
eBook - ePub
Contemporary Feminist Utopianism
Lucy Sargisson
Share book
272 pages
English
ePUB (mobile friendly)
Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub
Contemporary Feminist Utopianism
Lucy Sargisson
Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations
About This Book
A new and challenging entry into the debates between feminism and postmodernism, Contemporary Feminist Utopianism challenges some basic preconceptions about the role of political theory today. Sargisson explores current debates within utopian studies, feminist theory and poststructuralist deconstruction. Utopian thinking is offered as a route out of the dilemma of contemporary feminism as well as a way of conceptualizing its current situation. This book provides an exploration of, and exercise in, utopian thought.
Frequently asked questions
How do I cancel my subscription?
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlegoâs features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan youâll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, weâve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Contemporary Feminist Utopianism an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Contemporary Feminist Utopianism by Lucy Sargisson in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Politik & Internationale Beziehungen & Politik. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.
Information
1
FORM-BASED AND CONTENT-BASED APPROACHES TO UTOPIANISM
INTRODUCTION
I shall be arguing, in this part of the book, in favour of a new approach to utopianism; ânewâ, that is, in contrast to some of the dominant (historical) approaches which have contributed to the erection of the myth of utopianism. This myth, the âfalseâ or inappropriate view of the phenomenon, is present in many definitions and outlines of the colloquial usages of the terms âutopiaâ and âutopianismâ. Perusal of the reference section of any library tells us that âutopiaâ means something along the following lines:
1. An imaginary island, depicted by Sir Thomas More as enjoying a perfect social, legal and political systemâŚ. 2. Any imaginary, indefinitely remote region, country or locality. 3. A place, state, or condition ideally perfect in respect of politics, laws, customs and conditionsâŚ. 4. An impossibly ideal scheme, esp. for social improvement.
This comes from the Oxford English Dictionary. The Encyclopedia Britannica provides a similar characterization, in which a utopia is described as âAn ideal commonwealth whose inhabitants exist under perfect conditionsâ. This is clearly the standard colloquial view of utopia.
I shall make the mythical character of these understandings of utopianism clear later in the chapter. First, though, I should like to return to the first sentence of this chapter in order to make two important preliminary points:
- Not all historically previous utopias have contributed to this myth. Thomas More and William Morris are both cited later in the 9 chapter as providing utopian visions which transgress these definitions.
- The importance of the term âapproachâ should be noted at this early stage. Descriptive statements perform creative acts. Naming a thingâgiving a concept, idea or entity a name, description or categoryâis an act of creation. Descriptive, defining statements bring into being that which they (claim to) describe.
These beliefs inform my text and are informed by Derridean poststructuralism. Hence âapproachâ is an important concept within the confines of this book: the nature of the approach taken towards an idea or phenomenon affects the eventual product of conceptualizationâthe concept (as conceptualized). This, if you like, is a methodological claim; and I shall be adopting a transgressive approach (or methodology) towards what I shall identify as the transgressive phenomenon of utopianism.
Utopianism, then, needs to be reconceived. At the root of these arguments are three justificatory claims which will inform the discussions below. Utopianism should be reapproached because:
- 1 what I shall call the standard view of utopia is fundamentally flawed;
- the standard view is inappropriate to much of contemporary feminist utopianism and is, therefore, unnecessarily exclusive;
- the new approach offered in this book is more appropriate to contemporary feminist utopianism.1
The most comprehensive study of utopian thought to be published recently is Ruth Levitasâs The Concept of Utopia (1990). Levitas states that utopianism has historically been approached in terms of one (or more) of three aspects: content, form and function (Levitas, 1990: pp. 4â5). Levitasâs scheme is a useful one, and I shall adopt and adapt these headings in order to give shape to the discussions that follow.2 This chapter will identify and assess those approaches to utopianism which privilege form and content and will identify the (problematic) implications of these approaches. Chapter 2 will look at approaches to utopianism which privilege function. Approaches of this type are cautiously supported.
Part I, then, is concerned to look behind the question âwhat do (feminist) women want?ââwhat are the desires and hopes and aspirations of contemporary feminism(s)?3âto the more interesting question âhow are these desires and hopes and aspirations formulated?â and, finally, to the root or heart of this book: âhow can we (as political theorists, theorists of utopian studiesâwe, the recipients/readers/ audience) best approach these desires as scholars?â
FORM
Does form represent the best approach to utopianism? The answer must be ânoâ, because approaches that take form as the primary defining characteristic of utopianism tend to assume that the form in question is that of literary fiction.4 The assumption that utopianism is a literary genre is common in utopian studies and is perhaps dominant in colloquial understanding.5 This approach, I suggest, results in an unnecessarily restrictive definition of utopianism and of utopias (constructions of utopian thought). Lyman Tower Sargent, the main bibliographer of the field, veers, albeit self-consciously, in this direction (Sargent, 1975, 1994). An early and influential definition comes from Darko Suvin (Sargent himself found this definition to be âby far the bestâ (1975: p. 140)) and situates the phenomenon firmly within the field of literature:
The verbal construction of a particular quasi-human community where sociopolitical institutions, norms and individual relationships are organized according to a more perfect principle than in the authorâs community, this construction being based on estrangement arising out of an alternative historical hypothesis.
