Herbert Marcuse
eBook - ePub

Herbert Marcuse

A Critical Reader

John Abromeit, W. Mark Cobb, John Abromeit, W. Mark Cobb

Share book
  1. 288 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Herbert Marcuse

A Critical Reader

John Abromeit, W. Mark Cobb, John Abromeit, W. Mark Cobb

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

The Legacy of Herbert Marcuse: A Critical Reader is a collection of brand new papers by seventeen Marcuse scholars, which provides a comprehensive reassessment of the relevance of Marcuse's critical theory at the beginning of the 21st century.
Although best known for his reputation in critical theory, Herbert Marcuse's work has had impact on areas as diverse as politics, technology, aesthetics, psychoanalysis and ecology. This collection addresses the contemporary relevance of Marcuse's work in this broad variety of fields and from an international perspective.
In Part One, veteran scholars of Marcuse and the Frankfurt school examine the legacy of various specific areas of Marcuse's thought, including the quest for radical subjectivity, the maternal ethic and the negative dialectics of imagination. Part Two focuses on a very new trend in Marcuse scholarship: the link between Marcuse's ideas and environmental thought. The third part of this collection is dedicated to the work of younger Marcuse scholars, with the aim of documenting Marcuse's reception among the next generation of critical theorists. The final section of the book contains recollections on Marcuse's person rather than his critical theory, including an informative look back over his life by his son, Peter.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Herbert Marcuse an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Herbert Marcuse by John Abromeit, W. Mark Cobb, John Abromeit, W. Mark Cobb in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Filosofia & Storia e teoria della filosofia. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2014
ISBN
9781134700493

