Hannah Arendt and Isaiah Berlin
eBook - ePub

Hannah Arendt and Isaiah Berlin

Freedom, Politics, and Humanity

Kei Hiruta

Compartir libro
  1. 288 páginas
  2. English
  3. ePUB (apto para móviles)
  4. Disponible en iOS y Android
eBook - ePub

Hannah Arendt and Isaiah Berlin

Freedom, Politics, and Humanity

Kei Hiruta

Detalles del libro
Vista previa del libro
Índice
Citas

Información del libro

For the first time, the full story of the conflict between two of the twentieth century's most important thinkers—and the lessons their disagreements continue to offer Two of the most iconic thinkers of the twentieth century, Hannah Arendt (1906–1975) and Isaiah Berlin (1909–1997) fundamentally disagreed on central issues in politics, history and philosophy. In spite of their overlapping lives and experiences as Jewish émigré intellectuals, Berlin disliked Arendt intensely, saying that she represented "everything that I detest most, " while Arendt met Berlin's hostility with indifference and suspicion. Written in a lively style, and filled with drama, tragedy and passion, Hannah Arendt and Isaiah Berlin tells, for the first time, the full story of the fraught relationship between these towering figures, and shows how their profoundly different views continue to offer important lessons for political thought today.Drawing on a wealth of new archival material, Kei Hiruta traces the Arendt–Berlin conflict, from their first meeting in wartime New York through their widening intellectual chasm during the 1950s, the controversy over Arendt's 1963 book Eichmann in Jerusalem, their final missed opportunity to engage with each other at a 1967 conference and Berlin's continuing animosity toward Arendt after her death. Hiruta blends political philosophy and intellectual history to examine key issues that simultaneously connected and divided Arendt and Berlin, including the nature of totalitarianism, evil and the Holocaust, human agency and moral responsibility, Zionism, American democracy, British imperialism and the Hungarian Revolution. But, most of all, Arendt and Berlin disagreed over a question that goes to the heart of the human condition: what does it mean to be free?

Preguntas frecuentes

¿Cómo cancelo mi suscripción?
Simplemente, dirígete a la sección ajustes de la cuenta y haz clic en «Cancelar suscripción». Así de sencillo. Después de cancelar tu suscripción, esta permanecerá activa el tiempo restante que hayas pagado. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Cómo descargo los libros?
Por el momento, todos nuestros libros ePub adaptables a dispositivos móviles se pueden descargar a través de la aplicación. La mayor parte de nuestros PDF también se puede descargar y ya estamos trabajando para que el resto también sea descargable. Obtén más información aquí.
¿En qué se diferencian los planes de precios?
Ambos planes te permiten acceder por completo a la biblioteca y a todas las funciones de Perlego. Las únicas diferencias son el precio y el período de suscripción: con el plan anual ahorrarás en torno a un 30 % en comparación con 12 meses de un plan mensual.
¿Qué es Perlego?
Somos un servicio de suscripción de libros de texto en línea que te permite acceder a toda una biblioteca en línea por menos de lo que cuesta un libro al mes. Con más de un millón de libros sobre más de 1000 categorías, ¡tenemos todo lo que necesitas! Obtén más información aquí.
¿Perlego ofrece la función de texto a voz?
Busca el símbolo de lectura en voz alta en tu próximo libro para ver si puedes escucharlo. La herramienta de lectura en voz alta lee el texto en voz alta por ti, resaltando el texto a medida que se lee. Puedes pausarla, acelerarla y ralentizarla. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Es Hannah Arendt and Isaiah Berlin un PDF/ePUB en línea?
Sí, puedes acceder a Hannah Arendt and Isaiah Berlin de Kei Hiruta en formato PDF o ePUB, así como a otros libros populares de Philosophy y Political Philosophy. Tenemos más de un millón de libros disponibles en nuestro catálogo para que explores.

