individuals can acquire rights to particular parcels, and since no particular human being has a natural relation to any particular piece of land or place, but, other things being equal, any person could use any piece of land or external object, any individual’s claim to any particular parcel must be accepted by others, and, if their claim is to be just or rightful, the consent of others or the “omnilateral will” that one should use a particular parcel must be freely obtained, that is, not itself be an undue limitation on the freedom of others:
a unilateral will cannot serve as a coercive law for everyone with regard to possession that is external and therefore contingent, since that would infringe upon freedom in accordance with universal laws. So it is only a will putting everyone under a general obligation, hence only a collective general (common)
(MS, RL §8, 06:256)
will that can create individual rights to determinate possessions. And the only kind of division of land and resources that all who could use them could freely consent to must be one that all involved can see as in some fundamental way equal or fair (which Kant would understand primarily in terms of equality of opportunity rather than outcome).8
But further, since human beings, as a matter of empirical fact, cannot trust each other (or themselves) to adhere even to a just division of land and resources out of the goodness of their hearts, that is, out of respect for the moral law alone, they must have assurance of some other motivation for adhering to such a division. Thus the division of resources and assignments of rights to them to which all could freely consent must also be coercively enforceable: no one i...

Table of contents