Part IVeteran Scholars' Reflections on Marcuse's Theoretical Legacy

1 Marcuse's Legacies

Angela Y. Davis 1
DOI: 10.4324/9780203755013-2
Any attempt to identify the plural legacies of Herbert Marcuse’s life and work must seriously engage the political contexts of his writings as well as the discourse that has entombed his theoretical contributions within the history of radical activism during the 1960s. Academics and activists alike find it difficult to disassociate Marcuse from the era of the late 1960s and early 1970s. His persona and his work are often evoked as a marker of a radical era, our primary relationship to which tends to be defined by nostalgia. Consequently, the mention of the name Herbert Marcuse elicits a sigh; many of my generation and older tend to treat him as a sign of our youth — wonderful, exciting, revolutionary, but meaningful only within the context of our reminiscences. As those of us who came of age during the 1960s and early 1970s grow older and older, there seems to be a tendency to spatialize “the sixties.” Recently I have noticed that many people of my generation like to introduce themselves by saying “I come from the sixties” — the 1960s being viewed as a point of origin, an originary place, rather than a historical moment. It is a place that we evoke with wonder and joy, but one that is forever beyond our reach. Ironically, the very era during which we were encouraged by Herbert Marcuse to think about the radical potential of utopian thought has itself survived in our historical memory as utopia — as a place that is no place.
It is no less ironic that the most well-known and most widely read thinker associated with the Frankfurt School thirty years ago became the least studied in the 1980s and 1990s, while Theodor Adorno, Max Horkheimer, and Walter Benjamin are extensively studied in the contemporary era. As Marcuse himself acknowledged, his celebrity had both productive and counter-productive aspects. But we can say that the historical conjuncture that linked his own intellectual development with the search for a new political vocabulary during the late 1960s allowed many of us to understand the extent to which he took seriously the charge of critical theory to develop interdisciplinary approaches, anchored in the emancipatory promise of the philosophical tradition within which he worked, that would signal the possibility and need for transformative interventions in the real, social world. And many of Marcuse’s ideas during that period evolved in conversation with the contemporaneous social and cultural movements. When he addressed gatherings of young people from California to Paris to Berlin, he spoke as a philosopher who was perennially struggling with the challenges of critical theory to engage directly with contemporary social issues. He was received as a philosopher who urged participants in radical social movements to think more philosophically and more critically about the implications of their activism.
Despite my chronic critiques of nostalgia as an inadequate substitute for historical memory, I want to ask you to permit me to engage in what I would like to think of as a bit of productive nostalgia. Because I do long for the days of interminable philosophical discussions about such subjects as the historical agents of revolution, when the participants in such discussions might be students and professors, as well as organic intellectuals who were workers and organizers. Marcuse’s interventions as a public intellectual helped to stimulate such discussions. Did the working class still have a revolutionary potential? What role could students play? I imagine that I am nostalgic today because so few people seem to believe that anybody has any revolutionary potential left .
The thinkers associated with the Frankfurt School were motivated in many of their intellectual endeavors by the desire to develop oppositional — which at that time meant anti-fascist — theoretical work. Herbert Marcuse and Franz Neumann (whose work should also be more seriously read today) were more interested in exploring more immediate oppositional possibilities than their colleagues Adorno and Horkheimer. The first volume of Herbert Marcuse’s collected papers, edited by Doug Kellner, contains a prospectus, written in the late 1930s or early 1940s, for a study on which they apparently planned to collaborate — “A History of the Doctrine of Social Change.” 2 While this study was not actualized as a result of the outbreak of the Second World War, both Neuman and Marcuse were active in the denazification program after the war — Neuman in the prosecution of Nazis, Marcuse in his work with the State Department helping to develop the US denazification policy. I urge you to read the recently published posthumous work, 3 especially because of the mystery surrounding Marcuse’s involvement with the State Department — including the absurd rumors that he was a CIA agent. The first volume of the unpublished papers Kellner has made available allows us to see the important work he did on the cultural impact of Nazism.
Perhaps Marcuse’s willingness to engage so directly in this anti-fascist project in the aftermath of the Second World War led him to later broaden his anti-fascist theoretical approach, drawing US society into the frame of his analysis. In other words, precisely because he was so immediately involved in opposing German fascism, he was also able and willing to identify fascist tendencies in the US. Because Adorno’s and Horkheimer’s anti-fascism expressed itself on a more formal theoretical register, it remained anchored in German history and tradition. When Marcuse wrote “The Struggle Against Liberalism in the Totalitarian View of the State,” 4 arguing that fascism and liberalism were not political opposites — that, indeed, they were closely linked ideologically — he had already established the foundation for his later analysis of US society. When Horkheimer and Adorno returned to Frankfurt and refused to permit the publication of Dialectic of Enlightenment, Marcuse’s critical theory would explore the one-dimensional society in the US and would later identify the prominent role of racism, encouraging students like myself to attempt to further develop the emancipatory promise of the German philosophical tradition.
One of the most salient and persistent aspects of Marcuse’s work is his concern with the possibilities of utopia. This powerful philosophical concept (which meant that he had to contest the orthodox equation of Marxist notions of socialism with the “scientific” as opposed to a “utopian” socialism a la Fourier) was at the core of his ideas. In his important 1937 essay, “Philosophy and Critical Theory,” he wrote:
