Mathematical Physics
eBook - ePub

Mathematical Physics

Robert Geroch

Compartir libro
  1. English
  2. ePUB (apto para móviles)
  3. Disponible en iOS y Android
eBook - ePub

Mathematical Physics

Robert Geroch

Detalles del libro
Vista previa del libro
Índice
Citas

Información del libro

Mathematical Physics is an introduction to such basic mathematical structures as groups, vector spaces, topological spaces, measure spaces, and Hilbert space. Geroch uses category theory to emphasize both the interrelationships among different structures and the unity of mathematics. Perhaps the most valuable feature of the book is the illuminating intuitive discussion of the "whys" of proofs and of axioms and definitions. This book, based on Geroch's University of Chicago course, will be especially helpful to those working in theoretical physics, including such areas as relativity, particle physics, and astrophysics.

Preguntas frecuentes

¿Cómo cancelo mi suscripción?
Simplemente, dirígete a la sección ajustes de la cuenta y haz clic en «Cancelar suscripción». Así de sencillo. Después de cancelar tu suscripción, esta permanecerá activa el tiempo restante que hayas pagado. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Cómo descargo los libros?
Por el momento, todos nuestros libros ePub adaptables a dispositivos móviles se pueden descargar a través de la aplicación. La mayor parte de nuestros PDF también se puede descargar y ya estamos trabajando para que el resto también sea descargable. Obtén más información aquí.
¿En qué se diferencian los planes de precios?
Ambos planes te permiten acceder por completo a la biblioteca y a todas las funciones de Perlego. Las únicas diferencias son el precio y el período de suscripción: con el plan anual ahorrarás en torno a un 30 % en comparación con 12 meses de un plan mensual.
¿Qué es Perlego?
Somos un servicio de suscripción de libros de texto en línea que te permite acceder a toda una biblioteca en línea por menos de lo que cuesta un libro al mes. Con más de un millón de libros sobre más de 1000 categorías, ¡tenemos todo lo que necesitas! Obtén más información aquí.
¿Perlego ofrece la función de texto a voz?
Busca el símbolo de lectura en voz alta en tu próximo libro para ver si puedes escucharlo. La herramienta de lectura en voz alta lee el texto en voz alta por ti, resaltando el texto a medida que se lee. Puedes pausarla, acelerarla y ralentizarla. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Es Mathematical Physics un PDF/ePUB en línea?
Sí, puedes acceder a Mathematical Physics de Robert Geroch en formato PDF o ePUB, así como a otros libros populares de Mathematik y Mathematik Allgemein. Tenemos más de un millón de libros disponibles en nuestro catálogo para que explores.

