Science and the Life-World
eBook - ePub

Science and the Life-World

Essays on Husserl's Crisis of European Sciences

David Hyder, Hans-Jörg Rheinberger, David Hyder, Hans-Jörg Rheinberger

Share book
  1. 288 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Science and the Life-World

Essays on Husserl's Crisis of European Sciences

David Hyder, Hans-Jörg Rheinberger, David Hyder, Hans-Jörg Rheinberger

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This book is a collection of essays on Husserl's Crisis of European Sciences by leading philosophers of science and scholars of Husserl. Published and ignored under the Nazi dictatorship, Husserl's last work has never received the attention its author's prominence demands. In the Crisis, Husserl considers the gap that has grown between the "life-world" of everyday human experience and the world of mathematical science. He argues that the two have become disconnected because we misunderstand our own scientific past—we confuse mathematical idealities with concrete reality and thereby undermine the validity of our immediate experience. The philosopher's foundational work in the theory of intentionality is relevant to contemporary discussions of qualia, naive science, and the fact-value distinction. The scholars included in this volume consider Husserl's diagnosis of this "crisis" and his proposed solution. Topics addressed include Husserl's late philosophy, the relation between scientific and everyday objects and "worlds, " the history of Greek and Galilean science, the philosophy of history, and Husserl's influence on Foucault.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Science and the Life-World an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Science and the Life-World by David Hyder, Hans-Jörg Rheinberger, David Hyder, Hans-Jörg Rheinberger in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Filosofia & Fenomenologia in filosofia. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2009
ISBN
9780804772945

§ 1

Science, Intentionality, and Historical Background

David Woodruff Smith

Husserl’s Philosophy of Science

When we think of philosophy of science, we think of Ernst Mach, Rudolf Carnap, Carl Hempel, Ernest Nagel, W. V. Quine, Thomas Kuhn, Patrick Suppes, and others. We do not at first think of Edmund Husserl, noted for launching phenomenology as the reflective, first-person science of consciousness—in contrast with physics taken as the hypotheticodeductive, third-person science of nature at its most basic level. Yet Husserl explicitly addressed many issues in the foundations of mathematics, logic, and science at a time when the philosophy of science was taking shape around twentieth-century mathematical physics and mathematical logic. The term of art in Husserl’s day and milieu was not philosophy of science, but theory of science, or Wissenschaftslehre. In his lifetime Husserl had direct contact with Weierstrass, Kronecker, Cantor, Frege, Hilbert, Schlick, and Carnap, and his work was known to Tarski and Gödel. That is to say, Husserl was hardly out of the loop of thinkers then working on the foundations of mathematics, logic, and science. Husserl was not of course an architect of relativity theory, non-Euclidian geometry, number theory, set theory, or quantifier logic. But he was ever expanding a wide-ranging philosophy that addressed all these “sciences” (in the wide sense of the term then in vogue) as well as psychology and phenomenology.
Husserl’s first book was published in 1891 as Philosophie der Arithmetik. Partly due to Frege’s (understandable) misreading, that book was viewed as a psychologistic reduction of numbers to merely psychological activities of grouping and counting. A more careful and subtle study finds Husserl carrying out an analysis of the concepts of number and totality, which intentionally represent numbers and totalities. (This sympathetic reading of Husserl’s first book is outlined by Dallas Willard in his introduction to his English translation of Husserl’s book, Philosophy of Arithmetic; see in particular pp. xxi–xxix.) In terms of Husserl’s mature thought, he was aiming at an analysis of the sense (Sinn) of number and the coordinate essence (Wesen) of number, where a sense is an ideal intentional content and an essence is an ideal property. But these notions Husserl developed only later in his full theory of intentionality and its attendant ontology.