(Suvin, 1973: p. 132)
This definition is reached after careful and elaborate consideration of previous definitions, and I shall return to it again later in this chapter. For the present, it is illustrative of a definitional assumption that utopiaâthe expression of utopian thoughtâis a verbal construction, a literary or textual artifact. This view is, as I have said, common. Even Frank Manuel, infamous for shunning definitions, describes utopias as âspeaking picturesâ (Manuel, 1973: p. viii). The image of the word is clearly present in this phrase, which is evocative of an image captured in textual form. A.L.Morton adopts the following as a definition for his work: âan imaginary country described in a work of fiction with the object of criticising existing societyâ (Morton, 1952: p. 10). Krishan Kumar is even more specific; for him, utopianism belongs to the field of science fiction:
Utopia distinguishes itself from other forms of the ideal society, and from other forms of social and political theory, by being in the first place a piece of fiction. It is, using the term in its broadest sense, a species of science fiction.
(Kumar, 1991: p. 20)
Of course, these definitions do not take just the form as being the defining characteristicâthey do not, in other words, approach utopianism purely through a methodological route that privileges form. Mortonâs definition alludes to content, form and function. Likewise, Darko Suvin, cited above, does not approach utopianism solely in terms of form: content and function are also components of his definition. These thinkers do, however, privilege form in their various approaches. Peter Alexander and Roger Gill begin the introduction of their edited collection Utopias with this:
Utopian constructions may take the form either of a picture of an unrealisably ideal social order criticizing an existing order, teaching us lessons about organization and promoting understanding of the concepts involved, or, alternatively, of a blueprint intended to guide the actual reorganization of a society.
(Alexander and Gill, 1984: p. xi)
Here, again, we find an approach to utopianism which relies on form, function and content. Also present in this last definition is a negative and prescriptive element. For Alexander and Gill, the picture or vision which represents a âutopian constructionâ contains an âimpossibly ideal societyâ.
I shall return to discussion of content later. The point that I should like to raise now is that made by Ruth Levitas: that defining utopianism/utopia in terms of form in this way is too restrictive an approach, and one that issues in an unnecessarily narrow definition (Levitas, 1990: p. 4). This point can be illustrated by reference to the work of Ernst Bloch, who has perhaps been most persuasive in broadening the field of utopianism beyond the literary (Bloch, 1986). He finds utopianism (a utopian impulse) to be immanent in popular culture, in the fashion industry, dance, film, adventure stories, art, architecture, music and even medical science. Each of these fields contains its various Utopiasâvisions of a better or more desirable way of being, a desirable future or present.
Vincent Geoghegan uses Blochâs work alongside that of Karl Mannheim (who also argues for a utopian disposition) to broaden our understanding of what constitutes utopianism. For Geoghegan, âthe âclassicâ utopia (which he describes as the literary model established by More] is but one manifestation of utopianismâ (Geoghegan, 1987: p. 2). The implication here is that approaches which privilege form are mistaken, because utopianism and Utopias are expressed in many forms. Geoghegan rejects form in favour of function, which is discussed further below.
I mentioned above the fact that Levitas rejects approaches which privilege form. She is also critical of those which take Mores Utopia as their starting point. I will cite her in full on this point as her statement raises a number of other, related issues:
Some commentators take the form of Mores Utopia as a model and argue that the utopia is a literary genre, involving the fictional depiction of an alternative society in some detail. However,âŚdepictions of the good society do not necessarily take the form of literary fictionsâand indeed this form is only available under certain very specific historical conditions; is it then to be assumed that when these conditions do not exist, there are no utopias?
(Levitas, 1990: pp. 4â5)
I should like to note two of the points being raised here. The first is a concern brought up earlier by Levitas, which arises from the multidisciplinary nature of utopian studies, when she states that âthere is a temptation to try to delimit the field [of utopia] to oneâs own area of interest and set up boundaries which exclude large areas of material as not properly utopianâ (1990: p. 4). The disciplinary imperialism and exclusivity of such an approach must be resisted.6
The second point relates to another danger of a similar ilk, that of cultural imperialism and exclusivity. Because literary utopias are rare in cultures other than âWesternâ ones, does this mean that utopianism and Utopias do not exist in other cultures? Lyman Tower Sargent makes passing reference to an ongoing project in which he is involved: studying and cataloguing the Utopias of indigenous societies (Sargent, 1994). One of the questions that he poses is âAre utopias, as many (Krishan Kumar most recently) have argued, a phenomenon of the Christian West or are there indigenous pre-contact utopias outside the Christian West?â He responds:
No, utopias are not solely the product of the Christian West, but utopias as a genre of literature that has certain formal characteristics are most common in the West, almost certainly because the genre is identified with Thomas More, a person from the Christian West.
