I
Introductory
1
The theoretical absurd: an introduction
Now I knew that Jean-Paul Sartre and Mr Camus were right when they claimed it is the Absurd that matters. The Absurd with a most capital A ⊠(Jeanette Winterson, âHoly Matrimonyâ, in The World and Other Places, 1998)
The philosophical absurd
The âAbsurdâ (which henceforth will normally be spelt without the capital letter and mostly without quotation marks) appears not to be, as such, a fully accredited philosophical category. That is to say, at least, that it is not accorded its own entry in the major philosophical encyclopedias (for instance the multi-volumed works edited by Paul Edwards [En. Phil.] in 1967, and by Edward Craig in 1998). It does receive a brief entry in The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, as the âterm used by existentialists to describe that which one might have thought to be amenable to reason but which turns out to be beyond the limits of rationalityâ, the thought of Sartre being cited as the prime (if âmistakenâ) example (TRB, in Honderich, 1995, 3). It enjoys, though, far more currency in literature, or comprises âan important aspect of the broader cultural context of existentialismâ (ibid.), where it has become the subject (in either a general or a particular sense) of a number of monographs and has given the name to the now widely familiar âtheatre of the absurdâ â this phrase itself having been coined by Martin Esslin in his book of that title, the first edition of which was published in 1961.
Chris Baldick, in
The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Literary Terms (1990), explains the absurd as âa term derived from the existentialism of Albert Camus, and often applied to the modern sense of human purposelessness in a universe without meaning or valueâ; he goes on to single out the works of Kafka, âin which the characters face alarmingly incomprehensible predicamentsâ, and to stress the âtheatre of the absurdâ
phenomenon, highlighting Beckettâs
Waiting for Godot (originally written in French as
En attendant Godot, 1952). Already we gather that existentialism and purposelessness feature strongly as key concepts, while Sartre, Camus and Beckett are seen as leading exponents in thought and literature.
Websterâs New Collegiate Dictionary confirms the noun âabsurdâ as âthe state or condition in which man exists in an irrational and meaningless universe and in which manâs life has no meaning outside his own existenceâ, while âabsurdismâ is defined as a philosophy based on this, and on the belief that â[manâs] search for order brings him into conflict with his universeâ (adding âcompare EXISTENTIALISMâ). The
Oxford English Dictionary gives the original meaning of absurd as âout of harmonyâ â initially in a musical sense, but subsequently and more generally out of harmony âwith reason or propriety; incongruous, unreasonable, illogicalâ, or in modern everyday parlance âridiculous, sillyâ. Peter L. Berger (175) chooses to stress the Latin derivation:
absurdum âliterally means out of deafnessâ.
1 All of these qualities may well contribute to a literary understanding of the absurd.
Ionescoâs conception of the absurd is âthat which is devoid of purpose ⊠Cut off from his religious, metaphysical, and transcendental roots, man is lost; all his actions become senseless, absurd, uselessâ (quoted from Esslin, Th. Abs., 23). For Sartre, absurdity is not âsillyâ, but âcontingentâ (Danto, 24), while, with the thought of Hume in mind, Terry Eagleton (in his study of tragedy, Sweet Violence, 223) comments that âThe price we pay for our liberty is contingency, which is never very far from absurdityâ. William Lane Craig refers to âthe hopeless absurdities of the Megaric schoolâ; these pre-Socratics (who were dismissed as of âno particularsâ by Erasmus in his Praise of Folly (23) âhad denied all becoming and change in the worldâ (W.L. Craig, 27; 20). The seeds of irrationality, therefore, are lurking throughout the history of western thought; a sense of paradox and ambiguity, and the decline of religious faith are all of the essence. And Existenz, âthe existence of a human beingâ, Kierkegaard argued, âis prior to âessenceââ (Passmore, 468); Sartre, in consequence, holds too that existence âprecedesâ essence (Danto, 24). For Camus, in his key treatise for an understanding of the absurd, The Myth of Sisyphus (ostensibly written as an enquiry into suicide), âthe absurd is sin without Godâ (Camus, Myth, 42); it is also âthe revolt of the fleshâ (ibid., 20) â what John Macquarrie (Existentialism, 77) terms âheroic absurdity in Camusâ. There have always been constraints imposed on the posing of the most difficult questions, from Aristotleâs injunction, âone must stopâ, to Kantâs caution over those âabsurdâ questions that ânot only [bring] shame on the propounder of the question, but may betray an incautious listener into absurd answersâ (Critique of Pure Reason: cited Fotiade, 197). The shame of absurdity can therefore call forth moderation!
