Anthropology of the Self
eBook - ePub

Anthropology of the Self

The Individual in Cultural Perspective

Brian Morris

Share book
  1. 240 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Anthropology of the Self

The Individual in Cultural Perspective

Brian Morris

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Western society is individualised; we feel at ease talking about individuals and we study individual behaviour through psychology and psychoanalysis. Yet anthropology teaches us that an individual approach is only one of many ways of looking at ourselves. In this wide-ranging text Morris explores the origins, doctrines and conceptions of the self in Western, Asian and African societies passing though Greek philosophy, Buddhism, Hinduism, Confuscism, Tao and African philosophy and ending with contemporary feminism. Scholarly and written in a lucid style, free of jargon, this work is written from an anthropological perspective with an interdisciplinary approach. Morris emphasises the varying conceptions of the self found cross-culturally and contrasts these with the conceptions found in the Western intellectual traditions.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Anthropology of the Self an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Anthropology of the Self by Brian Morris in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Ciencias biológicas & Ciencias en general. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Pluto Press
Year
1994
ISBN
9781783715244
1 Introduction
The present study is a critical introduction to cultural conceptions of the person. It has therefore a specific focus – on what an earlier generation of anthropologists would have termed cultural ‘world-views’, or on what Roy D’Andrade (1984) has more recently described as ‘cultural meaning systems’. Such meaning systems are quite distinct from – though of course related to – social structure and human praxis. Nothing but confusion reigns if culture is simply conflated with social practice and social relationships; and the tendency of writers like Jurgen Habermas (1972) and Tim Ingold (1986) to separate social interaction and communicative processes from human material and pragmatic relationships with the world, in neo-Kantian fashion, is I think also to be resisted. I am not in this study then concerned with social praxis, but rather with cultural paradigms, and with what, in specific contexts, these paradigms have to tell us about people’s conception of the person as a cultural category. I do not therefore focus on such psychosocial phenomena as the self, personal identity or subjectivity in its wider sense, and so I devote little discussion to such important topics as race, ethnicity, nationality, occupation, class and gender – all of which are constitutive of people’s conception of themselves, as individual subjects.
In the past decade there has been a resurgence of interest in cultural conceptions of the person. In a wide variety of academic disciplines – Marxism, psychoanalysis, structuralist and post-structuralist theory, cultural anthropology, feminist philosophy, humanistic psychology – theories of the person or of the human subject are now commonplace. ‘Self’ and ‘subjectivity’ have become key concepts in social theory, and some general texts in philosophy take the issue of the ‘self’ as their main organising principle (e.g. Barrett 1986, Solomon 1988). I have elsewhere (1991) explored the varying conceptions of the human subject within the Western intellectual tradition, and the varying responses to the classical episteme of the Enlightenment which, with respect to both the empiricists and the rationalists, tended to conceptualise the person as an ‘individuated’ asocial being. The present study is, in a sense, a sequel to this text and looks at conceptions of the person from a more cross-cultural perspective.
For many anthropologists three scholars have been particularly important in generating an interest in cross-cultural understanding of the person. These are Marcel Mauss, Irving Hallowell and Meyer Fortes; their writings have been seminal. I discuss the work of Fortes in the text, specifically focusing on his ethnographic studies of the Tallensi. But it may be useful here to introduce the work of the other two scholars before attempting to clarify the various meanings that surround the concept of the person.
A nephew of Durkheim, Marcel Mauss was also probably his foremost student. Durkheim decribed him as ‘my alter ego’. After Durkheim’s death, Mauss became a leading figure of French sociology, and had an important influence on both Radcliffe-Brown and Levi-Strauss. An important Sanskrit scholar as well as a sociologist, Mauss was by all accounts a man of immense erudition, although he lacked a strong sense of direction and organisation and never completed his dissertation.
Throughout his life Mauss closely followed the methodological and theoretical canons of Durkheim’s sociology, and appears to have studiously avoided any criticisms of his uncle (Evans-Pritchard 1981:190). But he went beyond Durkheim in at least two important ways. In the first place his analyses drew upon a greater diversity of empirical material – both historical and ethnographic. In doing so he developed the structuralist aspects of Durkheim’s sociology (Bottomore and Nisbet 1979:572). Levi-Strauss indeed suggests that his essay on The Gift has a ‘revolutionary character’, inaugurating for the social sciences a ‘new era’ (1987:37–41). Second, Mauss was far more willing than Durkheim to explore psychological issues, and with respect to the present study two essays are of particular interest. The first was an address to the Societe de Psychologie (1924) on the relationship between psychology and sociology; the second, ‘A category of the human mind; the notion of person; the notion of self’ (1938), was one of his last works.
