New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics, and the History of Ideas
eBook - ePub

New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics, and the History of Ideas

F. A. Hayek

Compartir libro
  1. English
  2. ePUB (apto para móviles)
  3. Disponible en iOS y Android
eBook - ePub

New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics, and the History of Ideas

F. A. Hayek

Detalles del libro
Vista previa del libro
Índice
Citas

Información del libro

Following on F. A. Hayek's previous work Studies in Philosophy, Politics, and Economics (1967), New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and the History of Ideas collects some of Hayek's most notable essays and lectures dealing with problems of philosophy, politics and economics, with many of the essays falling into more than one of these categories. Expanding upon the previous volume the present work also includes a fourth part collecting a series of Hayek's writings under the heading 'History of Ideas.'Of the articles contained in this volume the lectures on 'The Errors of Constructivism' (chapter 1) and 'Competition as a Discovery Procedure' (chapter 12) have been published before only in German, while the article on 'Liberalism' (chapter 9) was written in English to be published in an Italian translation in the Enciclopedia del Novicento by the Istituto della Enciclopedia Italiana at Rome.

Preguntas frecuentes

¿Cómo cancelo mi suscripción?
Simplemente, dirígete a la sección ajustes de la cuenta y haz clic en «Cancelar suscripción». Así de sencillo. Después de cancelar tu suscripción, esta permanecerá activa el tiempo restante que hayas pagado. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Cómo descargo los libros?
Por el momento, todos nuestros libros ePub adaptables a dispositivos móviles se pueden descargar a través de la aplicación. La mayor parte de nuestros PDF también se puede descargar y ya estamos trabajando para que el resto también sea descargable. Obtén más información aquí.
¿En qué se diferencian los planes de precios?
Ambos planes te permiten acceder por completo a la biblioteca y a todas las funciones de Perlego. Las únicas diferencias son el precio y el período de suscripción: con el plan anual ahorrarás en torno a un 30 % en comparación con 12 meses de un plan mensual.
¿Qué es Perlego?
Somos un servicio de suscripción de libros de texto en línea que te permite acceder a toda una biblioteca en línea por menos de lo que cuesta un libro al mes. Con más de un millón de libros sobre más de 1000 categorías, ¡tenemos todo lo que necesitas! Obtén más información aquí.
¿Perlego ofrece la función de texto a voz?
Busca el símbolo de lectura en voz alta en tu próximo libro para ver si puedes escucharlo. La herramienta de lectura en voz alta lee el texto en voz alta por ti, resaltando el texto a medida que se lee. Puedes pausarla, acelerarla y ralentizarla. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Es New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics, and the History of Ideas un PDF/ePUB en línea?
Sí, puedes acceder a New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics, and the History of Ideas de F. A. Hayek en formato PDF o ePUB, así como a otros libros populares de Commerce y Commerce Général. Tenemos más de un millón de libros disponibles en nuestro catálogo para que explores.

