Person-Centred Counselling
eBook - ePub

Person-Centred Counselling

An Experiential Approach

David L Rennie

Share book
  1. 160 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Person-Centred Counselling

An Experiential Approach

David L Rennie

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

`This book offers a truly engaging "read". The writing style is good and it gives the reader a wide range of perspectives, from the meta-theoretical to the concrete practical experience of clients and counsellors.... David Rennie?s book serves to continue the development as well as the exposition of the person-centred approach to counselling? - British Journal of Guidance and Counselling

`This is a very good book... clearly within the humanistic/experiential tradition... It seems to me to be very important that this kind of research continues - it is the raw data of the counselling profession? - Person-Centred Practice

This book contains powerful new ideas about person-centred theory and practice. Supported by intensive qualitative research into the client?s experience of counselling, the book highlights the significance and pervasiveness of reflexivity - defined as self-awareness and agency within that self-awareness - and explores surprising ways in which clients contribute reflexively to the counselling process.

Vivid examples highlight activities, show the therapy in action and illustrate how counsellors can use their own experiences creatively to facilitate their attunement to themselves, their clients and their relationships with them. The theoretical framework covers matters such as the use of images and metaphor, counsellor transparency and the assistance of clients? agency. Emphasis is placed on the client/counsellor relationship through such crucial areas as the working alliance, power dynamics and metacommunication.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Person-Centred Counselling an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Person-Centred Counselling by David L Rennie in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Psychology & History & Theory in Psychology. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
1998
ISBN
9781446235393
Edition
1

1

Situating the Approach


The counselling described in this book is in keeping with those that share Carl Rogers’s deep interest in working within the client’s frame of reference but do not subscribe strictly to Rogerian theory and practice. It thus joins the broad category of person-centred and experiential counselling and psychotherapy approaches described by Lietaer as:
the classic Rogerians; the client-centered therapists who are in favour of some form of integration or even eclectism; the Gendlians, for whom the whole focusing approach is a precious way of working; the client-centered therapists who look at the therapy process in information-processing terms; the client-centered therapists for whom the interpersonal aspect, the here-and-now of interaction between the client and therapist is their central focus, and maybe some other suborientations or combinations of them. (1989, p. 17)
Like the orthodox or, as Shlien (1970) terms it, the ‘literal’ person-centred approach, the present one places its main emphasis on the client’s experience, choice and personal freedom and makes following the client’s lead a priority. It both differs from the literal approach in some respects and adds to it. Rather than traditional Rogerian theory, it is organized around the concept of reflexivity, which I have defined as self-awareness and agency within that self-awareness (Rennie, 1992, 1997).1 Moreover, as much emphasis is placed on the counsellor’s reflexivity as on the client’s, which brings the counsellor’s process into the picture equally with the client’s. A high value is placed on the counsellor’s demystification of his or her presence in the counselling transaction through the activity of being open about what he or she is up to, so long as doing so does not detract from the focus on the client. In this regard, it contributes to the emphasis being placed in many quarters on counsellor transparency. The approach also draws upon metacommunication as practised in most forms of interpersonal therapy, while going beyond the conceptualization and application of metacommunication as used in that form of therapy. Finally, the approach entails counsellor directiveness of the client’s processing of experience when it seems warranted by both client and counsellor.
It is the counsellor’s guidance of the client’s processing of experience that gives rise to the book’s subtitle: An Experiential Approach. Yet, as will be seen, the process work outlined is nontechnical. It takes the form either of directing clients’ attention to the cognitive activity in which they appear to be currently engaged or of suggesting that they might engage in a particular process. This kind of process work is integral to the flow of the client’s experience and fits smoothly into the emphasis on empathic responding characteristic of the literal approach. At the same time, it constitutes a bridge between that mode of responding and the more technical experiential approaches, if the counsellor is so inclined.
In terms of Lietaer’s classification, then, the implicit assumptions and practices involved in the approach position it between the literal person-centred approach and therapies characterized by, as Rice (1974) succinctly put it, the therapist being directive in terms of the client’s process and non-directive regarding content. These therapies include Gendlin’s experiential therapy (Gendlin, 1981, 1996), the process-experiential approach developed by Rice and Greenberg (Greenberg, 1984; Greenberg, Rice and Elliott, 1993; Rice and Saperia, 1984) and the perceptual-processing approach advanced by Toukmanian (1986, 1990, 1992). There are, of course, many differences that separate these various ‘directive’ approaches. Gendlin’s is holistic whereas the process-experiential and perceptual-processing approaches draw upon information-processing theory and are more reductionistic. In this respect, the current approach is more in keeping with Gendlin’s holism. The middle ground occupied by the approach is thus compatible with the views of thinkers and practitioners such as Mearns (1994; Mearns and Thorne, 1988), Thorne (1989; Mearns and Thorne, 1988), Lietaer (1984), Sachse (1989), Liejssen (1990),2 Holdstock (1996) and O’Hara (1984), among others.
In the remainder of this introductory chapter, I consider these points more fully. I begin with the quality of reflexivity. Following that, I address how this approach and the theory supporting it compare with the others in terms of self-actualization, the necessity and sufficiency of the core conditions, experience and its leading edge, and holism.

