The Constitution of Electoral Speech Law
eBook - ePub

The Constitution of Electoral Speech Law

The Supreme Court and Freedom of Expression in Campaigns and Elections

Brian K. Pinaire

Share book
  1. 368 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

The Constitution of Electoral Speech Law

The Supreme Court and Freedom of Expression in Campaigns and Elections

Brian K. Pinaire

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Bush v. Gore brought to the public's attention the significance of election law and the United States Supreme Court's role in structuring the rules that govern how campaigns and elections function in America. In this book, Brian K. Pinaire examines one expanding domain within this larger legal context: freedom of speech in the political process, or, what he terms, electoral speech law.

Specifically, Pinaire examines the Court's evolving conceptions of free speech in the electoral process and then traces the consequences of various debates and determinations from the post-World War II era to the present. In his analysis of the broad range of cases from this period, supplemented by four recent case study investigations, Pinaire explores competing visions of electoral expression in the marketplace of ideas, various methods for analyzing speech dilemmas, the multiple influences that shape the justices' notions of both the potential for and privileged status of electoral communication, and the ultimate implications of these Court rulings for American democracy.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is The Constitution of Electoral Speech Law an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access The Constitution of Electoral Speech Law by Brian K. Pinaire in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Law & Public Law. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2008
ISBN
9780804779609
Edition
1
Topic
Law
Subtopic
Public Law
Index
Law

PART ONE

Constitutional Elements

CHAPTER 1

Constituent Concepts

OUR ATTENTION in this chapter is directed toward those constituent concepts that figure most prominently in the constitution of electoral speech law: “electoral superintendence” and the “marketplace of ideas.” As we will see, “electoral superintendence” represents, for my purposes, the general supervisory capacity the U.S. Supreme Court has assumed in electoral process cases since about World War II, while the concept of a “marketplace of ideas” has developed (over approximately the same period of time) from Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes’s famous contemplation of the potential for “free trade in ideas” to serve as the vehicle for evaluating competing claims and ultimately realizing the social good in the realm of expression. We begin first with an exploration of the essence and evolution of “superintendence,” as this notion encapsulates the Court’s involvement in the organization of American politics.1

ELECTORAL SUPERINTENDENCE

While the justices may, at times, appear “confused, or indifferent, about what politics is for,”2 as one commentator has suggested, at least since the judicial construction of Baker v. Carr and the spawning of the “Reapportionment Revolution” in the early 1960s,3 the U.S. Supreme Court has assumed the role of electoral superintendent, a development that has consistently and increasingly involved the justices in the regulation of politics. Indeed, as election law scholars have stressed, judicial oversight has increased to a degree “unimaginable when the Supreme Court first entered the political thicket” in Baker.4 Before proceeding further then, a brief recap of the road leading here is appropriate. While the first three of the White Primary Cases (Nixon v. Herndon in 1927, Nixon v. Condon in 1932, and Grovey v. Townsend in 1935)5 are probably the most well known of the Court’s early twentieth-century interventions in the political process, what is in effect the theory—or a theory—for why the justices would superintend in such a fashion was not articulated as such until 1938, in United States v. Carolene Products Co.6

