Altruism
eBook - ePub

Altruism

The Power of Compassion to Change Yourself and the World

Matthieu Ricard

Share book
  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Altruism

The Power of Compassion to Change Yourself and the World

Matthieu Ricard

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

In Happiness, Matthieu Ricard demonstrated that true happiness is not tied to fleeting moments or sensations, but is an enduring state of soul rooted in mindfulness and compassion for others. Now he turns his lens from the personal to the global, with a rousing argument that altruism - genuine concern for the well-being of others - could be the saving grace of the 21st century.

Altruism is, he believes, the vital thread that can answer the main challenges of our time: the economy in the short term, life satisfaction in the mid-term, and environment in the long term. Ricard's message has been taken up by major economists and thinkers, including Dennis Snower, Amartya Sen, Joseph Stiglitz, and George Soros.

Matthieu Ricard makes a robust and passionate case for cultivating altruistic love and compassion as the best means for simultaneously benefitting ourselves and our society. It's a fresh outlook on an ardent struggle - and one that just might make the world a better place.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on ā€œCancel Subscriptionā€ - itā€™s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time youā€™ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlegoā€™s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan youā€™ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, weā€™ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Altruism an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Altruism by Matthieu Ricard in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Social Sciences & Sociology. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2015
ISBN
9780857897008
1 The Nature of Altruism
Some Definitions
Is altruism a motivation, a momentary state of mind that aims at accomplishing the good of others, or a disposition to care for others in a benevolent way, pointing to a more lasting character trait? Deļ¬nitions abound and, sometimes, contradict each other. If we want to show that real altruism exists and help it spread throughout society, it is necesĀ­sary to clarify the meaning of this term.
The word ā€œaltruism,ā€ derived from the Latin alter, ā€œother,ā€ was used for the ļ¬rst time in the nineteenth century by Auguste Comte, one of the fathers of sociology and the founder of positivism. Altruism, accordĀ­ing to Comte, implies ā€œthe elimination of selļ¬sh desire and of egocenĀ­trism, as well as leading a life devoted to the well-being of others.ā€1
The American philosopher Thomas Nagel explains that altruism is ā€œa willingness to act in consideration of the interests of the other perĀ­son, without the need of ulterior motive.ā€2 It is a rational determinaĀ­tion to act stemming from ā€œthe direct inļ¬‚uence of one personā€™s interest on the actions of another, simply because in itself the interest of the former provides the latter with a reason to act.ā€ 3
Other thinkers, conļ¬dent in the potential for benevolence present in humans, go further and, like the American philosopher Stephen Post, deļ¬ne altruistic love as ā€œunselļ¬sh delight in the well-being of others, and engagement in acts of care and service on their behalf. Unlimited love extends this love to all others without exception, in an enduring and constant way.ā€4 The agapeĀÆ of Christianity is an uncondiĀ­tional love for other human beings, while altruistic love and compasĀ­sion in Buddhism, maitri and karuna, extend to all sentient beings, humans and non-humans.
Some authors emphasize putting intentions into practice, while others think it is motivation that deļ¬nes altruism. The psychologist Daniel Batson, who has devoted his career to the study of altruism, points out that ā€œaltruism is a motivational state with the ultimate goal of increasing anotherā€™s welfare.ā€5 He clearly distinguishes altruism as ultimate goal (my explicit aim is to accomplish othersā€™ welfare) from altruism as means (I accomplish othersā€™ welfare with a view to fulļ¬llĀ­ing my own well-being). In his eyes, for a motivation to be altruistic, the well-being of others must constitute a goal in itself.6
Among the other modes of altruism, goodness corresponds to a way of being that translates into actions as soon as circumstances allow; benevolence, from the Latin benevole, ā€œto want the well-being [of the other],ā€ is a favorable disposition toward others, accompanied by a desire to act upon that desire. Solicitude consists of caring in a lasting way and with vigilance about anotherā€™s fate: concerned about his situation, one is anxious to provide for his needs, promote his well-being, and remedy his suffering. Dedication consists of selļ¬‚essly placing oneself in the service of persons or a cause beneļ¬cial to society. Kindness is a form of caring, warm-hearted consideration that is manifested in the way we behave toward others. Fraternity stems from the feeling of belonging to the great human family whose every representative is perceived as a brother or sister whose fate matters to us; fraternity also evokes the ideas of harmony, cohesion, and union. The feeling of solidarity with a more or less extensive group of people is born when all must confront together common challenges and obstacles. By extension, this feeling can be experienced for the most destitute, or for those who are affected by a catastrophe; it is the community of fate that unites us.
