Anarchy, State, and Utopia
eBook - ePub

Anarchy, State, and Utopia

An Advanced Guide

Lester H. Hunt

Condividi libro
  1. English
  2. ePUB (disponibile sull'app)
  3. Disponibile su iOS e Android
eBook - ePub

Anarchy, State, and Utopia

An Advanced Guide

Lester H. Hunt

Dettagli del libro
Anteprima del libro
Indice dei contenuti
Citazioni

Informazioni sul libro

Anarchy, State, and Utopia: An Advanced Guide presents a comprehensive and accessible introduction to the ideas expressed in Robert Nozick's highly influential 1974 work on free-market libertarianism—considered one of the most important and influential works of political philosophy published in the latter half of the 20th-century.

  • Makes accessible all the major ideas and arguments presented in Nozick's complex masterpiece
  • Explains, as well as critiques, Robert Nozick's theory of free market libertarianism
  • Enables a new generation of readers to draw their own conclusions about the wealth of timely ideas on individualism and libertarian philosophy
  • Indicates where Nozick's theory has explanatory power, where it is implausible, and where there are loose ends with further work to be done

Domande frequenti

Come faccio ad annullare l'abbonamento?
È semplicissimo: basta accedere alla sezione Account nelle Impostazioni e cliccare su "Annulla abbonamento". Dopo la cancellazione, l'abbonamento rimarrà attivo per il periodo rimanente già pagato. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui
È possibile scaricare libri? Se sì, come?
Al momento è possibile scaricare tramite l'app tutti i nostri libri ePub mobile-friendly. Anche la maggior parte dei nostri PDF è scaricabile e stiamo lavorando per rendere disponibile quanto prima il download di tutti gli altri file. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui
Che differenza c'è tra i piani?
Entrambi i piani ti danno accesso illimitato alla libreria e a tutte le funzionalità di Perlego. Le uniche differenze sono il prezzo e il periodo di abbonamento: con il piano annuale risparmierai circa il 30% rispetto a 12 rate con quello mensile.
Cos'è Perlego?
Perlego è un servizio di abbonamento a testi accademici, che ti permette di accedere a un'intera libreria online a un prezzo inferiore rispetto a quello che pagheresti per acquistare un singolo libro al mese. Con oltre 1 milione di testi suddivisi in più di 1.000 categorie, troverai sicuramente ciò che fa per te! Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui.
Perlego supporta la sintesi vocale?
Cerca l'icona Sintesi vocale nel prossimo libro che leggerai per verificare se è possibile riprodurre l'audio. Questo strumento permette di leggere il testo a voce alta, evidenziandolo man mano che la lettura procede. Puoi aumentare o diminuire la velocità della sintesi vocale, oppure sospendere la riproduzione. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui.
Anarchy, State, and Utopia è disponibile online in formato PDF/ePub?
Sì, puoi accedere a Anarchy, State, and Utopia di Lester H. Hunt in formato PDF e/o ePub, così come ad altri libri molto apprezzati nelle sezioni relative a Philosophy e Philosophy History & Theory. Scopri oltre 1 milione di libri disponibili nel nostro catalogo.