Información

Año
2018
ISBN
9780226321288
Categoría
Commerce
PART ONE
Philosophy
CHAPTER ONE
The Errors of Constructivism*
1
It seemed to me necessary to introduce the term ‘constructivism’1 as a specific name for a manner of thinking that in the past has often, but misleadingly, been described as ‘rationalism’.2 The basic conception of this constructivism can perhaps be expressed in the simplest manner by the innocent sounding formula that, since man has himself created the institutions of society and civilisation, he must also be able to alter them at will so as to satisfy his desires or wishes. It is almost 50 years since I first heard and was greatly impressed by this formula.3
At first the current phrase that man ‘created’ his civilisation and its institutions may appear rather harmless and commonplace. But as soon as it is extended, as is frequently done, to mean that man was able to do this because he was endowed with reason, the implications become questionable. Man did not possess reason before civilisation. The two evolved together. We need merely to consider language, which today nobody still believes to have been ‘invented’ by a rational being, in order to see that reason and civilisation develop in constant mutual interaction. But what we now no longer question with regard to language (though even that is comparatively recent) is by no means generally accepted with regard to morals, law, the skills of handicrafts, or social institutions. We are still too easily led to assume that these phenomena, which are clearly the results of human action, must also have been consciously designed by a human mind, in circumstances created for the purposes which they serve – that is, that they are what Max Weber called wert-rationale products.4 In short, we are misled into thinking that morals, law, skills and social institutions can only be justified in so far as they correspond to some preconceived design.
It is significant that this is a mistake we usually commit only with regard to the phenomena of our own civilisation. If the ethnologist or social anthropologist attempts to understand other cultures, he has no doubt that their members frequently have no idea as to the reason for observing particular rules, or what depends on it. Yet most modern social theorists are rarely willing to admit that the same thing applies also to our own civilisation. We too frequently do not know what benefits we derive from the usages of our society; and such social theorists regard this merely as a regrettable deficiency which ought to be removed as soon as possible.
2
In a short lecture it is not possible to trace the history of the discussion of these problems to which I have given some attention in recent years.5 I will merely mention that they were already familiar to the ancient Greeks. The very dichotomy between ‘natural’ and ‘artificial’ formations which the ancient Greeks introduced has dominated the discussion for 2,000 years. Unfortunately, the Greeks’ distinction between natural and artificial has become the greatest obstacle to further advance; because, interpreted as an exclusive alternative, this distinction is not only ambiguous but definitely false. As was at last clearly seen by the Scottish social philosophers of the eighteenth century (but the late Schoolmen had already partly seen it), a large part of social formations, although the result of human action, is not of human design. The consequence of this is that such formations, according to the interpretation of the traditional terms, could be described either as ‘natural’, or as ‘artificial’.
The beginning of a true appreciation of these circumstances in the sixteenth century was extinguished, however, in the seventeenth century by the rise of a powerful new philosophy – the rationalism of René Descartes and his followers, from whom all modern forms of constructivism derive. From Descartes it was taken over by that unreasonable ‘Age of Reason’, which was entirely dominated by the Cartesian spirit. Voltaire, the greatest representative of the so-called ‘Age of Reason’, expressed the Cartesian spirit in his famous statement: ‘if you want good laws, burn those you have and make yourselves new ones’.6 Against this, the great critic of rationalism, David Hume, could only slowly elaborate the foundations of a true theory of the growth of social formations, which was further developed by his fellow Scotsmen, Adam Smith and Adam Ferguson, into a theory of phenomena that are ‘the result of human action but not of human design’.
Descartes had taught that we should only believe what we can prove. Applied to the field of morals and values generally, his doctrine meant that we should only accept as binding what we could recognise as a rational design for a recognisable purpose. I will leave undecided how far he himself evaded difficulties by representing the unfathomable will of God as the creator of all purposive phenomena.7 For his successors it certainly became a human will, which they regarded as the source of all social formations whose intention must provide the justification. Society appeared to them as a deliberate construction of men for an intended purpose – shown most clearly in the writing of Descartes’ faithful pupil, J.-J. Rousseau.8 The belief in the unlimited power of a supreme authority as necessary, especially for a representative assembly, and therefore the belief that democracy necessarily means the unlimited power of the majority, are ominous consequences of this constructivism.
3
You will probably most clearly see what I mean by ‘constructivism’ if I quote a characteristic statement of a well-known Swedish sociologist, which I recently encountered in the pages of a German popular science journal. ‘The most important goal that sociology has set itself’, he wrote, ‘is to predict the future development and to shape (gestalten) the future, or, if one prefers to express it in that manner, to create the future of mankind.’9 If a science makes such claims, this evidently implies the assertion that the whole of human civilisation, and all we have so far achieved, could only have been built as a purposive rational construction.
