Introduction to Logic
eBook - ePub

Introduction to Logic

Patrick Suppes

Condividi libro
  1. 336 pagine
  2. English
  3. ePUB (disponibile sull'app)
  4. Disponibile su iOS e Android
eBook - ePub

Introduction to Logic

Patrick Suppes

Dettagli del libro
Anteprima del libro
Indice dei contenuti
Citazioni

Informazioni sul libro

Part I of this coherent, well-organized text deals with formal principles of inference and definition. Part II explores elementary intuitive set theory, with separate chapters on sets, relations, and functions. Ideal for undergraduates.

Domande frequenti

Come faccio ad annullare l'abbonamento?
È semplicissimo: basta accedere alla sezione Account nelle Impostazioni e cliccare su "Annulla abbonamento". Dopo la cancellazione, l'abbonamento rimarrà attivo per il periodo rimanente già pagato. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui
È possibile scaricare libri? Se sì, come?
Al momento è possibile scaricare tramite l'app tutti i nostri libri ePub mobile-friendly. Anche la maggior parte dei nostri PDF è scaricabile e stiamo lavorando per rendere disponibile quanto prima il download di tutti gli altri file. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui
Che differenza c'è tra i piani?
Entrambi i piani ti danno accesso illimitato alla libreria e a tutte le funzionalità di Perlego. Le uniche differenze sono il prezzo e il periodo di abbonamento: con il piano annuale risparmierai circa il 30% rispetto a 12 rate con quello mensile.
Cos'è Perlego?
Perlego è un servizio di abbonamento a testi accademici, che ti permette di accedere a un'intera libreria online a un prezzo inferiore rispetto a quello che pagheresti per acquistare un singolo libro al mese. Con oltre 1 milione di testi suddivisi in più di 1.000 categorie, troverai sicuramente ciò che fa per te! Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui.
Perlego supporta la sintesi vocale?
Cerca l'icona Sintesi vocale nel prossimo libro che leggerai per verificare se è possibile riprodurre l'audio. Questo strumento permette di leggere il testo a voce alta, evidenziandolo man mano che la lettura procede. Puoi aumentare o diminuire la velocità della sintesi vocale, oppure sospendere la riproduzione. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui.
Introduction to Logic è disponibile online in formato PDF/ePub?
Sì, puoi accedere a Introduction to Logic di Patrick Suppes in formato PDF e/o ePub, così come ad altri libri molto apprezzati nelle sezioni relative a Matematica e Logica nella matematica. Scopri oltre 1 milione di libri disponibili nel nostro catalogo.

Informazioni

Anno
2012
ISBN
9780486138053

PART I

PRINCIPLES OF INFERENCE AND DEFINITION

CHAPTER 1

THE SENTENTIAL CONNECTIVES

To begin with, we want to develop a vocabulary which is precise and at the same time adequate for analysis of the problems and concepts of systematic knowledge. We must use vague language to create a precise language. This is not as silly as it seems. The rules of chess, for example, are a good deal more precise than those of English grammar, and yet we use English sentences governed by imprecise rules to state the precise rules of chess. In point of fact, our first step will be rather similar to drawing up the rules of a game. We want to lay down careful rules of usage for certain key words: ‘not’, ‘and’, ‘or’, ‘if ..., then...’, ‘if and only if’, which are called sentential connectives. The rules of usage will not, however, represent the rules of an arbitrary game. They are designed to make explicit the predominant systematic usage of these words; this systematic usage has itself arisen from reflection on the ways in which these words are used in ordinary, everyday contexts. Yet we shall not hesitate to deviate from ordinary usage whenever there are persuasive reasons for so doing.
§ 1.1 Negation and Conjunction. We deny the truth of a sentence by asserting its negation. For example, if we think that the sentence ‘Sugar causes tooth decay’ is false, we assert the sentence ‘Sugar does not cause tooth decay’. The usual method of asserting the negation of a simple sentence is illustrated in this example: we attach the word ‘not’ to the main verb of the sentence. However, the assertion of the negation of a compound sentence is more complicated. For example, we deny the sentence ‘Sugar causes tooth decay and whiskey causes ulcers’ by asserting ‘It is not the case that both sugar causes tooth decay and whiskey causes ulcers’. In spite of the apparent divergence between these two examples, it is convenient to adopt in logic a single sign for forming the negation of a sentence. We shall use the prefix ‘–’, which is placed before the whole sentence. Thus the negation of the first example is written:
-(Sugar causes tooth decay).
The second example illustrates how we may always translate ‘–’; we may always use ‘it is not the case that’.
The main reason for adopting the single sign ‘–’ for negation, regardless of whether the sentence being negated is simple or compound, is that the meaning of the sign is the same in both cases. The negation of a true sentence is false, and the negation of a false sentence is true.
We use the word ‘and’ to conjoin two sentences to make a single sentence which we call the conjunction of the two sentences. For example, the sentence ‘Mary loves John and John loves Mary’ is the conjunction of the sentence ‘Mary loves John’ and the sentence ‘John loves Mary’. We shall use the ampersand sign ‘&’ for conjunction. Thus the conjunction of any two sentences P and Q is written
P & Q.
The rule governing the use of the sigh i & is in close accord with ordinary usage. The conjunction of two sentences is true if and only if both sentences are true. We remark that in logic we may combine any two sentences to form a conjunction. There is no requirement that the two sentences be related in content or subject matter. Any combinations, however absurd, are permitted. Of course, we are usually not interested in sentences like ‘John loves Mary, and 4 is divisible buy 2’. Although it might seem desirable to have an additional rule stating that we may only conjoin two sentences which have a common subject matter, the undesirability of such a rule becomes apparent once we reflect on the vagueness of the notion of common subject matter.
Various words are used as approximate synonyms for ‘not’ and ‘and’ in ordinary language. For example, the word ‘never’ in the sentence:
I will never surrender to your demands
has almost the same meaning as ‘not’ in:
I will not surrender to your demands.
Yet it is true that ‘never’ carries a sense of continuing refusal which ‘not’ does not.
The word ‘but’ has about the sense of ‘and’, and we symbolize it by ‘&’, although in many cases of ordinary usage there are differences of meaning. For example, if a young woman told a young man:
I love you and I love your brother almost as well,
he would probably react differently than if she had said:
I love you but I love your brother almost as well.
In view of such differences in meaning, a natural suggestion is that different symbols be introduced for sentential connectives like ‘never’ and ‘but’. There is, however, a profound argument against such a course of action. The rules of usage agreed upon for negation and conjunction make these two sentential connectives truth-functional; that is, the truth or falsit...

Indice dei contenuti