In discussing the relationship between sociology and psychology, Mauss follows Durkheim in arguing that they are distinct sciences which relate to two ‘different terrains’, and he is thus sceptical of William McDougall’s contention that sociology is fundamentally a collective psychology that reduces collective phenomena to individual interactions. But Mauss is equally critical of separating the consciousness of the group from the whole of its material and concrete substratum. A social fact, no matter how abstract, should never be completely detached, he writes, either from its local moorings or from its historical matrix (1979:9). In fact he defines anthropology as the sum total of the sciences (biology, psychology, sociology) that considers the human person ‘as a living, conscious and sociable being’ (5). For Mauss, unlike Comte and Leslie White, there is always scope for psychology. No matter how completely invasive the collective representations may be, it always ‘leaves the individual a sanctuary, his consciousness’, and it is the individual who is always the source of action (1979:10).
In his other essay Mauss discusses the various forms that the notion of the self (moi) has assumed at various times and in various places. The essay follows the style of the French school of sociology, namely in focusing on the social history of one of the categories of the human mind. With Mauss, as with Durkheim, the shades of Aristotle and Kant hover in the background. Whereas his essay on symbolic classification, co-authored with Durkheim, had focused upon the category of class, and his analysis of magic, co-authored with Hubert, on the concept of cause, so the present essay focused on the category of the person (personne) or self (moi). Mauss makes it clear that a concept of self is probably evident in all human communities, and he makes a distinction between the sense of self, the conscious personality, and the concept of self, and it is with the latter, as a social category, that he is specifically concerned. He clearly felt that this notion had evolved, and had passed through a succession of forms during the course of history. The modern conception of the person, and particularly the ‘cult of the self’ was, he felt, of recent origin. He also made it clear that in his opinion all human beings had an awareness of their bodies, and of their individuality, both spiritual and physical.
In earlier human communities, Mauss suggests, people have an essentially sociocentric conception of the person, and this notion is intrinsically linked to clan membership. In ritual contexts and sacred dramas, however, when they take on specific roles (personnage), there emerges the beginning of a detachment of the individual subject from absorption in the social group. Drawing on the limited ethnographic material then available, Mauss discusses the Zuni, Kwakuitl and Winnebago Indians, and the Australian Aboriginal conceptions of the person, stressing the importance that is often given to spiritual reincarnation. In the metaphysical religious systems of China and India (particularly the Samkhya and Vedanta systems) the development of the human person as a complete entity independent of society, but not of god, is further developed. There is an increasing awareness of the notion of the self (moi) with Roman culture, from which the term personne (meaning mask) is taken, and the idea of an independent self was particularly expressed by the Stoics. Slaves, of course, were not conceived of as persons by the Roman aristocracy and thus had no personality. But, Mauss argues, it is only with the coming of Christianity that the true metaphysical foundations of the person as a moral subject became fully established. A transition occurred between the notion of persona, of a ‘man clad in a condition’, to the notion of the person as an autonomous human subject. Of particular importance in this changing conception of the person were the sectarian movements of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, for they ‘posed the question regarding individual liberty, regarding the individual conscience and the right to communicate directly with god’ (1979:88). Finally, a further transformation occurred in the notion of person when, in the philosophical writings of Kant and Fichte, it became a psychological category. Thus Mauss concludes that the conception of the person as an individuated self is not an innate or primordial idea ‘inscribed since Adam in the deepest part of our being’ but is rather a notion that has historically developed (1979:87).
Many have seen this evolutionary approach as somewhat old fashioned, but nevertheless Mauss has stimulated a wealth of discussion on the category of the person (Carrithers et al. 1985). Mauss also had an important influence on Maurice Leenhardt, Meyer Fortes and Louis Dumont. Dumont’s stimulating critique of the individualism inherent in the Western intellectual tradition, and in much anthropology, I have discussed more fully elsewhere (1991:262–74).
