Financial Market Analysis and Behaviour
eBook - ePub

Financial Market Analysis and Behaviour

The Adaptive Preference Hypothesis

Emil Dinga, Camelia Oprean-Stan, Cristina-Roxana Tănăsescu, Vasile Brătian, Gabriela-Mariana Ionescu

Compartir libro
  1. 328 páginas
  2. English
  3. ePUB (apto para móviles)
  4. Disponible en iOS y Android
eBook - ePub

Financial Market Analysis and Behaviour

The Adaptive Preference Hypothesis

Emil Dinga, Camelia Oprean-Stan, Cristina-Roxana Tănăsescu, Vasile Brătian, Gabriela-Mariana Ionescu

Detalles del libro
Vista previa del libro
Índice
Citas

Información del libro

This book addresses the functioning of financial markets, in particular the financial market model, and modelling. More specifically, the book provides a model of adaptive preference in the financial market, rather than the model of the adaptive financial market, which is mostly based on Popper's objective propensity for the singular, i.e., unrepeatable, event. As a result, the concept of preference, following Simon's theory of satisficing, is developed in a logical way with the goal of supplying a foundation for a robust theory of adaptive preference in financial market behavior. The book offers new insights into financial market logic, and psychology: 1) advocating for the priority of behavior over information - in opposition to traditional financial market theories; 2) constructing the processes of (co)evolution adaptive preference-financial market using the concept of fetal reaction norms - between financial market and adaptive preference; 3) presenting a new typology of information in the financial market, aimed at proving point (1) above, as well as edifying an explicative mechanism of the evolutionary nature and behavior of the (real) financial market; 4) presenting sufficient, and necessary, principles or assumptions for developing a theory of adaptive preference in the financial market; and 5) proposing a new interpretation of the pair genotype-phenotype in the financial market model. The book's distinguishing feature is its research method, which is mainly logically rather than historically or empirically based. As a result, the book is targeted at generating debate about the best and most scientifically beneficial method of approaching, analyzing, and modelling financial markets.

Preguntas frecuentes

¿Cómo cancelo mi suscripción?
Simplemente, dirígete a la sección ajustes de la cuenta y haz clic en «Cancelar suscripción». Así de sencillo. Después de cancelar tu suscripción, esta permanecerá activa el tiempo restante que hayas pagado. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Cómo descargo los libros?
Por el momento, todos nuestros libros ePub adaptables a dispositivos móviles se pueden descargar a través de la aplicación. La mayor parte de nuestros PDF también se puede descargar y ya estamos trabajando para que el resto también sea descargable. Obtén más información aquí.
¿En qué se diferencian los planes de precios?
Ambos planes te permiten acceder por completo a la biblioteca y a todas las funciones de Perlego. Las únicas diferencias son el precio y el período de suscripción: con el plan anual ahorrarás en torno a un 30 % en comparación con 12 meses de un plan mensual.
¿Qué es Perlego?
Somos un servicio de suscripción de libros de texto en línea que te permite acceder a toda una biblioteca en línea por menos de lo que cuesta un libro al mes. Con más de un millón de libros sobre más de 1000 categorías, ¡tenemos todo lo que necesitas! Obtén más información aquí.
¿Perlego ofrece la función de texto a voz?
Busca el símbolo de lectura en voz alta en tu próximo libro para ver si puedes escucharlo. La herramienta de lectura en voz alta lee el texto en voz alta por ti, resaltando el texto a medida que se lee. Puedes pausarla, acelerarla y ralentizarla. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Es Financial Market Analysis and Behaviour un PDF/ePUB en línea?
Sí, puedes acceder a Financial Market Analysis and Behaviour de Emil Dinga, Camelia Oprean-Stan, Cristina-Roxana Tănăsescu, Vasile Brătian, Gabriela-Mariana Ionescu en formato PDF o ePUB, así como a otros libros populares de Economics y Econometrics. Tenemos más de un millón de libros disponibles en nuestro catálogo para que explores.

Información

Editorial
Routledge
Año
2022
ISBN
9781000609738
Edición
1
Categoría
Economics
Categoría
Econometrics

1 Adaptive preference

DOI: 10.4324/9781003283690-1

Introduction

Rationality, expectation, belief, preference

Rationality is defined as a property (either of a decision or of an action) in relation to a given model of rationality. Therefore, there is no absolute rationality, or itself, but only a contextualized (or relative) rationality for a given model of rationality. Models of rationality can be either explicit, often formalized (as in the model of economic rationality within neoclassical economic theory, known as homo œconomicus), or implicit (which is the case of behaviourist models or, more recently, evolutionary models, inspired by the biological paradigm). If we note with MRi a model of rationality i, then a decision j taken into context of the given model of rationality dMRij can be of three categories (all related to MRi):
  • rational decision – when it is validly inferred1 fromMRi, noted with dMRij;
  • irrational decision – when it is invalidly inferred from MRi, noted with d¯MRij;
  • a-rational decision (or logically inferred) – when it has no relationship with type inference MRi, noted with dMRi~j.
Of course, what appears as irrational or a-rational in relation to one model of rationality can be rational in relation to another model of rationality and vice versa. Thus, if we note a decision k, dMRqk in relation to a model of rationality q, MRq, we can have any of the following situation: the noted logical constant ⋈ has the meaning ‘is compatible with’ (¯ means ‘is incompatible with’), and the logical constant → has the meaning ‘validly implies’ (↛ means ‘does not validly imply’):
  • formalization of the rational decision:
    • dMRij[djMRiMRidj]
  • formalization of the irrational decision:
    • dMRi−jdj¯MRiMRidj
  • formalization of the a-rational decision:
    • d¯MRij[dj¯MRiMRidj][dj¯MRiMRidj]
Human behaviour may take place under four ‘authorities’: under the authority of rationality, under the authority of expectation (subjective), under the authority of belief, and under the authority of preference.
Of course, this typology is rather academic because, in fact, the four ‘authorities’ can be combined two by two or (which is, additionally, the most common case) co-exist in different weights, weights which, in turn, change because of the experience, as a result of environmental pressure, or as a result of both causes.