Like philosophy, [critical theory] opposes making reality into a criterion in the manner of complacent positivism. But unlike philosophy, it always derives its goals from present tendencies of the social process. Therefore it has no fear of the utopia that the new order is denounced as being. When truth cannot be realized within the established social order, it always appears to the latter as mere utopia. This transcendence speaks not against, but for, its truth. The utopian element was long the only progressive element in philosophy, as in the constructions of the best state and the highest pleasure, of perfect happiness and perpetual peace. The obstinacy that comes from adhering to truth against all appearances has given way in contemporary philosophy to whimsy and uninhibited opportunism. Critical theory preserves obstinacy as a genuine quality of philosophical thought. 5
This obstinacy is most productive, I believe, when it travels from one generation to the next, when new ways of identifying those promises and new oppositional discourses and practices are proposed. In this context, I want to acknowledge the important intergenerational character of this conference. 6 In a passage from the introduction to an Essay on Liberation that many of you — old as well as new Marcuse scholars — have probably committed to memory, Marcuse writes that
what is denounced as “utopian” is no longer that which has “no place” and cannot have any place in the historical universe, but rather that which is blocked from coming about by the power of the established societies. Utopian possibilities are inherent in the technical and technological forces of advanced capitalism and socialism_ the rational utilization of these forces on a global scale would terminate poverty and scarcity within a very foreseeable future. 7
Marcuse’s life-long insistence on the radical potential of art is linked to this obstinate insistence on the utopian dimension. On the one hand, art criticizes and negates the existing social order by the power of its form, which in turn creates another universe, thus hinting at the possibility of building a new social order. But this relationship is highly mediated, as Marcuse continually emphasized — from “The Affirmative Character of Culture” (1937), to the recently published “Some Remarks on Aragon: Art and Politics in the Totalitarian Era” (1945), to the ninth chapter of Eros and Civilization (1955), to the last book he published before his death, entitled, like the ninth chapter of Eros and Civilization, The Aesthetic Dimension. 8 I cite a passage from his essay on Aragon:
Art does not and cannot present the fascist reality (nor any other forms of the totality of monopolistic oppression). But any human activity which does not contain the terror of this era is by this very token inhuman, irrelevant, incidental, untrue. In art, however, the untruth may become the life element of the truth. The incompatibility of the artistic form with the real form of life may be used as a lever for throwing upon the reality the light which the latter cannot absorb, the light which may eventually dissolve this reality (although such dissolution is no longer the function of art). The untruth of art may become the precondition for the artistic contradiction and negation. Art may promote the alienation, the total estrangement of man from his world. And this alienation may provide the artificial basis for the remembrance of freedom in the totality of oppression. 9
On the other hand, emancipatory possibilities reside in the very forces that are responsible for the obscene expansion of an increasingly exploitative and repressive order. It seems to me that the overarching themes of Marcuse’s thought are as relevant today on the cusp of the twenty-first century as they were when his scholarship and political interventions were most widely celebrated.
At this point in my remarks I would like to make some comments about my own development. I have often publicly expressed my gratitude to Herbert Marcuse for teaching me that I did not have to choose between a career as an academic and a political vocation that entailed making interventions around concrete social issues. In Frankfurt, when I was studying with Adorno, he discouraged me from seeking to discover ways of linking my seemingly discrepant interests in philosophy and social activism. After the founding of the Black Panther Party in 1966, I felt very much drawn back to this country (the US). During one of my last meetings with him (students were extremely fortunate if we managed to get one meeting over the course of our studies with a professor like Adorno), he suggested that my desire to work directly in the radical movements of that period was akin to a media studies scholar deciding to become a radio technician.
In the summer of 1967, I was present when Herbert Marcuse delivered one of the major addresses during the Congress of the Dialectics of Liberation convened in London and organized by four British psychiatrists (including David Cooper and R.D. Laing) associated with the anti-psychiatry movement. Other presenters included Paul Sweezy, Lucien Goldmann, and Stokeley Carmichael. Having spent the two previous years studying at the University in Frankfurt with Marcuse’s colleagues, scholars affiliated with the Frankfurt School, I attended this heterogenous gathering of radical scholars, students, activist leaders and organizers from black communities in the United States and Britain on my way back to the United States. The congress took place at the Roundhouse in Chalk Farm, which, originally a locomotive turntable, served as an overarching metaphor for the gathering’s collective ambitions — to turn the motive power of radical intellectuals and activists in the direction of social revolution, or what Marcuse called “qualitative change.”
Many of the young participants in the two-week conference decided to set up camp in the building, turning the congress into a brief utopian experiment in collaborative theorizing buttressed by cooperative living arrangements. In this sense it reproduced, in abridged format, the radical experiments in communal living that characterized the era of the hippies. Marcuse opened his own address by acknowledging the numerous flowers people had brought into the Roundhouse. But, he said, “flowers, by themselves, have no power whatsoever, other than the power of men and women who protect them and take care of them against aggression and destruction.” 10 Later, he spoke pointedly about the hippies, identifying the more politically radical formations among them — the Diggers and the Provos — as uniting sexual, moral, and political rebellion, as encouraging new sensibilities, as exhibiting “a non-aggressive form of life: a demonstration of an aggressive non-aggressiveness which achieves, at least pot...

Table of contents