Irving Hallowell was, like Malinowski, a perceptive ethnographer, but his theoretical suggestions are very different. A much-neglected scholar, whose work has only in recent years come to be recognised, Hallowell has implicitly, and through his students – Spiro, Bourguignon and Wallace in particular – had a profound and pervasive influence in the making of psychological anthropology. He has been described as ‘a unique scholar with ideas far ahead of his time’ (Bock 1980:81).
For Hallowell an understanding of human nature and culture seemed to necessitate both a relativist and a universalist viewpoint. As he wrote:
Perhaps it is characteristic of man to be always different yet always the same. Perhaps this is what anthropologists have sensed without formulating it, since in moving from one people to another the fieldworker always has assumed that there were both psychological and cultural constants to be expected; identifiable emotions such as sorrow and hate, self-awareness and reflective thought, a scheme of moral values, a world view, tools etc. (1976:228)
On the whole, he suggested, cultural anthropologists had tended to overstress cultural relativism. Experimental psychologists, on the other hand, had gone to the other extreme: ‘They ignored the study of man as a social being and the varieties in his culturally constituted mode of life.’ Human nature cannot be
exclusively identified with what is biologically innate and invariant … Viewed functionally and historically, it appears to be the indeterminate aspect of man’s nature that makes him unique, the inherent potentialities of which, under the necessary motivational conditions, may lead to new and varied forms of social, cultural and psychological adjustment.
And Hallowell concludes that ‘cultural diversities and common denominators of culture are part of the total human picture; both categories of phenomena must be related to the whole nature of man’ (1976:227–8).
In adopting such an approach Hallowell came to suggest two essential themes, which he explored and developed in a number of essays: namely, that generic psychological structures are intrinsically related to the evolution of the human species and human culture; and that the self is structured in terms of a variable behavioural environment. I shall briefly discuss each of these themes in turn.
Although some earlier anthropologists like Mauss, Radin and Lee had discussed the concepts of person and self from an anthropological perspective, it is safe to say that these concepts – central though they are – were generally neglected in ethnographic studies. The person is but a shadowy figure in these earlier accounts. Hallowell, in an important sense, laid the foundations for the study of what has come to be termed ‘indigenous psychologies’ – though of course studies of the person or self by philosophers and psychologists are voluminous, particularly in relation to phenomenology and personality theory.
Hallowell observed that the evolution of the human species had been examined from a number of perspectives – in terms of the taxonomy and phylogeny of the primates; in terms of the development of language or tool-making; in terms of social structure or culture as a specific human mode of adaptation. He suggested that an increased understanding of the complex process of human evolution may be gained in two ways. Firstly, that we should try to get away from the idea that there is a radical discontinuity inherent in the evolutionary process, as if culture, language and humankind suddenly leapt into existence. He therefore postulated the concept of protoculture, a preadaptive stage exemplified by non-hominid primates (Hallowell 1960:359–60, 1976:291–4, Bourguignon 1979:29–39).
Secondly, he suggested a conjunctive approach to human evolution, seeing behaviour as the ‘unifying centre’ of other significant variables. Tool-making would then, for example, be interpreted as an early indication of the reality principle, involving ego functions. A psychological dimension could then be added to our conception of the personality structure of the early hominids. Thus Hallowell came to suggest that for hominid evolution to have advanced beyond the protocultural level, a major ‘psychological transformation’ must also have occurred. The ecological development of our human forebears through the invention and use of technological devices, the normative orientation of human societies, involving regulations and moral precepts (like incest), the cultural transmission of a human system of communication; all these, Hallowell suggests, necessitated the existence of a self-concept, persistent in time. The ego permits adaptation at a new behavioural level. Consequently a capacity for self-awareness and self-identification must be assumed as psychological universals. In phylogenetic terms, he writes, ‘the evolutionary status of Homo sapiens implies common psychological potentialities. These would appear to be necessary for the functioning of notions of eschatology as for the manufacture of tools and other forms of cultural adaptation’ (1976:257). Thus Hallowell postulates both the development of self-awareness and of a ‘concept of self’ as necessary conditions for the functioning of a human society (1955:83).
Various points emerge from this perspective, and are worth noting. Firstly, the self is seen as a constant factor in the human personality structure, and intrinsic to the operation of human society and all situations of social interaction. Self and society, for Hallowell, are aspects of a single whole, and culture and personality cannot be postulated as completely independent variables.
