European Disunion
eBook - ePub

European Disunion

Democracy, Sovereignty and the Politics of Emergency

Stefan Auer

Share book
  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

European Disunion

Democracy, Sovereignty and the Politics of Emergency

Stefan Auer

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

The European Union means many different things to its many peoples. In Germany, for example, the European project was conceived mainly as post-national, or even post-sovereign. In France, by contrast, President Emmanuel Macron has pursued the vision of a sovereign Europe; that is, an EU that would become a formidable geopolitical actor. Yet, instead, Europe has struggled to ascertain its values abroad and even domestically, facing a sovereignist rebellion from its newer member states, such as Hungary and Poland, and the departure of Britain. The eurozone crisis has undermined the EU's economic credentials, the refugee crisis its societal cohesion, the failure to stand up to Russia its sense of purpose, and the Covid-19 pandemic its credibility as a protector of European citizens.

The key argument of this book is that the multiple crises of the European project are caused by one underlying factor: its bold attempt to overcome the age of nation-states. Left unchecked, supranational institutions tend to become ever more bureaucratic, eluding control of the people they are meant to serve. The logic of technocracy is thus pitted against the democratic impulse, which the European Union is supposed to embody. Democracy in Europe has suffered as a result.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is European Disunion an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access European Disunion by Stefan Auer in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Politics & International Relations & Democracy. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.
1
THE RETURN OF SOVEREIGNTY
‘The dictator is coming.’
With these words, the then President of the European Commission, Jean-Claude Juncker, turned towards the then Prime Minister of Latvia, Laimdota Straujuma, to announce the arrival of her Hungarian counterpart, Viktor Orbán. Upon his entry, Juncker greeted Orbán as ‘dictator’—shaking his hand and playfully slapping him in the face.1
It was remarkable that Europe’s leading political figures appeared jovial and exceedingly friendly towards Orbán, just at a time when within Europe and beyond there was growing concern about Hungary’s turn towards authoritarian rule.2 The bizarre encounter took place in Riga in May 2015, when the Latvian presidency of the Council of the EU hosted yet another summit chaired by Donald Tusk, then President of the European Council. The leaders gathered according to a well-established ritual of the European Council, a part of which is taking a ‘family photo’, symbolising Europe’s unity. The role of the Council has always been somewhat contradictory—very powerful in practice, as it comprises all the national leaders, though formally its brief is rather circumscribed. In fact, the Council’s purpose was only explicitly defined as recently as 2009 in the Treaty of Lisbon, which describes its mission as providing ‘the Union with the necessary impetus for its development’ and defining ‘the general political direction and priorities thereof’. Importantly, the Treaty stipulates that the Council ‘shall not exercise legislative functions’ (cited in Olsen 2020: 111).3
But my focus here is not on the EU’s institutional architecture. Instead, this vignette aims to highlight a troubling paradox at the heart of the European project. The European Union’s raison d’ĂȘtre is to protect democracy in Europe. Yet over the last couple of decades it has overseen—or even became complicit in—the erosion of democracy in a number of its member states. The surprising camaraderie between Juncker and OrbĂĄn illustrates a strangely symbiotic relationship between technocracy and populism. The two leaders were able to feed off each other. This is not to say that Juncker was ever a mere technocrat, just as dismissing OrbĂĄn’s phenomenal political success simply as populism is an incomplete account at best. But what they came to represent in the eyes of their allies and opponents was respectively technocratic governance and populist rebellion: ‘post-political juristocracy on the one side and democratatorship Ă  la OrbĂĄn on the other’ (Manow 2020: 18).4
To describe Juncker as a technocrat at all is in fact something of a misnomer. The former Prime Minister of Luxembourg was a successful politician for many years prior to his EU career, and in his role as the EU Commission President he proved a formidable political actor. This is not to ignore Juncker’s lack of popularity, missteps, policy failures and even his controversial stewardship of Luxembourg’s fiscal regime (Faiola 2014). Evaluating his three-decades-long feat of political survival in Luxembourg (for eighteen years of which he was Prime Minister), a journalistic sketch referred to him as a ‘man with many talents but without qualities’ (Schmit, Stoldt and Thomas 2012), and predicted a quick end to his career. Instead, he became a veritable ‘Homo Europus’ (Mulder 2019), taking his survival skills to a higher European level. It was under Juncker’s leadership that the British voted to leave the EU. And as President of the EU Commission, Juncker also oversaw the (mis-)management of both the euro and the refugee crises. Yet the problem was not Juncker as a person, but rather what the Luxembourger came to personify—the mode of supranational governance that bounced between technocracy and the politics of the exception.