Ontology, Nihilism, Existentialism
Logic is doubtless unshakeable, but it cannot withstand a man who wants to go on living. (Franz Kafka, The Trial, 1914â15)
As good a starting point as any, perhaps, is the ontological conundrum. Heideggerâs question, âwhy is there anything at all and not rather nothing?â (Sartreâs protagonist Roquentin also wishes to wonder âhow it was that a world should exist rather than nothingâ:
Nausea, 192),
2 was earlier put in the same or similar form by Leibniz and by Schelling, Unamuno (in his
The Tragic Sense of Life, 105), and probably many others: Donald A. Crosby (131) calls it âthat favorite question of Western philosophersâ.
3 The question was later to pass from Heidegger to Ionesco. A negative answer, or even uncertainty, would appear to be but a short step from ânihilismâ and, for most commentators, absurdity is to be equated with nihilism. The objection to, for instance, the cosmological argument of Leibniz, that âthere is no sufficient reason for the universe, that it is simply unintelligible ⊠raises serious existential questionsâ, writes W.L. Craig (287), âsince it implies that man and the universe are ultimately meaninglessâ: again nihilism. âThe wonder of Greek metaphysicsâ, Michael Weston (96) stresses, âis directed toward this: that reality is intelligibleâ. Referring to ânegative doctrines in religion or moralsâ, or âan extreme form of scepticismâ (
OED), nihilism is a term commonly held to have been popularised by Turgenevâs novel
Fathers and Sons (or
Fathers and Children:
Ottsy i deti, 1862), through his protagonist Bazarov â although the
OED cites a number of earlier usages of the word.
Possibly the first nihilist thinker was Gorgias of Leontini (a contemporary of Socrates), whose treatise On Nature propounded the tripartite reasoning, according to which: firstly, âthat nothing isâ; secondly, âthat even if it is, it cannot be comprehendedâ; and thirdly âthat even if it can be comprehended, it cannot be communicatedâ (G.B. Keferd, En. Phil., 3:374â5). Gorgias maintains that âwe cannot say of a thing either that it is or is not, without absurd resultsâ. Appropriately enough too, for a precursor of the absurdists, this treatise has sometimes been taken as a parody or philosophical joke, or purely as a rhetorical exercise. As we shall see, it may have had a formative impact on Beckett, among others. Metaphysics, from the Greeks onwards, assumes or determines (or presumes to determine) âa ground for our ways of thinking and relating to what isâ; this ground, which âmust lie beyond languageâ, is undercut, denied or deconstructed by more recent thinkers (from Nietzsche to Derrida) in âthe death of Godâ or the lack of a âtranscendental signifiedâ (see Weston, 116â17). Nietzscheâs criticism of knowledge, or âsecret history of philosophersâ, according to Roberto Calasso (The Forty-Nine Steps, 17â18), amounted to a âhistory of nihilismâ.
The absurd, then, is born of nihilism, out of existentialism, fuelled by the certainty of death (anxiety, dread and death being the scourge of the existentialist). Eagleton (9) reminds us that âfor a certain strain of existentialist philosophy death is tragic as such, regardless of its cause, mode, subject or effectâ. So too is life; Crosby (30â1), in the spirit of Schopenhauer, puts it thus:
The existential nihilist judges human existence to be pointless and absurdâŠ.
⊠The only feasible goal for anyone who understands the human condition is the abandonment of all goals and the cultivation of a spirit of detached resignation while awaiting lifeâs last and greatest absurdity, an annihilating death that wipes us so cleanly from the slate of existence as to make it appear that we had never lived.
âIf consciousness is, as some inhuman thinker has said,â writes the Spanish âphilosopher of lifeâ Miguel de Unamuno, in his treatise on
The Tragic Sense of Life (13), ânothing more than a flash of light between two eternities of darkness, then there is nothing more execrable than existenceâ. â[T]he real discovery of deathâ, made independently by the Jews and the Greeks, he affirms (62), had constituted âthe entrance into spiritual pubertyâ. Death for Sartre âis just the final absurdity, neither more nor less absurd than life itselfâ (Macquarrie, 198). Macquarrie conjectures (195): âIs it not absurd even to imagine that one could arrive at an existential understanding of death?â As for notions of immortality through living on in oneâs descendants, in oneâs created works, or âin the universal consciousnessâ â all of this âis but vague verbiage which satisfies only those who suffer from affective stupidityâ (Unamuno, 16). Even the notion of posthumous survival (were it believable) would not necessarily help very much; for absurdist existential nihilists, Crosby avers (172), indeed âthe very prospect of a perfect afterlife can make our existence on this earth seem scandalous and absurdâ (for similar thoughts, see, for instance, the theoretical physicist Paul Davies, 111; 154). For Nietzsche, indeed, âthe compensatory belief in heaven (âthe Land of Back and Beyondâ)â merely âreduces the value and dignity of physical existenceâ (Stern, 93).