Secondly, Hallowell suggests that neither human society nor human personality can be conceived in functional terms apart from systems of symbolic communication. Thus social existence was a necessary condition of the development of the self (or mind) in the individual. He quotes Dewey who had suggested (1917) that the mind was not ‘an antecedent or ready made thing’: it was a ‘formation not a datum’. Likewise Hallowell argues that the development of the human psychological structure (mind, self, personality) is ‘fundamentally dependent upon socially mediated experience in interaction with other persons’ (1953:355). Like both Goldman (1977) and Singer (1980), Hallowell sees self and society as co-existent, and dialectically inter-dependent.
Finally, although stressing the generic aspect of psychological structures, Hallowell also explored and stressed that the nature of the self was itself a ‘culturally certifiable variable’. As Hallowell emphasised:
The psychological field in which human behaviour takes place is always culturally constituted, in part, and human responses are never reducible to their entirety to stimuli derived from an objective or surrounding world of objects in the physical or geographical sense. (1955:84)
In this Hallowell was echoing the tenet of a modified Whorfian theory and Marx’s criticisms of Feuerbach’s contemplative materialism.
This led Hallowell to the concept of ‘behaviourial environment’, the culturally established locus of the self ‘structured in terms of a diversified world of objects other than the self’. All cultures, he suggested, provide the individual with a cognitive orientation, postulating a cosmos or world-view within which there is reason, order and meaning. In a series of illuminating essays on Ojibwa culture, which have both ethnographic and theoretical significance, Hallowell demonstrated that the concept of person for the Ojibwa is by no means synonymous with the Western conception, even less with the notion of human organism. Not content with offering a purely phenomenological analysis he argues with equal emphasis that an objective study of other cultures cannot be achieved by ‘projecting upon those cultures categorical abstractions derived from Western thought’. For the simple reason that Western classifications and terminology are steeped in a mechanistic and dualistic paradigm – a warning that many contemporary anthropologists have not heeded.
The world-view of the Ojibwa Indians, a group of nomadic hunters and fishers living east of Lake Winnipeg, implied a personalistic or cosmological conception of the universe. Instead of a dualistic paradigm, there is a ‘basic metaphysical unity in the ground of being’, and a personal rather than a mechanistic or impersonal theory of causation. Hallowell suggests that the European dichotomous categorisation of nature and the supernatural is inappropriate in trying to understand this world-view, while the suggestion of earlier anthropologists that the whole universe for the Ojibwa is animate or personalised is equally misleading. What typifies their mode of thinking is that they do not make any categorical or sharply defined differentiation between myth and reality, or between dreaming and the waking state; neither can any hard or fast line be drawn between humans and animals. This does not in the least imply that the Ojibwa are unable to make these distinctions, and thus confuse objectivity and subjectivity. A bear is an animal which unlike humans hibernates during the winter, but in specific circumstances it may be interpreted as a human sorcerer. Equally, although ‘there is no lack of discrimination between the experiences of the self when awake and when dreaming’ (1976:378) – and indeed Hallowell suggests that it is inconceivable that humans could have evolved without making this distinction – for the dream-conscious Ojibwa events that occur in dreams are interpreted as communications with the dream visitors Pawaganak. These are also known as ‘our grandfathers’, a collective term for what Hallowell describes as ‘other-than-human’ persons.
The world-view of the Ojibwa is thus fundamentally a religious one; the concept of soul or spirit being linked not only to the quality of life or animation, but allowing also for the possibility of metamorphosis. The Ojibwa recognise a category of living things, but the animate category does not exactly correspond to Western classifications, although most objects that Europeans would describe as inanimate are also described that way by the Ojibwa. Yet certain classes of objects, certain shells or stones, may under specific circumstances be considered animate, while such natural phenomema as thunder, sun and moon, and the four winds are thought of not only as animate by the Ojibwa, but are categorised as persons. To the Ojibwa human beings are only one class of persons, the others being, besides the aforementioned, the thunderbird (classified with the hawks), the ‘owners’ of various species of animals and plants, and the characters of their various myths. Collectively spoken of as ‘our grandfathers’, this class of other-than-human persons is communicated to through dreams, through ceremonies and through the vision trance undertaken by teenage boys. Although disease and illness is associated by the Ojibwa with moral transgressions, these other-than-human persons are seen essentially as supernaturals who share their power and knowledge with living humans. They are thus a source of blessing (Hallowell 1976:357–474).
Hallowell’s ethnographic account of the Ojibwa world-view and the behavioural environment of the self (which I have summarised above) indicates the limitations of imposing a dualistic paradigm...

Table of contents