Reflecting the EU’s intricate system of governance, the role of the EU Commissioners is somewhat ambiguous. They are not meant to act as politicians, but neither are they merely civil servants. An example of this ambiguous role is the recent attempt at ‘politicising’ the Commission. Its aim has been to improve the quality of the EU’s democracy via the so-called Spitzenkandidaten process, in which the European Parliament was to have a decisive voice in the selection of the Commission President. Yet, the European Commission, in its position as the ‘Guardian of the Treaties’ is also meant to fulfil the role of an impartial arbiter between all member states, regardless of which political party rules them. Not surprisingly then, ‘Juncker’s political Commission’ of 2014–19 was a mixed blessing (Dawson 2019). In fact, it can be argued that the limited success of this approach—empowering the Commission President as a Spitzenkandidat—exposed the limits of the idea that the EU should be democratised by further empowerment of the European Parliament and its transnational party system. If anything, strengthening the role of the Commission might unwittingly accelerate the process of ‘the de-institutinalisation of power’ (White 2021: 2), the result of which would be less, rather than more democratic accountability. As Jonathan White argued, Juncker’s governing style exemplifies the tendency within the contemporary EU, which responded to numerous emergencies by individuals subordinating and remaking institutions to serve higher ends—such as the preservation of European unity. In other words, rather than taking his authority from the office, Juncker ‘was an individual asserting his personal authority to redefine and reshape what the office entailed’ (White 2021: 11). Ursula von der Leyen might not be as charismatic as her predecessor, nor was she ever a Spitzenkandidat, but like Juncker she too had strong personal ambitions. Following on from his ‘political Commission’, she promised to lead a ‘geopolitical’ one.
Juncker also articulated a classic defence of technocratic rationality removed from parliamentary scrutiny when he explained, ‘we all know what to do, we just don’t know how to get re-elected after we’ve done it’. Amongst EU officials and scholars, this notion became known as the ‘Juncker Curse’ (Copsey 2015: 147). Following this logic, Juncker defended the EU’s decision-making mechanisms that were often opaque and lacking sufficient democratic accountability. Doing so, he echoed the logic of what is known as the ‘Monnet method’, which is embraced by proponents of functionalist theories of European integration, and criticised by more sceptical voices as ‘integration through stealth’ (Majone 2005): ‘We decide on something, leave it lying around, and wait and see what happens. If no one kicks up a fuss, because most people don’t understand what has been decided, we continue step by step until there is no turning back’ (cited in De Vries 2018: 56).
The downside of this approach is the erosion of trust in both EU and national political institutions and their representatives. The more competencies the EU acquired affecting various aspects of citizen’s lives, the harder it got to pursue this mode of integration. Particularly over the last couple of decades, the process of European integration had been punctuated by numerous episodes of people ‘kicking up a fuss’. In order to pre-empt such responses, Juncker went so far as to justify lying in the pursuit of major policy goals, stating that ‘if things get serious, you have to know how to lie’ (Hewitt 2014). This might come as a surprise to observers of contemporary politics who consider lies to be an indispensable part of the populist playbook. This takes us back to Hungary, where a Prime Minister confessed to his party faithful:
There’s not much choice. There’s not much because we screwed up. Not a little, but badly. No country in Europe has been as dim-witted as we have. There’s an explanation. Obviously we lied throughout the last year-and-a-half or two. I nearly died when for a year-and-a-half I had to pretend to govern. Instead, we lied morning, noon and night.5
This frank speech was later leaked to the press, leading to anti-government protests and clashes with the police that left more than a hundred people wounded. Yet the target of people’s anger was not Orbán, the self-proclaimed adherent of illiberal democracy, but rather his liberal, pro-European predecessor Ferenc Gyurcsány, whose government paved the way for the Fidesz landslide victory, enabling the ensuing consolidation of Orbán’s rule. What Gyurcsány represents in the context of post-1989 democratic transformation in Central and Eastern Europe is the failure of pro-European, liberal elites to gain sufficient public support for economic and political reforms (as I discuss further in Chapter 5). The governing elites’ reliance on technocratic rationality backfired, leaving many people across the region feeling that their revolutions were ‘stolen’ (Krapfl 2013). What was particularly disconcerting was the ability of many former communists to reinvent themselves as passionate adherents of free market liberalism and European integration. They succeeded in transforming their pre-1989 