It must suffice for the moment to show that this constructivistic interpretation of social formations is by no means merely harmless philosophical speculation, but an assertion of fact from which conclusions are derived concerning both the explanation of social processes and the opportunities for political action. The factually erroneous assertion, from which the constructivists derive such far-reaching consequences and demands, appears to me to be that the complex order of our modern society is exclusively due to the circumstance that men have been guided in their actions by foresight – an insight into the connections between cause and effect – or at least that it could have arisen through design. What I want to show is that men are in their conduct never guided exclusively by their understanding of the causal connections between particular known means and certain desired ends, but always also by rules of conduct of which they are rarely aware, which they certainly have not consciously invented, and that to discern the function and significance of this is a difficult and only partially achieved task of scientific effort. Expressing this differently – it means that the success of rational striving (Max Weber’s zweckrationales Handeln) is largely due to the observance of values, whose role in our society ought to be carefully distinguished from that of deliberately pursued goals.
I can only briefly mention the further fact, that success of the individual in the achievement of his immediate aims depends, not only on his conscious insight into causal connections, but also in a high degree on his ability to act according to rules, which he may be unable to express in words, but which we can only describe by formulating rules. All our skills, from the command of language to the mastery of handicrafts or games – actions which we ‘know how’ to perform without being able to state how we do it – are instances of this.10 I mention them here only because action according to rules – which we do not explicitly know and which have not been designed by reason, but prevail because the manner of acting of those who are successful is imitated – is perhaps easier to recognise in these instances than in the field directly relevant to my present concerns.
The rules we are discussing are those that are not so much useful to the individuals who observe them, as those that (if they are generally observed) make all the members of the group more effective, because they give them opportunities to act within a social order. These rules are also mostly not the result of a deliberate choice of means for specific purposes, but of a process of selection, in the course of which groups that achieved a more efficient order displaced (or were imitated by) others, often without knowing to what their superiority was due. This social group of rules includes the rules of law, of morals, of custom and so on – in fact, all the values which govern a society. The term ‘value’, which I shall for lack of a better one have to continue to use in this context, is in fact a little misleading, because we tend to interpret it as referring to particular aims of individual action, while in the fields to which I am referring they consist mostly of rules which do not tell us positively what to do, but in most instances merely what we ought not to do.
Those taboos of society which are not founded on any rational justification have been the favourite subject of derision by the constructivists, who wish to see them banned from any rationally designed order of society. Among the taboos they have largely succeeded in destroying are respect for private property and for the keeping of private contracts, with the result that some people doubt if respect for them can ever again be restored.11
For all organisms, however, it is often more important to know what they must not do, if they are to avoid danger, than to know what they must do in order to achieve particular ends. The former kind of knowledge is usually not a knowledge of the consequences which the prohibited kind of conduct would produce, but a knowledge that in certain conditions certain types of conduct are to be avoided. Our positive knowledge of cause and effect assists us only in those fields where our acquaintance with the particular circumstances is sufficient; and it is important that we do not move beyond the region where this knowledge will guide us reliably. This is achieved by rules that, without regard to the consequences in the particular instance, generally prohibit actions of a certain kind.12
That in this sense man is not only a purpose-seeking but also a rule-following animal has been repeatedly stressed in the recent literature.13 In order to understand what is meant by this, we must be quite clear about the meaning attached in this connection to the word ‘rule’. This is necessary because those chiefly negative (or prohibitory) rules of conduct which make possible the formation of social order are of three different kinds, which I now spell out. These kinds of rules are: (1) rules that are merely observed in fact but have never been stated in words; if we speak of the ‘sense of justice’ or ‘the feeling for language’ we refer to such rules which we are able to apply, but do not know explicitly; (2) rules that, though they have been stated in words, still merely express approximately what has long before been generally observed in action; and (3) rules that have been deliberately introduced and therefore necessarily exist as words set out in sentences.
Construetivists would like to reject the first and second groups of rules, and to accept as valid only the third group I have mentioned.
4