Información

Año
2021
ISBN
9780691226132
Categoría
Philosophy

1

Introduction

Years ago, I brought Hannah and Isaiah together. […] The meeting was a disaster from the start. She was too solemn, portentous, Teutonic, Hegelian for him. She mistook his wit for frivolousness and thought him inadequately serious.
—ARTHUR SCHLESINGER JR.1
IN 1991, the American philosopher Norman Oliver Brown wrote to his friend and former tutor Isaiah Berlin,2 and favourably mentioned a recently published book entitled Republic of Fear.3 A pioneering study of Saddam Hussein and his Baʿath Party, the book drew comparisons between the ‘Kafkaesque’ world of Saddam’s Iraq and its purported precursors in the twentieth century. In so doing, it drew on some of the anti-totalitarian classics, including Berlin’s Four Essays on Liberty and Hannah Arendt’s The Origins of Totalitarianism.4 Berlin was not pleased with this pairing. He wrote to Brown, ‘I assume that [Republic of Fear] is about the horrors of Iraq, etc., but what deeply offends me is the linking of my name with that of Miss Hannah Arendt […]. [D]o tell me that you do see some radical differences between Miss Arendt and myself—otherwise how can we go on knowing each other?’5
The strong dislike for Arendt that Berlin expressed in his 1991 letter to Brown has a long history. It began a half-century earlier, when the two thinkers were introduced to each other in wartime New York. Not much is known about this meeting, but their opinions were certainly different and their personal chemistry evidently bad. The relationship between the two thinkers did not improve, to say the least, when they spoke again at Harvard University about a decade later, probably in 1949. Arthur Schlesinger Jr., the political scientist who arranged this meeting, would later recall the occasion as a ‘disaster from the start’.6 Their paths did not cross again for more than fifteen years, as Berlin continued to build his dazzling academic career in Britain, while Arendt established herself as an influential public intellectual in the United States. Nevertheless, they were not far apart socially, culturally or intellectually. They not only shared various research interests but also had many mutual friends, academic contacts and collaborators. Some of them, most notably the British political theorist Bernard Crick, attempted to persuade Berlin of the importance of Arendt’s work. The Oxford philosopher was never persuaded. On the contrary, enhanced by his deep scepticism about the phenomenological tradition in philosophy, Berlin dismissed her theoretical work such as The Human Condition as an assemblage of ‘free metaphysical association’.7 His contempt subsequently evolved into a lifelong hatred with the publication of Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil in 1963. He wholeheartedly endorsed the widespread accusation that Arendt arrogantly and patronisingly blamed the victims of the Holocaust and that she proposed a deeply flawed account of evil.
Curiously, despite his disdain for Arendt and her work, Berlin kept reading—or, more precisely, skimming through—her books and articles, including neglected works such as Rahel Varnhagen: The Life of a Jewess as well as more major writings such as The Human Condition and On Revolution.8 The more he read, however, the more convinced he was that his assessment of Arendt’s work had been sound. The late Berlin summarised his considered opinion as follows: Arendt ‘produces no arguments, no evidence of serious philosophical or historical thought.’9 In addition, Berlin’s animosity towards Arendt was never softened either by her death or by the ensuing passage of time. In the 1991 letter to Brown cited above, Berlin described Arendt as ‘a real bête noire to me—in life, and after her death’. He continued, ‘I really do look upon her as everything that I detest most.’10
Arendt was aware of Berlin’s hostility towards her. This was thanks in no small part to the writer Mary McCarthy, who repeatedly disputed Berlin’s dismissal of Arendt, so much so that her friendship with him came to be ‘destroyed’ as a result.11 Meanwhile, Arendt herself never quite reciprocated Berlin’s hostility. For one thing, she was, and was proud to be, a controversial figure, attracting many embittered critics especially after the publication of Eichmann in Jerusalem. She could not possibly respond to all of them, and from her point of view Berlin did not stand out as an especially important or worthy one. She was aware of his standing and connections in Britain, Israel and the USA, but she hardly considered him to be an original thinker.12 This was partly because Arendt took the superiority of German philosophy over its Anglo-American counterpart for granted. Although she respected Hobbes, she generally saw Britain as something of a philosophical desert and saw little merit in the analytic movement inaugurated by Russell, Moore and others. In this respect, our protagonists’ prejudices were symmetrical: just as Berlin was unable to appreciate German phenomenology, Arendt was unable to appreciate British empiricism. Nevertheless, Arendt regarded Berlin as a learned scholar, especially when it came to Russian intellectual history. She sometimes used his writings in her classes;13 and her surviving personal library contains a copy of Berlin’s first book, Karl Marx: His Life and Environment, and four essays by him.14 It is, however, indicative that the only piece by Berlin that Arendt seems to have read carefully was his introduction to Franco Venturi’s Roots of Revolution. In fact, it is as the author of this introduction that Berlin makes his one and only appearance (in a footnote) in Arendt’s published work.15 For her, Berlin was a respectable intellectual historian and a moderately important member of what she called the ‘Jewish establishment’. His animosity towards her was met by her indifference to him, accompanied by occasional suspicion.
Things could have been different. They were contemporaries, Arendt born in 1906 and Berlin in 1909. They belonged to the group of twentieth-century Jewish émigré intellectuals whose thoughts and life stories were intertwined with each other.16 Born into German-Jewish and Baltic-Jewish families respectively, Arendt and Berlin alike experienced their share of antisemitism in their formative years. Both came to be preoccupied with Europe’s looming crises in the 1930s, decided to abandon a promising career in pure philosophy by the end of World War II and thereafter devoted much of their time and energy to understanding the roots of totalitarianism, containing its growth and pre-empting its resurgence. Both of them had friends and relatives murdered or driven to death by the totalitarian regimes that they came to study in their academic work. Moreover, they themselves lived in the emerging totalitarian world and were consequently in a position to do something akin to what anthropologists call ‘participatory observation’: data collection by way of actually living in the society one aims to study. As is well known, the young Isaiah Berlin witnessed in horror both the February and October Revolutions in Petrograd. He subsequently returned to Soviet Russia to serve in the British Embassy in 1945–46, after having ‘a recurring nightmare of being arrested’ and giving thought to the prospect of suicide in the event of an arrest.17 For her part, Arendt was arrested and endured an eight-day interrogation in Nazified Germany, followed by a five-week detention in an internment camp in occupied France (where she too gave thought to taking her own life) before migrating to the United States to write The Origins of Totalitarianism. Oppression, domination, inhumanity and the subversion of politics were their existential as well as intellectual issues; so were freedom, humanity and politics.