Informazioni

Anno
2015
ISBN
9781118880609
Edizione
1
Argomento
Philosophy

1
Nozick’s Introduction and Preface

1. Why Read a Book about a Book?

Robert Nozick’s Anarchy, State, and Utopia (hereafter ASU)1 created a sensation when it appeared in 1974. It won the National Book Award in 1975 and in 2008 was listed by the Times Literary Supplement as one of the hundred most influential books since World War II. It is certainly, and by far, one of the most influential philosophical books of the twentieth century, having had a strong impact, not merely on the tiny world of academic philosophy, but on many people in the great world outside the academy as well. And yet Nozick once described this book as “an accident.”2
As he told the story years later, he began writing it in the academic year of 1971–1972, which he spent at the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences near Stanford University. The original purpose for his stay there was to write on the problem of free will. Unfortunately, having come to California without having already worked out his views on the subject of fee will, he found himself spinning his wheels for several months. In early December, he was invited to give a talk to a student group at Stanford. In his talk he explained how he thought a state could arise out of conditions of anarchy. He then wrote these thoughts out. At about this time, his Harvard colleague John Rawls sent him a copy of his new book, A Theory of Justice.3 Nozick had read an earlier draft of the book and discussed it in detail with the author. Finding that the published version was quite different from the draft he had seen, he read it and was moved to set down his reflections on why he still disagreed with Rawls’ view. At the same time, he sketched out his own ideas on the subject of Rawls’ book: the problem traditionally known as that of “distributive justice.” By this time the original project on free will must have seemed to be receding into the impossibly far distance. However, he noticed that the two pieces he had written that year seemed to fit rather nicely with a paper he had produced for a 1969 session of the American Philosophical Association in which he presented a new conception of utopia. If he just elaborated these writings and added some connecting material he would have a book – and something to show for his year at the Center. So he set to work and by the time his stay there was over in July he had hammered out a draft.4 He then rewrote the whole work in the summer of 1973 (xv).
Nozick’s book is often compared and contrasted – mainly contrasted – with the one he received in the mail that January, A Theory of Justice. Rawls’ book does indeed have a very different history, and is a very different sort of book from Nozick’s, despite their overlapping subject matter. Nozick’s book came into existence rather suddenly and almost as an afterthought. In fact, it was only a few years earlier that he had first come to hold the radical point of view he defends there. On the other hand, Rawls’ work on the ideas presented in his 1971 book goes back at least as far as his 1951 paper, “Outline of a Decision Procedure in Ethics.”5 These ideas were subjected to a long and laborious process of working and reworking. Several drafts of Rawls’ book circulated widely in the philosophical community and were much commented upon. The book itself (the 1971 edition) is 607 pages long. In it, Rawls tries to forestall every misinterpretation of his views that he can think of, in addition to answering every sensible objection that comes to mind. (Notwithstanding all this work, people managed to disagree with it and even misunderstand it anyway.) Rawls’ aim in writing his book was, clearly, to establish something.
Readers of Nozick’s book soon realize that it is written with a sharply different end in view. It is not intended to present a closed system, nor to present irrefutable proofs that compel the reader’s assent at every turn – very far from it. Instead of the rigorous proofs that we expect from an analytic philosopher, what we often find are jokes, paradoxes, outlandish examples, and curious digressions. Though the author does have strong – some would say extreme – views on many of the subjects he discusses, and though he does argue brilliantly for them, his ultimate purpose is to indicate lines of further fruitful research and to stimulate the reader to further reflection. The fundamental impression on the reader is that thinking about these issues on a high level of sophistication is interesting and fun, and that we ought to come along and think with him. Where the great virtue of Rawls’ book is thoroughness, that of Nozick’s is brilliance. Where one strives for completeness, the other seeks to dazzle and amaze, even to amuse.
As we will see, Nozick’s book has the shortcomings of one that was written in this accidental way: There are many loose ends, abrupt transitions, digressions vaguely or poorly integrated into the whole, and (for those who insist that this is a shortcoming) plenty of unfinished business. However, it is also clearly a work of genius and, as such, it has virtues that only an “accidental” book can have: an air of genuine freshness and spontaneity. Among the writings of philosophers, that is something one usually only finds in published notebooks, or in the works of philosophers who write aphorisms, such as Nietzsche and Wittgenstein. It is very hard to think of another book by an Anglophone analytic philosopher (with the possible exception of other books by the same author, of course) in which this feeling of openness and fresh air can be found at all.
I think a book on ASU must take a different approach to its subject matter from the one that would be appropriate if the subject were A Theory of Justice. Since Rawls is trying to establish something once and for all, the commentator’s aim should be to say what it is that he is trying to establish, how he attempts to do so, and how close he comes to succeeding.
With Nozick, who is not trying to establish something once and for all, the approach must be different. My aim here is to support the further reflection Nozick is trying to stimulate, without (I hope!) completely euthanizing the sense of fun he instills. I will try to accomplish this by carrying out two broadly different functions. One is a matter of interpretation and explanation. ASU is at many points a rather difficult book to penetrate. Sometimes this is because of the complexity and profundity of the thoughts it expresses. At other times it is because the presentation of those thoughts is confusing, due, perhaps, to the rather hurried way in which it was written. In these cases I will do my best to straighten out the text and remove any difficulties that do not belong to the ideas themselves.
The other function I will be trying to carry out will be to engage critically with the text. We don’t read a book like ASU for its literary beauties – though it is generally well and often brilliantly written. We read such a book to see if it can help us to get closer to the truth on the great issues with which it deals. In what follows, I will point out what I see as the strengths and weaknesses of Nozick’s argument. I will indicate where the theory has explanatory power, where it is implausible, and where there are loose ends with further work to be done. I will also indicate ends that are not loose – that is, places where ideas are actually connected, sometimes in surprising ways, with ideas in other parts of the book. These connections often either explain or strengthen his argument. Sometimes I will suggest friendly amendments, so to speak: additions to a theory or argument that would make it stronger. Ultimately, my purpose will be neither to defend Nozick nor to attack him, but to try to indicate the wealth of things that can be learned by thinking about what he is saying.
Finally, I should say a word about the point of view from which I am writing this. In the first part of the book, Nozick attempts to show that a state can be both just and desirable. In the second, he presents reasons for thinking that no state more extensive than a “minimal state” is justified, in that such a state would necessarily violate individual rights. The third part, which is based on the paper on utopia, gives a reason why we should not mind the fact that, as he sees it, no more extensive state than a minimal one is justified. Rather, we should welcome it gladly. I think Nozick’s justification of the state is a failure, though an extremely interesting and instructive one. As to the conception of distributive justice presented in Part II, I think that, though it stands in need of amendment and correction, the needed changes are more or less in the spirit of his enterprise and that the amended doctrine would have very similar political implications. Further, I think that Part III, which is almost ignored in the secondary literature, is one of the most interesting parts of the book. The interest here may be more political than purely philosophical, but it is no less substantial for that. He succeeds in making a strong case that the seemingly austere state that he seeks to justify can appeal to the idealistic side of human nature.