Sweet Carolene

Announcing a routine-enough assertion of the deference to be paid to legislation having a rational relationship to a professed concern for the health and well-being of the public and its markets, Carolene is, of course, most known for the significance of its fourth footnote: a signal, if you will, of the heightened scrutiny to be paid to particular, noncommercial, classes of legislation. As Chief Justice Harlan Fiske Stone suggested in this forecast, the operative scope for the presumption of constitutionality may be “narrower” when “legislation appears on its face to be within a specific prohibition of the Constitution, such as those of the first ten amendments, which are deemed equally specific when held to be embraced within the Fourteenth.”7
Following the Carolene invitation over the course of the next generation, the Court, in United States v. Classic,8 Smith v. Allwright,9 and Terry v. Adams,10 appeared to demonstrate its intention to “unclog” the “channels of political change,” as John Hart Ely put it—acting as a sort of “referee” for the political process.11 Election law scholars such as Samuel Issacharoff and Richard Pildes, informed by Ely’s work and looking to the White Primary Cases for evidence of prototypical problems, have applauded this mode for the Court and theorized that the justices should adopt a “structural” or “functional” approach to guide their review of political process cases,12 intervening “only when the ‘market,’” (in their case, the “political market”) was “systematically malfunctioning”—that is, essentially when the process is undeserving of trust because “the ins are choking off the channels of political change to ensure that they will stay in and the outs will stay out,”13 as Ely put it.
What this emphasis on “structure” or “function” would do for practical purposes, Issacharoff and Pildes contend, would be to present democratic politics as akin to a “robustly competitive market,” whose “vitality depends on both clear rules of engagement and on the ritual cleansing born of competition.”14 Only within a system of competitive party politics, in other words, can the “policy outcomes of the political process be responsive to the interests and views of citizens,” and thus they advocate a “theory of legal regulation of politics premised on a skeptical view of political lockups, akin to the ‘hard look’ given to managerial self-protection in the corporate setting.”15
Critics of this approach, such as Richard Hasen, find it to be a “shallow theory” that “says nothing about how the courts should intervene in the face of political market failure.” 16 For Hasen, the Court should focus instead on substantive equality principles, working to distinguish between “core political equality rights,” such as not discriminating against individuals on the basis of race, and “contested political equality rights,” such as the right espoused by some that minorities should have the right to generally proportional representation in legislatures, for example. Hasen admits that “most core rights are socially constructed,” meaning that they are the product of social consensus, but his recommendation is that when the Court intervenes regarding contested political equality rights, it should craft a “murky (or vague) political rule,” whereas intervention in cases implicating core political equality rights calls for the use of “bright-line rules.” 17 But he contends that this more articulate focus clarifies “for both members of the Court and the public at large what normative value judgments the Court is making,” meaning, too, that “the Court is more likely to consider whether the case’s holding might have unintended consequences on other political issues,” an approach he finds to be “more honest than a focus on process, because the Court will not always provide process protection absent a threat to a substantive equality principle recognized by a Court majority.”18

“Platonic Guardianship”

But critics of intervention—for any reason and however cabined by theoretical partitions—contend that such authority vested in the Court necessarily envisions the justices as “Platonic Guardians” summoned for their wisdom in the arrangements of political life and operations.19 Beyond this sort of normative resistance, however—rooted as it typically is in the perception that the Court’s involvement is somehow un- or antidemocratic—a separate argument for resisting the lure of Carolene would point to the various and prominent examples of electoral reform that successfully emerged without courts (i.e., through the political process), such as the institution of the Australian “secret ballot” system; the direct primary; the direct election of senators; various campaign finance regulations; term limits; and the extension of the franchise to blacks, women, those over age eighteen, and recently, in some states, to ex-felons who have completed their sentences—a class which has actually been stymied in its efforts to regain voting rights through the courts,20 and which has, instead, relied on unequivocal public support for the eventual return of the franchise in the course of political mobilization campaigns, grassroots lobbying of state legislatures, and appeals to state executives .21
But the concept of electoral superintendence invites us as well to consider the theoretical implications and consequences of the phenomenon that Richard Pildes has recently referred to as the “constitutionalization of democratic politics”22—or the tendency over the last generation for “issues concerning the design of democratic institutions and the central processes of democracy” to “increasingly become questions of constitutional law throughout the world.”23 Regarding this “constitutionalization,” Pildes explains that “the contours of fair political representation and political equality,” the constitution of “group identities in the design of democratic institutions,” and the campaign voices and political participation of corporations, interest groups, unions, and parties, “are now substantially constrained by constitutional law.”24 Indeed, even in the rejection of particular claims, he continues, “constitutional law has been credibly invoked and has generated divided Court decisions over other central aspects of elections, governance, and politics,” such as the “role of third parties in American politics, the place of write-in candidacies, the structure of campaign debates, and the role of partisanship in the design of election districts.”25
Thus, with the “stakes for the practice of democracy, and the role of constitutional law” as “dramatic” as they are,26 and with “hardly any issue concerning the institutions of governance or the conduct of elections . . . outside the reach of contemporary constitutional law,”27 Pildes contends that in the coming years, constitutional law will be “shaped, in part, by the collision of these two developments: a Supreme Court increasingly constitutionalizing the structures of democracy, and political circumstances that spawn recurring challenges to existing democratic structures.”28 In this context then, the Supreme Court “remains well entrenched in the political thicket and is likely to remain there.”29
As we will see in the next section, a concept of equal constituent significance has evolved within the Court’s free speech jurisprudence. While more of an interpretive device than a historical trend or tendency, the “marketplace of ideas” warrants attention in understanding the constitution of this domain because it presents the framework, or design, which effectively absorbs and animates the characteristics drawn from the “superintendent” construct. Next we will review the marketplace concept in terms of its development, doctrinal establishment, discontents, and ultimate dominion in free speech law.

THE “MARKETPLACE OF IDEAS”

An enormous literature contemplating its historical origins, philosophical justifications, political values, contemporary applications, and...

Table of contents