Husserl’s first mature work was the Logical Investigations, first published in 1900–1901 in three volumes spanning some 1,000 pages. In that work Husserl developed a unified philosophical system of logic, semantics, ontology, phenomenology, and epistemology. As Husserl explained in the opening volume, titled “Prolegomena to Pure Logic,” that system was inspired in good measure by Bernard Bolzano’s 1837 groundbreaking opus Theory of Science (Wissenschaftslehre) (1972). Accordingly, Husserl was seeking inter alia a basic account of the logical and epistemological structure of any science. A crucial part of the Investigations was Husserl’s detailed theory of intentionality, the foundation of phenomenology, which was followed by an extended analysis of evidence or “intuition” (Anschauung ) in the theory of knowledge, starting with sense perception. Issues of logic, ontology, intentionality theory, and epistemology thus frame the background for Husserl’s subsequent programmatic presentation of the discipline of phenomenology in Ideas I (1913).
Empirical science, from physics to psychology, was prominent in the horizon of Husserl’s phenomenology (even in his technical sense of horizon ). Phenomenology was to be sharply distinguished from empirical psychology, which would include today’s cognitive science, because phenomenology seeks ideal structures of meaning (Sinn) in the content of experience, whereas empirical psychology seeks contingent patterns of mental activity and its causes, even as in today’s functionalist models in cognitive science and cognitive neuroscience. Physics too lies beyond the scope of phenomenology because phenomenology (in one range of analysis) is to bracket the existence and the essence of physical nature (even, we note today, the essence of the neural activities on which our consciousness depends) in order precisely to shift our attention to the way we experience things in nature. Thus we shift our attention away from the objects of our consciousness (in everyday perception or indeed in the abstract thinking we might practice in doing mathematical physics), and we turn instead to our own forms of experience, and therewith to their contents or meanings. Armed with phenomenological analyses of perception, judgment, and so forth, we will however return to an analysis of the structure of knowledge, ranging from our familiar knowledge of everyday affairs to our collective scientific knowledge, as in mathematical physics. That is where the Logical Investigations ends: poised for more specific analyses of formations of knowledge, say, in the natural sciences. As we consider below, philosophy of science followed out such an analysis not least in the work of Rudolf Carnap, in ways surprisingly congenial to Husserl’s intentionality based “theory of science.” Keep in mind that Husserl’s conception of intentionality and phenomenology is framed by his wider theory of science, überhaupt.
Husserl’s last wave of work, during the period 1935–38, was collected in the posthumous book called The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology. The intellectual and spiritual crisis Husserl saw resides in the way in which mathematical physics has lost touch with everyday human experience. Galileo’s vision of science began the ideal of a “mathematization” of nature, which in the early twentieth century produced first general relativity theory and then quantum theory. As widely discussed, both relativity theory and quantum theory seem incompatible with our Lebenswelt (life-world) experience and our everyday knowledge of the world around us—even though science begins with everyday perceptual observation and proceeds with work in the laboratory, at the computer screen, and so forth. Husserl addressed this problem concerning the foundations of twentieth-century physics in a “transcendental” critique of mathematical physics.
As Husserl’s analysis of science unfolded from his early work in the Logical Investigations to his late work in the Crisis, we find a strong tension. The early vision is full of hope for the model of any science as a formal, ideally mathematical theory of a given domain supported by evident experience or intuition of an appropriate type. But the late vision finds a crisis, as mathematical physics no longer seems tied to human experience, and we can no longer really understand what mathematical physics—Einsteinian physics in particular—says about the world around us.
Our present task is to explore certain issues in a Husserlian philosophy of science, looking to its foundation in a Husserlian theory of intentionality and attendant ontology. We will be pressing three themes further than Husserl did. The first theme is the indexical structure of perception (seeing “this such-and-such”), which is the form of experience that serves as the evidential base of any empirical science. The second theme is the “global” indexicality of our concepts of things in nature (such as the concept tree), concepts that by their very meaning represent things in our surrounding world, or Umwelt. The third theme is the ontological dependence of our theories, even in mathematical physics, on historical human intentional activities.
The results of this exploration allow a new view of the formal and material aspects of science, which we shall bring into relief by drawing on Michael Friedman’s Kantian-Carnapian-Kuhnian account of science.