(Sargent, 1994: p. 2)
These last points can be related to something which emerges repeatedly throughout this book: that is, a concern about the function and nature of definitions and the act of definingâand, consequently, a concern about the function and nature of political theorizing. Definitions exclude that which is not the subject of the definition in question; this is their primary function. But it is possible, as I shall suggest below, that definitions may be constructed in such a way as to exclude that which should be included. A route around this problem, which is advocated in many sections of this book, is to strive for openended definitions, or, to borrow Sargentâs phrase, to seek definitions with âporous boundariesâ (1990: p. 5). This is a project with its own problems, which will become increasingly clear as I proceed and with which I shall grapple in the concluding chapter. The implications for political theory are methodological onesâpolitical theory has traditionally sought classificatory systems and schemas in order to make sense of the world. A politicalâtheoretical approach to feminist thought, for instance, divides it into liberal, socialist, marxist, radical and, latterly, black and postmodern feminisms, which are then analysed for their own differentiating ideological content. (Books of this type fill the shelves of university bookshops. Examples are Jagger (1983) and Bryson (1992).) The fact that these categories are themselves artificial constructions into which few actual feminists âfitââor indeed that some people may wish to occupy more than one position, or none of the above, yet still regard themselves as âfeministââ is worrying. At the root of these concerns is the inadequacy of the original system of definition or classification: the approach.
To conclude this preliminary discussion of approaches which privilege form, I should like to note that many of the texts referred to in the discussions in later chapters of this book are not of the literary-fictional form. Form as literary (or other) genre, then, represents too restrictive a starting point for comprehensive analysis of utopianism.7 In making this argument it is not my intention to close debate of the fictional status of utopian thought and other manifestations of utopianism, and I shall be discussing the function of a fictional format below.8
So, whilst this book is concerned with âverbal constructionsâ or with textual utopianismâspeaking picturesâwe cannot presume to define utopianism, Utopia or utopian thought in these terms. Utopia, the literary genre, will be discussed further below, but this particular manifestation of utopian thought cannot be taken as the definitional point of departure for its other forms.
CONTENT
Formulaic content
Approaching utopian expressions in terms of their content is perhaps the most common way of looking at and defining utopia(nism). The question asked by commentators who take this approach is âwhat is a utopia?ââand the answer comes in a formula that specifies the common or necessary âingredientsâ or criteria that a text needs in order to be defined and categorized as a utopia. Given then that utopianism is not (just) a literary genre, but given too that the subjects of this book are textual (written) utopias and utopian theory, investigation of approaches to utopianism which stress the importance of formal criteria is necessary. This ground has been well covered, though, and I shall keep discussion brief on this point.
Approaches to utopianism which take this form tend to distinguish âthe utopiaâ from other forms of ideal society. Indeed, this differentiation of utopia is the basis of most projects of definition. J.C.Davis and Krishan Kumar both adopt this approach and both identify five types of ideal society, of which utopia is only one. The first is characterized as âCockaygneâ, from the medieval poem âThe Land of Cokaygneâ.9 In Cockaygne desires are instantly gratified; it is a world containing self-roasting birds, rivers of wine, fountains of youth, wishing trees and ever-available and desirable sexual partners. It is a hedonistic paradise. Cockaygne privileges material and sensual satisfaction and assumes natural abundance. Its inhabitants symbolize satiated desire.
The second ideal society is said to be the arcadia: a pastoral setting of natural abundance to which are added morally or aesthetically motivated humans. Appetites in arcadia are temperately satisfied. The third ideal is what Davis calls âthe perfect commonwealthâ, a society with a prescriptive moral order, perfectly realized by all of its members. This complements but is different from the millennium, the fourth type of ideal society, in which men and women are transformed, usually for the better, by an external force. This force is a god-like figure whose strength is greater than that which it is believed is the force causing evil thoughts and behaviour.
Only the fifth type of ideal society is identified as the utopia, that in which there is âno invocation of a dens ex machina, nor any wishing away of the deficiencies of man or natureâ (Davis, 1984: p. 9). Rather, says Davis, the utopia creates systems which will cope with these deficiencies, systems that are recognizable as pertaining to the modern state: âSuch systems are inevitably bureaucratic, institutional, legal and educational, artificial and organisationalâ (Davis, 1984: p. 9). Utopia, says Davis, idealizes organization.
I should like to begin discuss...
Table of contents
Citation styles for Contemporary Feminist Utopianism
APA 6 Citation
Sargisson, L. (2002). Contemporary Feminist Utopianism (1st ed.). Taylor and Francis. Retrieved from https://www.perlego.com/book/1618572/contemporary-feminist-utopianism-pdf (Original work published 2002)
Chicago Citation
Sargisson, Lucy. (2002) 2002. Contemporary Feminist Utopianism. 1st ed. Taylor and Francis. https://www.perlego.com/book/1618572/contemporary-feminist-utopianism-pdf.
Harvard Citation
Sargisson, L. (2002) Contemporary Feminist Utopianism. 1st edn. Taylor and Francis. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/1618572/contemporary-feminist-utopianism-pdf (Accessed: 14 October 2022).
MLA 7 Citation
Sargisson, Lucy. Contemporary Feminist Utopianism. 1st ed. Taylor and Francis, 2002. Web. 14 Oct. 2022.