Reflexivity and its embodiment

The most significant quality of ‘human beingness’ is our ability to think about ourselves, to think about our thinking, to feel about our feelings, to treat ourselves as objects of our attention and to use what we find there as a point of departure in deciding what to do next. This is reflexivity as I understand it. Many thinkers attach significance to reflexivity in terms of its implications for the concept of self but its importance is much broader; reflexivity is a major feature of consciousness and is integral to action. I was led to its pervasiveness after interviewing clients about their moment-to-moment experience of counselling/therapy (e.g. Rennie, 1984, 1990, 1992, 1994a, 1996). By virtue of reflexivity we can intervene into ourselves, make decisions, change ourselves. This is not to say that this capacity is total. The evidence for unconscious determination of actions, for societal constraints on change and for resistance to change is indisputable. But these considerations should not be allowed to diminish the centrality of reflexivity in our experience. We move in and out of streams of thought, just as we move into and out of various bodily activities associated with them. At one moment, we are ‘in’ a stream of thought; we are not aware that we are – we just ‘are’ (see Searle, 1983). The next moment or hour, as the case may be, the stream ceases, enabling us to be aware that we were in the stream. In that moment of awareness, we may either undeliberatively think of something else and go along with that thought, or deliberate on what to attend to next and enter the stream resulting from that decision, thus the repeating cycle. This is consciousness – an ongoing alternation of non-reflexive and reflexive thought.
Thinking is activity. We know this because when someone asks us what we are doing when we are immersed in thought, it is perfectly natural and correct to reply, ‘I’m thinking’. For this and other reasons given in Chapter 2, I make no attempt to separate reflexivity and agency. They are part of each other in that agency is purposive activity emanating from reflexive activity and returning to it (Rennie, 1997).
There are reasons for being suspicious of reflexivity, especially if one is a client or a counsellor helping a client. In the act of attending to ourselves, we can detach from ourselves, as when we distance ourselves from painful feelings while allowing ourselves to be aware of what the feelings are about. Still we may not distance thought from our experience in this way. It is possible to draw our attention to our feelings as well as to our thoughts. Furthermore, although we are not capable of thinking about what we are thinking in precisely the same instant, we are capable of being aware of what we are feeling in a given instant. The reason the first is true is that we cannot think and be aware of that thinking simultaneously. Instead, either we think without being aware of it, or we think about what we just thought or should next think about; we cannot catch in action the ‘I’ that instigates activity. Interestingly the same does not seem to be true of feeling, at least not to the same extent. Somehow, feeling is ‘there’ – an ongoing presence – ready for scanning and symbolization. Feeling seems to be in a different place than our thoughts; it seems to be in our bodies.