Husserl’s Unified Theory: A Theory of Theory, Essence, Meaning, Part/Whole, Intentionality, Evidence—and Thus Empirical Science

Husserl’s Logical Investigations (1900–1901) unfolds a unified system of logic, ontology, phenomenology, and epistemology: defining a framework within which we may outline a Husserlian philosophy of science. The Investigations includes seven interrelated studies. The Prolegomena outlines a theory of “pure logic,” which prefigures the development of semantics or metalogic by Carnap, Tarski, and others. Investigation I offers a theory of linguistic expression, meaning, and reference (with some similarity to Frege’s). Investigation II offers a theory of universals, or “ideal species” or essences (Wesen), combining elements of the Platonic and Aristotelian views of universals. Investigation III is a theory of part and whole, including the notion of “moment,” or dependent part. Investigation IV applies that part/whole ontology to ideal meanings in a theory of “grammar.” Investigation V is a long presentation of Husserl’s groundbreaking theory of intentionality, carefully distinguishing act, content, and object of consciousness. That theory of intentionality is the foundation of Husserl’s conception of phenomenology. Finally, Investigation VI develops a phenomenological theory of knowledge, featuring the character of evidence in intuition, including visual perception. What is remarkable, and too little appreciated, is the tightly knit unity of Husserl’s system. In my view Husserl joins Aristotle and Kant among the most systematic of philosophers.1
Looking to philosophy of science, I should like to emphasize three parts of Husserl’s system: his theory of theories, his theory of intentionality, and his theory of evidence. Husserl’s system as a whole is a wide-ranging theory that includes a theory of what it is to be a theory. That is, Husserl’s theory of almost everything includes a metatheory that applies to the overall theory. And the metatheory is itself a part of the theory, in the sense explicated in Husserl’s theory of parts/wholes. (How does this play today in light of the results in metalogic that followed in Husserl’s wake?)
Husserl’s theory of theory (Prolegomena) holds that a theory is a system of propositions, which are ideal meanings (compare Bolzano’s notion of Satz an sich and Frege’s notion of Sinn or Gedanke). A deductive theory includes deductive consequences of propositions in the theory; an inductive theory includes propositions made probable (“motivated”) by other propositions in the theory. Each theory forms a semantically coherent group of propositions that characterize a domain, or field of knowledge. The propositions in a theory develop “laws of essence” about the domain of the theory, that is, they specify the essence (Wesen), or properties, of objects in that domain. All this should sound familiar to us today. But notice that the elements in a theory are propositions, ideal propositional meanings (Sinne), rather than sentences in a language (as subsequent logicians, such as Carnap, Quine, and others, assume). And bear in mind that in Husserl’s mature ontology, essences and meanings are categorially distinct. Meanings are ideal intentional contents that semantically represent objects and their properties or essences. As an approximation, essences are like Aristotelian universals, while meanings are like Fregean Sinne.
If a theory is a system of propositions, what kind of entities are propositions for Husserl? Propositions are meanings that are propositional in form (expressible by a complete declarative sentence). But meanings are, for Husserl, ideal contents of intentional acts of consciousness. In the Investigations, Husserl identified ideal meanings with ideal species of intentional acts: A meaning is the ideal species of an experience of thinking or seeing or whatever. So a proposition is the ideal species or type of thinking that such-and-such is the case. By the time Husserl wrote Ideas I, however, he had come to hold instead that meanings are their own kind of ideal entities: not species of intentional act, but meanings sui generis, like Fregean Sinne, if you will.
What makes a theory true, for Husserl, is its correctly representing the essence of objects in its domain. But truth is distinct from evidence. What makes a theory count as knowledge of its domain is the evidence supporting it. In Husserl’s phenomenological theory of knowledge (Investigation VI), evidence consists in the phenomenological character of “evidence” (Evidenz) or “intuitive fullness” or “fulfillment.” An act of intuition (Anschauung) is an intentional act of consciousness that has the character of intuitiveness, that is, intuitive fullness or evidentness. When I see that red ball, part of the way the object is experienced is with a character of sensory evidence. I do not merely think of a red ball, I see—or, some insist, seem to see—a red ball. If I then judge visually that it is a red ball, my judgment has a meaning supported by the character of intuitive evidence in my act of so judging.
Husserl distinguishes some three types of intuition. Sensory or empirical intuition is found in sensory perception. Essential intuition (Wesenschau ) consists in coming to “see” something about an essence or ideal species of object, for instance, that a triangle has angles totaling 180 degrees, coming to see this perhaps through deduction or through eidetic variation. Transcendental phenomenological intuition consists in grasping the structure of an experience as lived, including its ideal intentional content or meaning, perhaps through bracketing or epoché. The techniques for achieving these types of intuition are very different, and beyond the scope of our discussion. I wish only to stress that there are different types of evident or intuitive experience or judgment, achieved in different ways.
A distinguishing feature of Husserl’s theory of theory, and thus of knowledge, including science, is his view that a theory is a form of intentionality, a system of propositions that serve as contents of judgments about a given domain of objects. In Formal and Transcendental Logic (1929), Husserl treats formal logic, where a theory is a formal or symbolic deductive system, as requiring a foundation in transcendental logic, by which Husserl means formal logic grounded in intentionality. As we might say today, a formal theory (a system of symbols, rules of inference, axiomatic sentences) is accompanied by a semantics, a system of assignments of meanings to relevant expressions in the formal theory. But meanings, for Husserl, are ideal contents of intentional acts of thought, perception, and so forth. Thus we find the later Husserl amplifying the early Husserl of the Logical Investigations. Husserl’s theory of scientific knowledge flows from this intentionalist account of a theory supported by appropriate evidence in perceptual experience.
In Husserl’s theory of knowledge, we may say that empirical knowledge consists in forming empirical judgments with appropriate sensory intuitive evidence. As Quine would say, empirical knowledge begins with observation, with sensory perception of objects. Husserl would specify then that an observation consists in a perceptual judgment, an intentional act with a certain propositional content and a certain character of sensory evidence.
When does empirical knowledge develop into what we call a science like physics? In Husserl’s scheme, a science like physics is an accumulation of empirical knowledge produced by a community of intentional subjects building on the work of others. A scientific theory, we may say, is thus a theory—a system of propositions (ideal meanings) about a domain of objects—that is supported by evidence (intuitive fulfillment) in observations (perceptual experiences) and put forth in judgments performed by individuals working collectively in the relevant scientific community.
In the Crisis (1935–38), drawing on results as early as Ideas II (1912), Husserl characterized what he called the sedimentation of knowledge. Traditional beliefs are sedimented propositions that we typically share while having little if any explicit awareness of these belief-contents. These may be called background beliefs. But mathematical knowledge too is sedimented. Husserl focuses on Euclidian geometry, the system of propositions we have inherited and developed since Euclid. After Galileo, Husserl emphasizes, modern European science developed a vision of the mathematization of nature. That is, Husserl argues at length, physics after Newton came to lay down laws of nature—laws of motion and gravity—that are expressed in mathematical language, starting with the calculus. The calculus itself rests on Cartesian analytic...

Table of contents