The twin goals of this study are to trace the development of the unfortunate relationship between the historical figures of Hannah Arendt and Isaiah Berlin, and to bring their ideas into conversation. The former goal is historical and biographical in nature; the latter, theoretical. The former involves the following questions:
When and where did Arendt and Berlin meet, and what happened during those meetings?
How did the personal conflict between the two emerge?
How did Berlin develop his animosity towards Arendt, and she her indifference and suspicion towards him?
What other interactions did they have apart from their actual meetings?
These questions are worth asking not only because they form a fascinating part of twentieth-century intellectual, literary and cultural history. They are worth asking also because the personal, the political and the intellectual were hardly separable in both Arendt’s and Berlin’s lives and works. I take seriously what I believe to be an elementary truth about them both: political theory for them was more than a job or paid work. It was a vocation in the Weberian sense, and each led the life of a political thinker, embodying a distinct theoretical outlook.18 Deeply concerned with urgent issues of their times, both of our protagonists attempted to exercise, albeit in differing ways, influence on the ‘real world’ they inhabited. As I shall show, this mode of living and thinking has its own downsides and consequently is not unequivocally superior to the more detached and institutionalised mode of political theorising that has become the norm today. Still, we have some good reason to feel nostalgic about the time when political theorists took themselves more seriously because their ‘ideas really did have consequences’.19
The other, theoretical side of this study concerns a set of fundamental issues that simultaneously connected and divided our protagonists. They connected in that they were central to both Arendt’s and Berlin’s thought; and they divided in that they were answered by the two thinkers in conflicting ways. Those central issues may be formally and schematically stated as follows:
What does it mean for human beings to be free?
What is it like for a person to be denied his or her freedom, and deprived of his or her humanity?20 What are the central features of the worst form of unfree and inhumane society, known as totalitarianism, and how does this paradigmatically emerge?
How should we assess the apparent failure to resist or confront the evil of totalitarianism, such as when one is coerced into cooperating with a state-sponsored mass murderer?
What kind of society or polity ought we to aim to build if we want as many people as possible to be free and live a genuinely human life?
Arendt’s and Berlin’s sometimes overlapping and sometimes conflicting reflections on these questions will be considered in Chapters 3–6. These chapters are thematically organised, although each is loosely tied to a chronological phase. The third chapter, on ‘Freedom’, focuses on the late 1950s and early 1960s, when both of our protagonists fully matured as political thinkers and presented their rival theories of freedom, underpinned by competing views of the human condition. The fourth chapter, on ‘Inhumanity’, covers a longer period and traces the protagonists’ lifelong engagement with totalitarianism. It mainly examines two distinct bodies of work: their wartime and immediate post-war analyses of totalitarian politics and society; and their later attempts to reconsider the history of Western political thought in light of the reality of Nazism and Stalinism. Chapter 5, on ‘Evil and Judgement’, focuses on Arendt’s Eichmann in Jerusalem and Berlin’s commentary on it. As their dispute is tied to their disagreement over central moral and political concepts, such as responsibility, judgement, power and agency, this chapter also covers the relevant work on these concepts. Chapter 6, on ‘Islands of Freedom’, delves more deeply into the two thinkers’ middle and late works to tease out their competing visions of an ideal polity. Along the way, it considers their rival perspectives on a range of real-world politics and societies, including Britain’s liberal present and its imperial past, the United States in the turbulent 1960s and Central and East European resistance to Soviet domination. In the Conclusion (Chapter 7), I briefly restate my main arguments and consider their implications for political thought and political philosophy today.
Although the story I tell in this book has many twists and turns, its backbone is simple and may be programmatically stated as follo...

Índice