Some philosophers are sceptical of reflexivity precisely because of its implicit dualism. This was true of Dewey who, in his attempt to overcome philosophical problems raised by dualism, combined Darwinism with the Romantic idea of growth and created a form of monistic naturalism in which human functioning (including thinking) is action in the service of adaptation and growth (Rennie, 1998). Dewey had a tacit but strong influence on Rogers (Van Belle, 1980) and the vestiges of this influence can be seen in many of his followers as well. Rogers and the literalists (e.g. Bozarth, 1984, 1990a; Bozarth and Brodley, 1986; Patterson, 1990; Shlien, 1996) appear to mistrust reflexivity, instead placing more trust in a non-reflexive union of feeling and action. This is not to say that they have discounted reflexivity totally. Influenced by Gendlin, particularly, Rogers realized increasingly that we have a felt-sense to which we can attend and that doing so is an important step towards the productive processing of experience. For Rogers, however, full functioning is non-reflexive: a union of feeling and thought and behaviour. Thus, Rogers never put much stock in the concept of the ego (Van Belle, 1980). Instead, very much like Dewey, his ontology is closer to a monistic processing of experience.3
Gendlin’s experiential approach to therapy, on the other hand, engages reflexivity. Gendlin maintains that embodied meaning as a felt-sense is a direct referent (e.g. Gendlin, 1962) or, more recently, an exact form (Gendlin, 1990) available for symbolization (the claim that it is thus analogous to a Husserlian ‘essence’ is debatable; cf. Gendlin, 1978/1979, 1990; Sass, 1988; see also Greenberg, Rice and Elliott, 1993). Thus, we can and should direct our attention to our felt-sense. This is a prescription of active reflexivity and is explicitly dualistic, for which Gendlin has been unfairly criticized (Leijssen, 1990; Wexler, 1974). There is a difference between subject–object and mind–body dualism (with the latter being exemplified by Descartes’s characterization of mind and body as separate substances). As Gendlin is well aware, contemporary philosophical thought is moving in the direction of characterizing human beingness as non-reductive, incarnated embodiment and thus disputes substance dualism (e.g. Merleau-Ponty, 1962; for an Anglo-American perspective, see Margolis, 1986, 1987). Reflexivity is but another aspect of that same incarnated embodiment, in that people have the ability to look at themselves as ‘objects’. Hence, there is nothing special about reflexivity. It is simply the most wonderful quality of being human (Donald, 1991; May, 1958a).4,5
In contrast, the process-experiential and perceptual-processing therapists are midway between the literal Rogerians and the Gendlians in terms of the recognition and application of reflexivity. For example, especially in their recent work that emphasizes the importance of emotion in therapeutic change (e.g. Greenberg, Rice and Elliott, 1993), the process-experiential therapists employ the Gendlian focusing technique when clients have difficulty making contact with their emotions. Thus, focusing is used as a means to the end of contacting (hypothesized) emotion schemes so that a given task (such as resolving a conflict split, dealing with unfinished business, resolving a problematic reaction to a past event, and so on) can proceed.

