Semantics - Foundations, History and Methods
eBook - ePub

Semantics - Foundations, History and Methods

Klaus Heusinger, Claudia Maienborn, Paul Portner, Klaus Heusinger, Claudia Maienborn, Paul Portner

Compartir libro
  1. 417 páginas
  2. English
  3. ePUB (apto para móviles)
  4. Disponible en iOS y Android
eBook - ePub

Semantics - Foundations, History and Methods

Klaus Heusinger, Claudia Maienborn, Paul Portner, Klaus Heusinger, Claudia Maienborn, Paul Portner

Detalles del libro
Vista previa del libro
Índice
Citas

Información del libro

Get to grips with the fundamentals of semantics research. Written by a team of world-class experts, this book introduces the subject for a broad audience of linguists, cognitive scientists, philosophers, and computer scientists. It explores the core concepts of sentential semantics and includes sections on questions, imperatives, copular clauses, and existential sentences. It also features essential research on sentence types, and explains central concepts in the theory of information structure and discourse structure. Now in paperback for the first time since its original publication, the material in this modern classic is an ideal resource for anyone involved in semantics research.

Preguntas frecuentes

¿Cómo cancelo mi suscripción?
Simplemente, dirígete a la sección ajustes de la cuenta y haz clic en «Cancelar suscripción». Así de sencillo. Después de cancelar tu suscripción, esta permanecerá activa el tiempo restante que hayas pagado. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Cómo descargo los libros?
Por el momento, todos nuestros libros ePub adaptables a dispositivos móviles se pueden descargar a través de la aplicación. La mayor parte de nuestros PDF también se puede descargar y ya estamos trabajando para que el resto también sea descargable. Obtén más información aquí.
¿En qué se diferencian los planes de precios?
Ambos planes te permiten acceder por completo a la biblioteca y a todas las funciones de Perlego. Las únicas diferencias son el precio y el período de suscripción: con el plan anual ahorrarás en torno a un 30 % en comparación con 12 meses de un plan mensual.
¿Qué es Perlego?
Somos un servicio de suscripción de libros de texto en línea que te permite acceder a toda una biblioteca en línea por menos de lo que cuesta un libro al mes. Con más de un millón de libros sobre más de 1000 categorías, ¡tenemos todo lo que necesitas! Obtén más información aquí.
¿Perlego ofrece la función de texto a voz?
Busca el símbolo de lectura en voz alta en tu próximo libro para ver si puedes escucharlo. La herramienta de lectura en voz alta lee el texto en voz alta por ti, resaltando el texto a medida que se lee. Puedes pausarla, acelerarla y ralentizarla. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Es Semantics - Foundations, History and Methods un PDF/ePUB en línea?
Sí, puedes acceder a Semantics - Foundations, History and Methods de Klaus Heusinger, Claudia Maienborn, Paul Portner, Klaus Heusinger, Claudia Maienborn, Paul Portner en formato PDF o ePUB, así como a otros libros populares de Filología y Semántica lingüística. Tenemos más de un millón de libros disponibles en nuestro catálogo para que explores.

Información

Año
2019
ISBN
9783110393347
Edición
1
Categoría
Filología
Claudia Maienborn, Klaus von Heusinger and Paul Portner

1 Meaning in linguistics

Claudia Maienborn ,Tübingen, Germany
Klaus von Heusinger, Cologne, Germany
Paul Portner, Washington, DC, USA
  1. Introduction
  2. Truth
  3. Compositionality
  4. Context and discourse
  5. Meaning in contemporary semantics
  6. References
Abstract: The article provides an introduction to the study of meaning in modern semantics. Major tenets, tools, and goals of semantic theorizing are illustrated by discussing typical approaches to three central characteristics of natural language meaning: truth conditions, compositionality, and context and discourse.

1 Introduction

Meaning is a key concept of cognition, communication and culture, and there is a diversity of ways to understand it, reflecting the many uses to which the concept can be put. In the following we take the perspective on meaning developed within linguistics, in particular modern semantics, and we aim to explain the ways in which semanticists approach, describe, test and analyze meaning. The fact that semantics is a component of linguistic theory is what distinguishes it from approaches to meaning in other fields like philosophy, psychology, semiotics or cultural studies. As part of linguistic theory, semantics is characterized by at least the following features:
  1. Empirical coverage: It strives to account for meaning in all of the world’s languages.
  2. Linguistic interfaces: It operates as a subtheory of the broader linguistic system, interacting with other subtheories such as syntax, pragmatics, phonology and morphology.
  3. Formal expliciteness: It is laid out in an explicit and precise way, allowing the community of semanticists to jointly test it, improve it, and apply it to new theoretical problems and practical goals.
  4. Scientific paradigm: It is judged on the same criteria as other scientific theories, viz. coherence, conceptual simplicity, its ability to unify our understanding of diverse phenomena (within or across languages), to raise new questions and open up new horizons for research.
In the following we exemplify these four features on three central issues in modern semantic theory that define our understanding of meaning: truth conditions, compositionality, and context and discourse.