2. The Preface

Though Nozick’s elegantly written preface needs no interpreting or straightening out, it might be useful to underscore some things he says there. He begins by straightforwardly revealing the platform upon which his argument will be based:
Individuals have rights and there are things no person or group may do to them (without violating their rights). So strong and far-reaching are these rights that they raise the question of what, if anything, the state and its officials may do.
He also tells us plainly the conclusion he will draw from his argument:
Our main conclusions … are that a minimal state, limited to the narrow functions of protection against force, theft, fraud … and so on is justified; that any more extensive state will violate persons’ rights not be forced to do certain things, and is unjustified; and that the minimal state is inspiring as well as right. Two noteworthy implications are that the state may not use its coercive apparatus for the purpose of getting some citizens to aid others, or in order to prohibit activities to people for their own good. (ix)
Among the sorts of coercion that are not justified, then, are forced redistribution of wealth and paternalistic coercion. This would obviously rule out many laws and policies now in effect.
He seems painfully aware that this is very far from the received view. He points out that, in a way, this puts him at a certain logical disadvantage compared to the adherents of the received view:
A codification of the received view … need not use elaborate arguments. It is thought to be an objection to other views merely to point out that they conflict with the view which readers wish anyway to accept. But a view which differs from the readers’ cannot argue for itself merely by pointing out that the received view conflicts with it! (x)
He is describing a rather odd sort of inference, one that always systematically aids the received view. If I react with horror to Nozick’s views because they are so “extreme” – supposing this means simply that they are very different from views commonly held – then the inference seems to be something like “your view is not the one commonly held, therefore it is wrong.” This is an inference that the critic of the common view cannot effectively reverse. The reverse argument, the one that would say, “well, the commonly held view is not mine, therefore it is wrong,” would obviously fall on deaf ears. And yet, from a purely logical point of view, these are exactly the same sort of argument. If one is a good argument, the other must be just as good, as far as their logic is concerned.
Some people would say, however, that they are not...

Indice dei contenuti