Action Alone Does Not Define Altruism
In her book entitled The Heart of Altruism, Kristen Monroe, professor of political science and philosophy at the University of Irvine at CaliĀ­fornia, suggests we reserve the term ā€œaltruismā€ for actions carried out for the well-being of others at the price of some risk for ourselves, without expecting anything in return. According to her, good intenĀ­tions are indispensable for altruism, but they are not enough. One must act, and action must have a precise goal, that of contributing to the well-being of another.7
Monroe does acknowledge, however, that motivations for an action count more than their results.8 So it seems preferable to us not to restrict the use of the term altruism to external behavior, since actions do not in themselves allow us to know with certainty the motivation that inspired them. Just as the appearance of undesirable and unforeĀ­seen consequences does not call into question the altruistic nature of an action meant for the good of the other, so a hindrance to taking action, which is beyond the control of the one who wants to act, does not at all diminish the altruistic nature of his motivation.
Moreover, for Monroe, an action cannot be considered altruistic if it does not bear a risk and has no ā€œcost,ā€ however potential, for the one who performs it. In our opinion, an altruistic individual will indeed be ready to take risks to accomplish good for others, but the simple fact of taking risks for someone else is neither necessary nor sufļ¬cient to qualify as altruistic behavior. One can imagine an individual putĀ­ting himself in danger to help someone with the idea of gaining his trust and drawing personal advantages from it sufļ¬ciently desirable to justify the perils encountered. Whatā€™s more, some people agree to court danger for purely selļ¬sh reasons ā€” to seek glory, for instance, by carĀ­rying out a dangerous exploit. On the other hand, a behavior can be sincerely devoted to the good of the other, without bearing any notable risk whatever. The one who, moved by benevolence, gives away part of his wealth or devotes years to a charity organization helping people in need does not necessarily take a risk; but his behavior deserves to be qualiļ¬ed as altruistic, in our sense of it.
It Is Motivation That Colors Our Actions
Our motivations, whether they are benevolent, malevolent or neutral, color our actions. One cannot distinguish altruistic behavior from selļ¬sh behavior, a lie meant to do good from another uttered to harm, by the sole appearance of actions. If a mother suddenly pushes her child to the side of the street to prevent it from being run over by a car, her action is violent only in appearance. If someone approaches you with a big smile and showers you with compliments with the sole aim of swindling you, his conduct may seem benevolent, but his intentions are obviously selļ¬sh.
Keeping in mind our limited ability to control outer events or anticipate the turn they will take in the long run, we cannot qualify an act as either altruistic or selļ¬sh on the basis of the simple observation of its immediate consequences. Giving drugs or a glass of alcohol to someone who is undergoing a detox cure, with the excuse that he is suffering from abstention symptoms, will no doubt provide him with much-appreciated temporary relief, but such an action will do him no good in the long run.
On the other hand, in every circumstance, it is possible for us to examine our motivations attentively and honestly, and to do our best to determine if they are selļ¬sh or altruistic. More often than not, we neglect to do so. It is also easy to misperceive our true motive. This is why Buddhist teachings emphasize the need to look again and again into the mirror of oneā€™s mind to check our motivations.
In his book Altruism in Humans, Daniel Batson offers a set of criteria by which we can qualify our motivations as altruistic.9
Altruism requires a motivation: an instinctive reļ¬‚ex or automatic behavior cannot be qualiļ¬ed as either altruistic or selļ¬sh, whatever the beneļ¬cial or harmful consequences may be.
The difference between altruism and selļ¬shness is qualitative: it is the quality of our motivation and not its intensity that determines its altruistic nature.
Various motivations, altruistic and selļ¬sh, can coexist in our minds, and create a motivational conļ¬‚ict when we simultaneously consider our interests and the otherā€™s.
Moreover, we sometimes act in ways that beneļ¬t others for reasons that are neither altruistic nor selļ¬sh, especially out of a sense of duty or to respect the law.
Carrying thought into action may depend on various factors that are beyond our control. This alone does not fundamentally change the altruistic or selļ¬sh nature of our motivations.
Altruism does not require a personal sacriļ¬ce: it can even lead to personal beneļ¬ts, provided that those beneļ¬ts do not constitute the ultimate goal of our behavior, but are only secondary consequences of it.
In essence, altruism does indeed reside in the motivation that animates oneā€™s behavior. Altruism can be regarded as authentic so long as the desire for the otherā€™s welfare constitutes our ultimate goal, even if our motivation has not yet been transformed into actions.
By contrast, a selļ¬sh person considers others as instruments in the service of his own interests. He does not hesitate to neglect, or even to sacriļ¬ce, the good of the other when that turns out to be useful to reach his ends.
The Importance of Valuing the Otherā€™s ...

Table of contents