2 Truth

If one is to develop an explicit and precise scientific theory of meaning, the first thing one needs to do is to identify some of the data which the theory will respond to, and there is one type of data which virtually all work in semantics takes as fundamental: truth conditions. At an intuitive level, truth conditions are merely the most obvious way of understanding the meaning of a declarative sentence. If I say It is raining outside, I have described the world in a certain way. I may have described it correctly, in which case what I said is true, or I may have described it incorrectly, in which case it is false. Any competent speaker knows to a high degree of precision what the weather must be like for my sentence to count as true (a correct description) or false (an incorrect description). In other words, such a speaker knows the truth conditions of my sentence. This knowledge of truth conditions is extremely robust – far and wide, English speakers can make agreeing judgments about what would make my sentence true or false – and as a result, we can see the truth conditions themselves as a reliable fact about language which can serve as part of the basis for semantic theory.
While truth conditions constitute some of the most basic data for semantics, different approaches to semantics reckon with them in different ways. Some theories treat truth conditions not merely as the data which semantics is to deal with, but more than this as the very model of sentential meaning. This perspective can be summarized with the slogan “meaning is truth conditions”, and within this tradition, we find statements like the following:
(1) [[ It is raining outside ]]t,s = TRUE iff it is raining outside of the building where the speaker s is located at time t, and = FALSE otherwise.
The double brackets [[ X ]] around an expression X names the semantic value of X in the terms of the theory in question. Thus, (1) indicates a theory which takes the semantic value of a sentence to be its truth value, TRUE or FALSE. The meaning of the sentence, according to the truth conditional theory, is then captured by the entire statement (1).
Although (1) represents a truth conditional theory according to which semantic value and meaning (i.e., the truth conditions) are distinct (the semantic value is a crucial component in giving the meaning), other truth conditional theories use techniques which allow meaning to be reified, and thus identified with semantic value, in a certain sense. The most well-known and important such approach is based on possible worlds:
(2) a. [[ It is raining outside ]]w,t,s = TRUE iff it is raining outside of the building where the speaker s is located at time t in world w, and = FALSE otherwise.
b. [[ It is raining outside ]]t,s = the set of worlds {w : it is raining outside of the building where the speaker s is located at time t in world w}
A possible world is a complete way the world could be. (Other theories use constructs similar to possible worlds, such as situations.) The statement in (2a) says virtually the same thing as (1), making explicit only that the meaning of It is raining outside depends not merely on the actual weather outside, but whatever the weather may turn out to be. Crucially, by allowing the possible world to be treated as an arbitrary point of evaluation, as in (2a), we are able to identify the truth conditions with the set of all such points, as in (2b). In (2), we have two different kinds of semantic value: the one in (2a), relativized to world, time, and speaker, corresponds to (1), and is often called the extension or reference. That in (2b), where the world point of evaluation has been transferred into the semantic value itself, is then called the intension or sense. The sense of a full sentence, for example given as a set of possible worlds as in (2b), is called a proposition. Specific theories differ in the precise nature of the extension and intension: The intension may involve more or different parameters than w, t, s, and several of these may be gathered into a set (along with the world) to form the intension. For example, in tense semantics, we often see intensions treated as sets of pairs of a world and a time.
The majority of work in semantics follows the truth conditional approach to the extent of making statements like those in (1)–(2) the fundamental fabric of the theory. Scholars often produce explicit fragments, i.e. mini-theories which cover a subset of a language, which are actually functions from expressions of a language to semantic values, with the semantic values of sentences being truth conditional in the vein of (1)–(2). But not all semantic research is truth conditional in this explicit way. Descriptive linguistics, functional linguistics, typological linguistics and cognitive linguistics frequently make important claims about meaning (in a particular language, or crosslinguistically). For example, Wolfart (1973: 25), a descriptive study of Plains Cree states: “Semantically, direction serves to specify actor and goal. In sentence (3), for instances, the direct theme sign /ā/ indicates the noun atim as goal, whereas the inverse theme sign /ekw/ in (4) marks the same noun as actor.”
(3) nisēkihānān atim
scare(1p-3) dog(3)
‘We scare the dog.’
(4)nisēkihikonānatim
scare(3-1p)dog(3)
‘The dog scares us.’
Despite not being framed as such, this passage is implicitly truth conditional. Wolfart is stating a difference in truth conditions which depends on the grammatical category of direction using the descriptions “actor” and “goal”, and using the translations of cited examples. This example serves to illustrate the centrality of truth conditions to any attempt to think about the nature of linguistic meaning.
As a corollary to the focus on truth conditions, semantic theories typically take relations like entailment, synonymy, and contradiction to provide crucial data as well. Thus, the example sentence It is raining outside entails (5), and this fact is known to any competent speaker.
(5) It is raining outside or the kids are playing with the water hose.
Obviously, this entailment can be understood in terms of truth conditions (the truth of the one sentence guarantees the truth of the other), a fact which supports the idea that the analysis of truth conditions should be a central goal of semantics. It is less satisfying to describe synonymy in terms of truth conditions, as identity of truth conditions doesn’t in most cases make for absolute sameness of meaning, in an intuitive sense – consider Mary hit John and John was hit by Mary; nevertheless, a truth conditional definition of synonymy allows for at least a useful concept of synonymy, since people can indeed judge whether two sentences would accurately describe the same circumstances, whereas it’s not obvious that complete intuitive synonymy is even a useful concept, insofar as it may never occur in natural language.
The truth conditional perspective on meaning is intuitive and powerful where it applies, but in and of itself, it is only a foundation. It doesn’t, at first glance, say anythi...

Índice