Behaviour led by rationality

It is a behaviour based exclusively on inferring the decision from the pre-accepted model of rationality (in the logically way described earlier). It is the behaviour considered in neoclassical economic theory2 (under the empire of which the efficient market hypothesis (EMH) was also constructed), which considers the human individual as having a hyper-rationality in choosing the optimal decision (i.e., the decision which extremizes an objective function under given restrictive conditions or, equivalently, minimizes the opportunity cost under those conditions). The best-known logical model of this type of behaviour is the (mathematical) homo œconomicus model. Over time, this abstract model has been relaxed in many ways (including here Simon’s concept of bounded rationality, as well as other formal relaxations), but rational behaviour remains predominant.

Behaviour led by expectation

Behaviour led by expectation is based primarily on behaviourist studies3 (behavioural economics), and the economic decision is based on a combination of rationality and emotion (fear and various aversions to risk, to loss, etc.), considering even that ‘realistic’ rationality contains emotion.4 Behaviourism accepts the important role of the individual’s past (experience) as an economic actor. In essence, an expectation is subjective (and, therefore, strongly idiosyncratic) and is manifested by the allocation of Bayesian probabilities5 events (occurring under conditions of uncertainty, which are logically equivalent to the absence of any information that would associate risks with the events concerned and which, by this allocation, would change the probabilities associated with them). The phrase ‘rational expectations’, extremely common in the literature, is quite ambiguous because being subjective, the expectation cannot be rational – because if it were rational, it would be associated with a model of rationality, so it would not be subjective (namely, free, based on free will or, at least, idiosyncratic desirability). Probably, those who use this phrase intend to say ‘rational anticipations’, which is something else entirely.6

Behaviour led by belief

Regarding behaviour led by belief, this is intended to be a more comprehensive theory related to that of behaviour led by expectations, in the sense that it is considered (in an axiomatically way) that the individual is ‘endowed’ with a (complete) system of beliefs about economic phenomenology, beliefs which underlie its decisions and actions (including, of course, religious beliefs, ethical values, etc.). This theory is closely linked to the theory of justification and, as a result, is more a post-factum theory than one which would constitute an operational predictor on the economic market (or, more specifically, on the financial market). Belief (put into relation with motivation, intention, and other psychological ‘objects’) constitutes one of the arguments of behaviourism (and evolutionism) for shaping the economic decision. In the specialty literature, the following categories of beliefs are considered:
  • overconfidence in their own judgements (i.e., self-attribution – luck is attributed to their own talent; hindsight – ex post, individuals always find that they ‘predicted’ well);
  • optimism, desire-oriented thinking, and greed;
  • representativeness, which leads to an underestimation of the sample size (there are two failures of representativeness, especially in assigning probabilities: (1) neglect of the base rate; (2) neglecting the sample size);
  • conservatism: leads to overestimation of the sample size;
  • perseverance of belief: inertia in renouncing the formed belief;
  • anchoring: availability errors – information that is no longer available in memory (Barberis & Thaler, 2012).

Behaviour led by preference

Behaviour led by preference is, in a way, a wrapper of all three types of behaviours described earlier, in the sense that the individual (actor or economic agent) externalizes both his model of rationality and idiosyncratic expectations and beliefs, through the preference. So, in a way, the preference is a synthesis (not aggregation, because the three bases of behaviour are, in principle, incommensurable two by two) of the whole ‘economic personality’ of the individual concerned. Although the authors did not agree on a ‘list’ of preferences (which, as mentioned earlier, are sometimes considered beliefs), in principle, there are three such preferences: (a) risk aversion; (b) aversion to loss – see Prospect Theory (Kahneman, 2012); and (c) aversion to ambiguity. In what follows, we will focus only on this type of economic behaviour.

The concept of economic preference

In economic theory, economic preferences mean anchors of behaviour of the individual (actor/economic agent) which are, in the most general sense, predictors of the behaviour concerned. There are two basic characteristics of economic preferences: (a) they are considered given, namely, they represent variables (in fact, rather, constraints) exogenous for the economic analyst;7 and (b) they are idiosyncratic, namely, specific to each specific individual (or, as the case may be, to each representative agent, if modelling based on representative agents is used), which means that they are incommensurable between any two individuals. More precisely, economic preferences act on economic behaviour analogously with the action of the principles assumed (and publicly announced) by each individual or, where appropriate, by each class of individuals considered homogeneous within that class and from the perspective of the accepted classification criterion.8 In this context, we can define economic preference, at the individual level, as the maximum probability of choice in conditions of uncertainty. The justifications for this content of economic preference are as follows:
  • in connection with a choice (or equivalent, with a decision between at least two measurable alternatives9 between them), ther...

Índice