political capital into considerable private wealth (Tucker 2015), which in turn endowed them with more political power. The widespread perception that politicians of all stripes were corrupt was thus not without justification. This is an aspect of populist rebellions in new member states that tends to be overlooked. In Hungary, following Gyurcsány’s fall from grace, Orbán’s party won the elections to the European Parliament in 2009, and national parliamentary elections in 2010. With his popularity unabated at the time of writing, Orbán is arguably one of the few remaining politicians who has shaped European politics for more than two decades (and in this respect, is on the path to overtake both Angela Merkel and Juncker). This is not to ignore the divisive nature of Orbán’s policies, or the nefarious methods he used to pursue them. Yet what is particularly interesting about his spectacular success in Hungary for the present book, is the extent to which it reveals democratic dysfunction across Europe.
The Crisis of Representative Democracy and the Return of the Political
In response to a number of pressing challenges, particularly over the last decade or so, the European Union has unwittingly exacerbated the crisis of representative democracy. As ‘emergency Europe’ (White 2015) has become the new normal of this experimental polity, unsettling the existing governing structures, the theoretical frameworks underpinning the European project ought to be questioned as well. To do so, I turn to political and legal thinkers including Hans Kelsen, Carl Schmitt and Hannah Arendt, who confronted a more dramatic and altogether more serious challenge to democracy: the constitutional breakdown of the Weimar Republic followed by the rise of Nazi Germany and the devastating impact of the Second World War. While the concept of popular sovereignty was at the centre of debates about democracy in the first half of the twentieth century, more recently its usefulness has been questioned. Ironically, discussions about sovereignty were declared retrograde just at the time when the process of European integration was entering a phase that would prove their relevance.
With the privilege of hindsight, one could say that the start of the new millennium marked the moment of peak globalisation, which was in Europe further reinforced by intensified processes of economic and political integration. While the EU scholarship was then dominated by claims about Europe leaving concerns with popular sovereignty behind, some major innovations at the EU level, such as the creation of the Economic and Monetary Union (EMU), exacerbated the perceived loss of control. The global financial crisis (GFC) of 2008, for which Europe was ill prepared, acted as a catalyst for a decade of crises from which the European Union is yet to recover. These upheavals led to a backlash against a more cosmopolitan Europe, and to the reassertion of sovereignty at a national level. Brexit was but one example—if a particularly spectacular one—of this trend. The rise of ‘sovereignist’ political leadership in Hungary and Poland, and the ongoing strength of nationalist mobilisation across Europe, including within large, founding member states such as Italy and France, suggest that nationalism as a political force is here to stay. As Bernard Yack pithily observed, ‘the age of liberal democracy is also the age of nationalism’ (2003: 29). Yack’s argument about politics in general applies equally to the EU: ‘liberal politics rests on a familiar but rarely analyzed image of political community, one that tends to nationalize our understanding of politics and politicize our understanding of nationality’ (ibid. 31).
To take this argument a step further, I suggest that the process of democratising the EU’s politics unwittingly nationalises it. On this view, increased national mobilisation is not, per se, undermining democracy in Europe, but is rather a response to attempts at its democratisation. In fact, Yack’s key argument is that an important source ‘of the politicization of national loyalties in the modern world seems to be an idea that most liberals continue to hold both dear and indispensable to a decent political order: the principle of popular sovereignty’ (2003: 50). This claim is no longer all that controversial within broader discussions of political history (Roshwald 2006) and contemporary political theory (Tamir 1993, 2019; Miller 1995, 2016; Stilz 2019). Yet it continues to be viewed with suspicion within EU studies, where popular sovereignty is seen as ‘the source of the ills that befell Europe in the twentieth century’ (Lev 2017: 208), with the EU being presented as a successful example of a ‘post-sovereign’ polity.6 A good illustration of this view is Jan-Werner MĂŒller’s series of rhetorical questions:
[D]oes European integration, in fact, prove how useless the Schmittian intellectual tool kit has become, and, in particular, that ‘Schmittian sovereignty’ remains caught in existentialist, concretist ways of thinking, which have long lost touch with the intricate ‘legitimation through procedure’ or the legitimation through prosperity which some see at the heart of the EU? Has functionalist integration, a kind of ‘polity-building by stealth,’ by ‘neutralizing’ the ‘primacy of the political,’ disproved Schmitt’s suspicion of the liberal order to sustain itself through purely economic means? Has Schmittian unitary and decisionist sovereignty, which always asks for the identification of the final arbiter, been extinguished in favor of ‘pooled sovereignty’ and a kind of subtle sovereignty by ‘mutual recognition, continuity and consent’? (2000: 1779)