What then is the origin of those rules that most people follow but few if anyone can state in words? Long before Charles Darwin the theorists of society, and particularly those of language, had given the answer that in the process of cultural transmission, in which modes of conduct are passed on from generation to generation, a process of selection takes place, in which those modes of conduct prevail which lead to the formation of a more efficient order for the whole group, because such groups will prevail over others.14
A point needing special emphasis, because it is so frequently misunderstood, is that by no means every regularity of conduct among individuals produces an order for the whole of society. Therefore regular individual conduct does not necessarily mean order, but only certain kinds of regularity of the conduct of individuals lead to an order for the whole. The order of society is therefore a factual state of affairs which must be distinguished from the regularity of the conduct of individuals. It must be defined as a condition in which individuals are able, on the basis of their own respective peculiar knowledge, to form expectations concerning the conduct of others, which are proved correct by making possible a successful mutual adjustment of the actions of these individuals. If every person perceiving another were either to try to kill him or to run away, this would certainly also constitute a regularity of individual conduct, but not one that led to the formation of ordered groups. Quite clearly, certain combinations of such rules of individual conduct may produce a superior kind of order, which will enable some groups to expand at the expense of others.
This effect does not presuppose that the members of the group know to which rules of conduct the group owes its superiority, but merely that it will accept only those individuals as members who observe the rules traditionally accepted by it. There will always be an amount of experience of individuals precipitated in such rules, which its living members do not know, but which nevertheless help them more effectively to pursue their ends.
This sort of ‘knowledge of the world’ that is passed on from generation to generation will thus consist in a great measure not of knowledge of cause and effect, but of rules of conduct adapted to the environment and acting like information about the environment although they do not say anything about it. Like scientific theories, they are preserved by proving themselves useful, but, in contrast to scientific theories, by a proof which no one needs to know, because the proof manifests itself in the resilience and progressive expansion of the order of society which it makes possible. This is the true content of the much derided idea of the ‘wisdom of our ancestors’ embodied in inherited institutions, which plays such an important role in conservative thought, but appears to the constructivist to be an empty phrase signifying nothing.
5
Time allows me to consider further only one of the many interesting interrelations of this kind, which at the same time also explains why an economist is particularly inclined to concern himself with these problems: the connection between rules of law and the spontaneously formed order of the market.15 This order is, of course, not the result of a miracle or some natural harmony of interests. It forms itself, because in the course of millennia men develop rules of conduct which lead to the formation of such an order out of the separate spontaneous activities of individuals. The interesting point about this is that men developed these rules without really understanding their functions. Philosophers of law have in general even ceased to ask what is the ‘purpose’ of law, thinking the question is unanswerable because they interpret ‘purpose’ to mean particular foreseeable results, to achieve which the rules were designed. In fact, this ‘purpose’ is to bring about an abstract order – a system of abstract relations – concrete manifestations of which will depend on a great variety of particular circumstances which no one can know in their entirety. Those rules of just conduct have therefore a ‘meaning’ or ‘function’ which no one has given them, and which social theory must try to discover.
It was the great achievement of economic theory that, 200 years before cybernetics, it recognised the nature of such self-regulating systems in which certain regularities (or, perhaps better, ‘restraints’) of conduct of the elements led to constant adaptation of the comprehensive order to particular facts, affecting in the first instance only the separate elements. Such an order, leading to the utilisation of much more information than anyone possesses, could not have been ‘invented’. This follows from the fact that the result could not have been foreseen. None of our ancestors could have known that the protection of property and contracts would lead to an extensive division of labour, specialisation and the establishment of markets, or that the extension to outsiders of rules initially applicable only to members of the same tribe would tend towards the formation of a world economy.
All that man could do was to try to improve bit by bit on a process of mutually adjusting individual activities, by reducing conflicts through modifications to some of the inherited rules. All that he could deliberately design, he could and did create only within a system of rules, which he had not invented, and with the aim of improving an existing order.16 Always merely adjusting the rules, he tried to improve the combined effect of all other rules accepted in his community. In his efforts to improve the existing order, he was therefore never free arbitrarily to lay down any new rule he liked, but had always a definite problem to solve, raised by an imperfection of the existing order, but of an order he would have been quite incapable of constructing as a whole. What man found were conflicts between accepted value...

Índice