Información

Año
2015
ISBN
9780226223063
Categoría
Mathematik
1
Introduction
One sometimes hears expressed the view that some sort of uncertainty principle operates in the interaction between mathematics and physics: the greater the mathematical care used to formulate a concept, the less the physical insight to be gained from that formulation. It is not difficult to imagine how such a viewpoint could come to be popular. It is often the case that the essential physical ideas of a discussion are smothered by mathematics through excessive definitions, concern over irrelevant generality, etc. Nonetheless, one can make a case that mathematics as mathematics, if used thoughtfully, is almost always useful—and occasionally essential—to progress in theoretical physics.
What one often tries to do in mathematics is to isolate some given structure for concentrated, individual study: what constructions, what results, what definitions, what relationships are available in the presence of a certain mathematical structure—and only that structure? But this is exactly the sort of thing that can be useful in physics, for, in a given physical application, some particular mathematical structure becomes available naturally, namely, that which arises from the physics of the problem. Thus mathematics can serve to provide a framework within which one deals only with quantities of physical significance, ignoring other, irrelevant things. One becomes able to focus on the physics. The idea is to isolate mathematical structures, one at a time, to learn what they are and what they can do. Such a body of knowledge, once established, can then be called upon whenever it makes contact with the physics.
An everyday example of this point is the idea of a derivative. One could imagine physicists who do not understand, as mathematics, the notion of a derivative and the properties of derivatives. Such physicists could still formulate physical laws, for example, by speaking of the “rate of change of . . . with . . .” They could use their physical intuition to obtain, as needed in various applications, particular properties of these “rates of change.” It would be more convenient, however, to isolate the notion “derivative” once and for all, without direct reference to later physical applications of this concept. One learns what a derivative is and what its properties are: the geometrical significance of a derivative, the rule for taking the derivative of a product, etc. This established body of knowledge then comes into play automatically when the physics requires the use of derivatives. Having mastered the abstract concept “rate of change” all by itself, the mind is freed for the important, that is, the physical, issues.
The only problem is that it takes a certain amount of effort to learn mathematics. Fortunately, two circumstances here intervene. First, the mathematics one needs for theoretical physics can often be mastered simply by making a sufficient effort. This activity is quite different from, and far more straightforward than, the originality and creativity needed in physics itself. Second, it seems to be the case in practice that the mathematics one needs in physics is not of a highly sophisticated sort. One hardly ever uses elaborate theorems or long strings of definitions. Rather, what one almost always uses, in various areas of mathematics, is the five or six basic definitions, some examples to give the definitions life, a few lemmas to relate various definitions to each other, and a couple of constructions. In short, what one needs from mathematics is a general idea of what areas of mathematics are available and, in each area, enough of the flavor of what is going on to feel comfortable. This broad and largely shallow coverage should in my view be the stuff of “mathematical physics.”
There is, of course, a second, more familiar role of mathematics in physics: that of solving specific physical problems which have already been formulated mathematically. This role encompasses such topics as special functions and solutions of differential equations. This second role has come to dominate the first in the traditional undergraduate and graduate curricula. My purpose, in part, is to argue for redressing the balance.
We shall here take a brief walking tour through various areas of mathematics, providing, where appropriate and available, examples in which this mathematics provides a framework for the formulation of physical ideas.
By way of general organization, chapters 2–24 deal with things algebraic and chapters 25–42 with things topological. In chapters 43–50 we discuss some special topics: structures which combine algebra and topology, Lebesque integrals, Hilbert spaces. Lest the impression be left that no difficult mathematics can ever be useful in physics, we provide, in chapters 51–56, a counterexample: the spectral theorem. Strictly speaking, the only prerequisites are a little elementary set theory, algebra, and, in a few places, some elementary calculus. Yet some informal contact with such objects as groups, vector spaces, and topological spaces would be most helpful.
The following texts are recommended for additional reading: A. H. Wallace, Algebraic Topology (Elmsford, NY: Pergamon, 1963), and C. Goffman and G. Pedrick, First Course in Functional Analysis (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1965). Two examples of more advanced texts, to which the present text might be regarded as an introduction, are: M. Reed and B. Simon, Methods of Modern Mathematical Physics (New York: Academic, 1972), and Y. Choquet-Bruhat, C. DeWitt-Morette, and M. Dillard-Bleick, Analysis, Manifolds and Physics (Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1982).
2
Categories
In each area of mathematics (e.g., groups, topological spaces) there are available many definitions and constructions. It turns out, however, that there are a number of notions (e.g., that of a product) that occur naturally in various areas of mathematics, with only slight changes from one area to another. It is convenient to take advantage of this observation. Category theory can be described as that branch of mathematics in which one studies certain definitions in a broader context—without reference to the particular area to which the definition might be applied. It is the “mathematics of mathematics.” Although this subject takes a little getting used to, it is, in my opinion, worth the effort. It provides a systematic framework that can help one to remember definitions in various areas of mathematics, to understand what many constructions mean and how they can be used, and even to invent useful definitions when needed. We here summarize a few facts from category theory.
A category consists of three things—i) a class O (whose elements will be called objects), ii) a set Mor(A, B) (whose elements will be called morphisms from A to B), where A and B are any two1 objects, and iii) a rule which assigns, given any objects A, B, and C and any morphism φ from A to B and morphism ψ from B to C, a morphism, written ψ φ, from A to C (this ψ φ will be called the composition of φ with ψ)—subject to the following two conditions:
1. Composition is associative. If A, B, C, and D are any four objects, and φ, ψ, and λ are morphisms from A to B, from B to C, and from C to D, respectively, then
image
(Note that each side of this equation is a morphism from A to D.)
2. Identities exist. For each object A, there is a morphism iA from A to A (called the identity morphism on A) with the following property: if φ is any morphism from A to B, then
image
if μ is any morphism from C to A, then
image
That is the definition of a category. It all seems rather abstract. In order to see what is really going on with this definition—why it is what it is—one has to look at a few examples. We shall have abundant opportunity to do this: almost every mathematical structure we look at will turn out to be an example of a category. In order to fix ideas for the present, we consider just one example (the simplest, and probably the best).
To give an example of a category, one must say what the objects are, what the morphisms are, what composition of morphi...

Índice