4 Without it, and in the teeth of the suffering of this world, âto live is to teeter for a few brief moments over an abyss, and then to be hurled indifferently into its depthsâ (Crosby, 57). Nevertheless, Leszek KoĆakowski suggests (in his
Metaphysical Horror, 58): âIt is perhaps better for us to totter insecurely on the edge of an unknown abyss than simply to close our eyes and deny its existenceâ. And time, of course, is the âworst enemyâ (Camus,
Myth, 20).
Existentialism concerns itself first and foremost with the subject, rather than the object. The personal pronoun â âIâ â represents âan existent who
stands out (the basic meaning of âexistingâ: my emphasis.) as this existent
and no otherâ (Macquarrie, 73). âExistentialism has its roots in German Romanticismâ, affirms John Passmore (467), although Pascal, St Augustine and Socrates are often credited as precursors. Arthur C. Danto (20) confirms that Sartre, for instance, âhas worked always ⊠within the dry array of distinctions of a largely scholastic metaphysicsâ. Kierkegaard, though, is commonly held to be the father of existentialism in its modern form,
5 with strong elements of pessimism coming from Schopenhauer
6 and of negation from Nietzsche; Lesley Chamberlain (90), indeed, affirms that Nietzsche might be called âthe First Existentialistâ. For Nietzsche, human orders in any guise were âvain attempts to draw a veil over the âghastly absurdity of existenceââ and his thinking, Catherine Bates affirms, had an immense effect thereafter on theory and philosophy: âDismantling the presupposition that order and meaning might inhere within the world, Nietzsche pulled the rug from under every theoristâs feet, orbiting himself and those who follow him into deconstructive free fallâ (Bates, v). Put in a not dissimilar way by Chamberlain (7â8): âHe questioned whether Western philosophy since Plato had any meaning in the face of the absurd and irrational forces underlying human life, symbolized by Dionysusâ.
Although a number of thinkers have contributed to existentialism as we now think of it (Berdyaev, Shestov, Unamuno and Karl Jaspers,
7 for instance; and â more recently and more significantly â Heidegger, Camus and Sartre), there is, in Macquarrieâs view, âno common body of doctrine to which all existentialists subscribeâ; it is therefore to be regarded not so much as a âphilosophyâ but rather as a âstyle of philosophizingâ (Macquarrie, 14). Ramona Fotiade distinguishes between âthe âexistentialâ line of thoughtâ (as developed in particular by Lev Shestov and Benjamin Fondane) and âthe emerging âExistentialismâ of the 1930sâ (Fotiade, 7). Alasdair Macintyre declares that âany formula sufficiently broad to embrace all the major existentialist tendencies would necessarily be so general and so vague as to be vacuousâ; for that matter, he avers, âas in theology so in politics existentialism appears to be compatible with almost every possible standpointâ (in
En. Phil., 3:147; 151).
Part of the paradoxical nature of existentialist thought involves âa kind of love-hate relationship in which elements of belief and disbelief are intertwinedâ (Macquarrie, 19). Dostoevsky has provided perhaps the finest novelistic illustrations of this contradiction, while in a famous epistolary comment he proclaimed that, were Christ ever proved to lie outside the truth, he would himself prefer to remain with Christ.
8 Within the tradition of mysticism, Meister Eckhart, âin a surprising fit of heresyâ (according to Camus:
Rebel, 25), declared that âhe prefers Hell with Jesus to Heaven without Himâ. Camus, however, states that, for âthe absurd manâ, âseeking what is true is not seeking what is desirableâ (
Myth, 43); we shall look in
Chapter 4 at Dostoevskyâs impact on Camus.
âSignificationâ, Gilles Deleuze extrapolates from Descartes, âdoes not establish the truth without also establishing the possibility of error. For this reasonâ, he continues, âthe condition of truth is not opposed to the false, but to the absurdâ â defined as âthat which is without signification or that which may be neither true nor falseâ (Deleuze, 14â15). Kierkegaard places his notion of ârepetitionâ (belonging to a different dimension of thought and analogous in part to Nietzscheâs âeternal returnâ) within the sphere of the absurd, or âthe level at which religious faith defies logical reasoning, ⊠at which individual, exceptional, unique occurrences disrupt the âchrono-logicalâ discourse, the homogeneous flux of historical continuityâ (Fotiade, 160).
Kierkegaard, having â even before Nietzsche â deconstructed the tenets of Christianity, nevertheless chooses (like Dostoevsky) a blind leap into Christian faith â which may be compared to Pascalâs famous wager.
9 Bates, however, raises the question as to whether God would necessarily have kept his side of the Pascalian bargain and sees the logic of this as having been, in any case, philosophically âfirst and most rigorously blown apartâ by Nietzscheâs insistence that âthe assumption of a logical world was ⊠no more than a presuppositionâ (Bates, 40; 55; 69). Nietzsche...