To be blunt, my answers are no, no and no. First, legitimation through procedures might work in normal times, but Europe has had very little normality over the last three decades. Second, I contest the view that a liberal order could ‘sustain itself through purely economic means’. What the recent European developments have shown instead are the limitations of ‘polity-building by stealth’. Attempts to overcome political conflicts via ‘neutralisation’ did not help European democracies, which leads me to my third ‘no’ regarding ‘pooled sovereignty’—a conceptual tool that tends to obscure power, unwittingly exacerbating the problem of democratic accountability. As Yack put it, sovereign control is exclusive—‘if one community possesses it, another cannot’. In other words, the sovereign is the one who has the final say on any given territory. Thus, sovereignty that is pooled or joint ‘is either a metaphor or a contradiction in terms’ (Yack 2003: 43).
In what follows, I will first sketch a somewhat schematic genealogy of the kind of thinking that MĂŒller’s praise of ‘post-sovereign’ polity exemplifies (Rousseau, Kelsen, KojĂšve) and foreground my further arguments with a brief discussion of opposing thinkers (Schmitt, Arendt).
The desire to neutralise the ‘primacy of the political’, which can be viewed as part of the EU’s DNA, has a long pedigree. It is linked to the idea that political conflicts could and ought to be overcome by reason, which can be traced back to a particular strand of the Enlightenment represented by the likes of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, and restated more recently by John Rawls and JĂŒrgen Habermas. Against the premise that ‘might makes right’, commonly associated with Hugo Grotius and Thomas Hobbes (and later revived by, e. g., Schmitt), Rousseau constructs a political order based on a social contract. Rousseau’s bold blueprint in effect reverses the earlier notion, suggesting that right makes might. The social contract is just and legitimate because it relies on citizens’ mutual acceptance of their shared interests, embodied in what Rousseau calls volontĂ© gĂ©nĂ©rale—‘the general will’. This is not to be confused with the will of a majority, as people can be easily deceived about what is good for them, while ‘the general will is always in the right, and always tends to the public welfare’ (Rousseau [1762] 1994: 66). It follows then, that true freedom consists in people’s compliance with the general will. By contrast, those individuals who are not sufficiently enlightened to internalise the wisdom of the general will and who defy its demands are enslaved by their selfish instincts. They shall be ‘forced to be free’ (ibid. 58). In other words, they ought to be liberated from the influence of their ill-informed private will. Clearly, what Rousseau envisaged is rather different from contemporary notions of liberty, in which freedom also entails the freedom to be left alone. In line with this, Rousseau did not believe in the possibility, or even desirability of political representation. His package was all or nothing, and his conception of sovereignty somewhat circular: ‘simply by virtue of its existence, the sovereign is always what it should be’ (ibid. 58).
Perpetual European Union
However impractical The Social Contract might appear today, Rousseau already understood that his blueprint could only work on a relatively small scale. How to apply the same logic to the relationship between sovereigns was far trickier. On the surface, it seems obvious that cooperation would be in their mutual rational interests. This assumption underpins a number of ambitious designs for lasting peace. As early as 1712, AbbĂ© de Saint-Pierre (1658–1743) advanced a project ‘to render Peace perpetual in Europe’, proposing ‘a Treaty to establish a perpetual European Union’ (cited in Heuser 2019: 132–3). Rousseau considered its underlying logic compelling, writing that it would be enough to ‘realize this commonwealth of Europe for a single day’ to make it last forever; ‘so fully would experience convince men that their own gain is to be found in the good of all’ (Rousseau [1756] 1991: 88–9). Yet however logical this scheme was, Rousseau was profoundly sceptical about its realisability. He anticipated Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s criticism of contractual theories applied to international relations. The rights of nations, Hegel argued in the Philosophy of Right (PR), ‘have reality not in a general will, which is constituted as a superior power, but in their particular wills’ (cited in Glendinning 2014; compare Hegel [1821] 1989: 499–500, §333). Along similar lines, Rousseau criticised Saint-Pierre’s ‘perpetual European Union’, describing his plan ‘as ineffectual for founding it and unnecessary for maintaining it’. Foreshadowing the problems of EU democratic legitimacy that cannot rely simply on ‘delivering the goods’, Rousseau observed that
though the advantages resulting to commerce from a general and lasting peace are in themselves certain and indisputable, still, being common to all states, they will be appreciated by none. For such advantages make themselves felt only by contrast, and he who wishes to increase his relative power is ...

Table of contents