Reflexivity and silent activity

In the reflexive moment we are in a position to choose what to do next, and how. When engaged in discourse, in what seems like a rapid series of feedback loops, we sense the possible impact – on the other person and on ourselves – of expressing a thought or feeling. We are guided by this sense in deciding whether or not to express an inner experience at all, and, if proceeding, in managing how much of it we express and how we go about expressing it. This monitoring is done feelingly and seemingly almost instantaneously but is reflexive all the same.
In the counselling situation, such self-monitoring goes on in clients as much as in counsellors, of course. The result is a complex and dynamic situation in which the conscious goings-on between the counsellor and client variously occur on either one or two levels, depending on whether each person is conversing non-reflexively or reflexively. Non-reflexive talk is simply the talk itself, within which those involved in discussion are not deliberating on what they are saying but rather are just saying it in expression of an intention in the process of fulfilment. Reflexive talk, on the other hand, involves thoughts and feelings between utterances in the way described.
Accordingly, in the present approach, great significance is attached to silent activity. Rogers and his literalist followers appear to recognize such activity implicitly but, seemingly because of their tacitly monistic ontology, do not accord it the attention it deserves. In the same vein, with the exception of the work by J.C. Watson (e.g. Watson, 1997; Watson and Greenberg, 1994; Watson and Rennie, 1994), the members of the process-experiential group do not make much of such covert, conscious control because of their interest in stimulating the client’s activation and expression of non-reflexive cognitive/affective schemes. Toukmanian addresses tacitly the significance of covert experience through her valuing of controlled as compared with automatic perceptual processing, with the former having to do with reflexivity. In contrast, Gendlin recognizes covert experience explicitly when he encourages clients to work silently when focusing. Gendlin pays comparatively less attention to the client’s silent experience of the therapist and of the therapy relationship, however. The approach put forward by Mearns (1994) is closest to the present one in recognizing and attempting to work productively with the full implications of silent activity.

Self-actualization and the necessity and sufficiency of the core conditions

Rogers and the literalists hold that all organisms have an actualizing tendency. The emphasis is on growth, optimal conditions for it, and individualism. As part of his most thorough theoretical statement, Rogers wrote:
It should be noted that this basic actualizing tendency is the only motive which is postulated in this theoretical system. It should also be noted that it is the organism as a whole, and only the organism as a whole, which exhibits this tendency. There are no homunculi, no other sources of energy or action in the system. The self, for example, is an important construct in our theory, but the self does not ‘do’ anything. It is only one expression of the general tendency of the organism to behave in those ways which maintain and enhance the self.6 (1959, p. 196)
In this same work, Rogers (1959) distinguishes between actualization of the organism and actualization of the self. Self-actualization may or may not be congruent with actualization of the organism, depending on the compatibility of organismic and societal influences on self-development. Thus, some social conditions are more conducive to growth than others. In the interests of adaptation and in response to conditional regard, individuals comply and identify with social admonitions in order to reduce conflict with the social environment. This reduction in conflict is achieved at the expense of inducing conflict with organismic experiencing, however. The result is incongruence (see Ford, 1991). In order to achieve congruence, it is necessary for individuals to encounter the antidote to conditional regard so that they can safely contact and identify with their suppressed organismic promptings. In his famous statement, Rogers (1957) proposes that six conditions, highlighted by the therapist’s three attitudes of empathy, unconditional positive regard and congruence, are both necessary and sufficient as conditions for positive therapeutic change in that they determine the client’s establishment of congruence with organismic experiencing.
Rogers’s and the literalists’ belief in self-actualization as defined appears to be the source of their respect for the uniqueness of the individual. It is also the origin of their belief that individuals can change themselves given the right conditions. Moreover, inherent in the concept of self-actualization is the belief that the growth impetus is intrinsically towards goodness. Hence, this theory is profoundly Romantic and even mystical, much as Dewey’s belief in growth is seen by some as mystical (Murphy, 1951; Thayer, 1968).
I have further difficulty with the theory of self-actualization because it fails to account for a great deal of what we know about people, particularly in terms of their negative aspects. As Land (1996) remarks, it is not easy to reconcile the concept of inherent, organismic goodness with the existence of so much evil in the world. For Land, support for the notion of organismic actualization comes from faith more than evidence (see also O’Hara, 1995; Wood, 1996).
Alternatives to the concept of organismic evaluation and self-actualization have been proposed by experientially inclined therapists as well as by existential ones. Gendlin (1974) suggests that the felt-sense should be substituted for the organismic valuing process. This suggestion is an improvement in that it addresses experience that is immediate and is not burdened with the mysticism surrounding organismic evaluation. Butler and Rice (1963) propose that there are three main classes of drives (maintenance, emergency and pain, and developmental) and two levels of activation (chronic and acute). This formulation encompasses the complexity of motivation more fully than does the singular concept of organismic actualizatio...

Table of contents