The Value of Luxury
eBook - ePub

The Value of Luxury

An Emerging Perspective

Beata Stępień

Condividi libro
  1. English
  2. ePUB (disponibile sull'app)
  3. Disponibile su iOS e Android
eBook - ePub

The Value of Luxury

An Emerging Perspective

Beata Stępień

Dettagli del libro
Anteprima del libro
Indice dei contenuti
Citazioni

Informazioni sul libro

What does luxury value mean? What constitutes luxury, and what does not? While previous research has focused on luxury as a global business and how companies have generated, communicated and monetized luxury, this book draws on empirical research to examine how consumers understand and interact with it. It identifies the components of luxury value, as seen by consumers, and the most influential factors that shape these perceptions. Drawing on a range of disciplinary approaches, the author investigates how consumer segments differ in their perception of luxury products, and how different generations understand value. A comprehensive overview of consumer perceptions of luxury, this book is a must-read for those students and researchers interested in luxury studies.

Domande frequenti

Come faccio ad annullare l'abbonamento?
È semplicissimo: basta accedere alla sezione Account nelle Impostazioni e cliccare su "Annulla abbonamento". Dopo la cancellazione, l'abbonamento rimarrà attivo per il periodo rimanente già pagato. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui
È possibile scaricare libri? Se sì, come?
Al momento è possibile scaricare tramite l'app tutti i nostri libri ePub mobile-friendly. Anche la maggior parte dei nostri PDF è scaricabile e stiamo lavorando per rendere disponibile quanto prima il download di tutti gli altri file. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui
Che differenza c'è tra i piani?
Entrambi i piani ti danno accesso illimitato alla libreria e a tutte le funzionalità di Perlego. Le uniche differenze sono il prezzo e il periodo di abbonamento: con il piano annuale risparmierai circa il 30% rispetto a 12 rate con quello mensile.
Cos'è Perlego?
Perlego è un servizio di abbonamento a testi accademici, che ti permette di accedere a un'intera libreria online a un prezzo inferiore rispetto a quello che pagheresti per acquistare un singolo libro al mese. Con oltre 1 milione di testi suddivisi in più di 1.000 categorie, troverai sicuramente ciò che fa per te! Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui.
Perlego supporta la sintesi vocale?
Cerca l'icona Sintesi vocale nel prossimo libro che leggerai per verificare se è possibile riprodurre l'audio. Questo strumento permette di leggere il testo a voce alta, evidenziandolo man mano che la lettura procede. Puoi aumentare o diminuire la velocità della sintesi vocale, oppure sospendere la riproduzione. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui.
The Value of Luxury è disponibile online in formato PDF/ePub?
Sì, puoi accedere a The Value of Luxury di Beata Stępień in formato PDF e/o ePub, così come ad altri libri molto apprezzati nelle sezioni relative a Commerce e Comportement du consommateur. Scopri oltre 1 milione di libri disponibili nel nostro catalogo.

Informazioni

Anno
2020
ISBN
9783030512187
© The Author(s) 2021
B. StępieńThe Value of LuxuryPalgrave Advances in Luxuryhttps://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-51218-7_1
Begin Abstract

1. Value

Beata Stępień1
(1)
Poznań University of Economics and Business, Poznań, Poland
Beata Stępień
Keywords
GoodnessValueValue in useValue co-creationValue measures
End Abstract
Value, embodied in goods, services and in the process of offering them to customers, is today considered to be the core of business logic. The correct definition, measurement and analysis of value and the subsequent translation of its outcomes into action is essential for companies to be able to achieve competitive advantage (Gale et al. 1994; Woodruff and Gardial 1996, Holbrook 1996; Woodruff 1997; Payne and Holt 2001; Eggert and Ulaga 2002; Vargo and Lusch 2004).
The considered preparation of a value proposition depends first of all on recognizing what the value is and in what areas, activities consumers see it. However finding an answer to this question is one of the most difficult business tasks.
The problem of recognizing what has value for people and what it is and means for them is not only a matter of business practice. Questions about how people define value, prioritize its individual components and how they make decisions on the basis of valuation, have been the subject of scientific research for thousands of years and the search for answers to these questions has been dealt with by philosophers, sociologists, anthropologists, psychologists and economists.
This book assumes that people, when shopping, do so for a variety of reasons and that these actions always reflect their needs, although they may not always be realized. The rich and varying hierarchy of needs is derived from the individual’s value system. This evolves and changes under the influence of the environment, although it always reflects the individual’s worldview of what is good/bad, true/false, beautiful/ugly, wise/stupid etc. However economic sciences do not provide us with an answer to the question of what this value system, reflected later in economic choices, consists and how it works, because they do not explore it.1 However since the economic foundations of the models are based on foundations whose nature is recognized by other sciences it is the task of economists to constantly observe and take into account the achievements of the sciences which are concerned with mechanisms of individual and collective behaviour.
The following are the fragments of the scientific output of philosophy, sociology, psychology and economic sciences which contain the most important findings on how expected and experienced value can be perceived, what influences it and what relationships can take place between an individual and his or her environment, that then make them recognize something as valuable and influence their respective market choices.

1.1 Value as Philosophical Category

Philosophy is the science that has researched value and what it is for the longest time, in the most in-depth and consistent but mostly ethical and then aesthetic ways. In philosophy value is identified with virtue and goodness. Value is the main moral or transcendent category guiding the behaviour of individuals (Tatarkiewicz and Krajewski 1990, volume 1, p. 8). The theory of values is identified with an axiology within which it is examined/analyzed (see also Rogoziński 2011; Tischner 1993; Ingarden 1966; Znaniecki 1910):
  • the nature of values: what is valuable and good and what is its nature: subjective and therefore relative, or absolute and objective;
  • the sources, bases of value and the mechanisms of its creation, e.g. through valuation;
  • classification and prioritization of values; distinguishing between immanent and instrumental values, which serve to achieve the former;
  • shaping values in societies over a certain period of time and their impact on the lives of individuals and groups.
The above mentioned scope of axiology is a common subject of the research of philosophers, anthropologists, sociologists, cultural scientists, psychologists, or representatives of economic sciences (mainly those dealing with welfare economics or consumer behaviour), but the contribution of philosophers to the clarification and ordering of the first three aspects (apart from the analysis of valuation mechanisms) is the greatest.
This contribution of philosophy to knowing the nature of values is a consequence of the time and attention that has been devoted to it since the creation of the mother of all sciences. Questions about the nature of values have already been asked by classical philosophers and their views have become the nucleus of contemporary considerations evolving from monistic absolutism to pluralistic, epistemological, or finally post-modern value analysis.

1.1.1 The Essence and Foundation of Values in Philosophy—Immanent and Instrumental Values

The fundamental philosophical question (to which there is still no clear answer) is whether value (as a goodness, truth or beauty) exists in an objectified way or whether it is attributed to states (including things) by individuals. Philosophers have also been looking for what is the ultimate, most important value and try to determine what leads to it.
Many classical philosophical texts have attempted to prove that universal value as the supreme Goodness exists and is objective, independent of the judgement of individuals. Goodness has an immanent value, although various activities can lead to it, which by contributing to the achievement of goodness, have an instrumental value. This approach is evident in the Platonic recognition of value as a universal and transcendental category. Platonic absolutism is expressed in the claim that value exists independently of mankind and individual views and is expressed in moral standards superior even to God (Popkin and Stroll 1993, pp. 7–11). The continuators of such an approach can be found not only in classical, but also in contemporary philosophical texts. Almost all medieval philosophy was subordinated to this way of understanding reality, but it is also present in the form of categorical moral imperatives in Kant, in Rickert’s neocantism, Sheler’s phenomenology, or Hartmann’s texts (Hartmann 1987; Scheler 1973; Rickert 1986). In these perspectives values are ideal self-contained entities, existing independently of the perception of individuals and although contemporary philosophy has not abandoned the search for a universal, objectified value, it has to a large extent abandoned the perception of it as a monistic ideal.
In opposition to the trend of objectivity of values many, including classical philosophers, saw values as being dependent on the individual and differed in what they could constitute. Aristotle, a disciple of Plato, already questioned that Goodness was universal and claimed that people, in various ways of life, could consider it good because it was happy. Aristotle was therefore one of the first subjectivists and relativists of the value theory and for its quintessence (i.e. immanent value) he considered happiness—“the action of the soul in accordance with perfect virtue” (after Popkin and Stroll 1993, p. 7 et seq., Russell, p. 205). Happiness is not a goal but is created by human actions, engaging in various activities (which have instrumental value), and performing them gives a sense of happiness. People can achieve this by trial and error. According to Aristotle they will experience it to the fullest extent by acting in moderation and avoiding drifting towards extremes in which the virtues are to help them: courage as a means between cowardice and bravado; pride as a means between vanity and humility; and finally generosity as a means between profligacy and stinginess.
In philosophy the sources of values and ways of creating them were also sought. Epicur, the creator of hedonism, considered pleasure while avoiding suffering to be the overriding value, which today is mistakenly associated with the postulate of succumbing to temptations or making up for the senses as the overriding goal of human action (see e.g. Krokiewicz 1961; Popkin and Stroll 1993, pp. 19–26). According to Epicur only “net” pleasures have value, i.e. those that bring more pleasure than suffering not only to the individual but also to the environment. Epicur’s work has led to a distinction between the value of the means (an instrumental value) of achieving a goal and the value of the goal and effect itself. Thus the use of valuable, pleasant things can have a devastating effect (e.g. overeating sweets leads to obesity) and vice versa; fundamentally unpleasant activities can lead to net pleasure (e.g. tedious and painful exercises leading to improved health).

1.1.2 Value or Values, Coe...

Indice dei contenuti