
eBook - ePub
Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz
The Concept of Substance in Seventeenth Century Metaphysics
Roger Woolhouse
Share book
224 pages
English
ePUB (mobile friendly)
Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub
Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz
The Concept of Substance in Seventeenth Century Metaphysics
Roger Woolhouse
Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations
About This Book
This book introduces student to the three major figures of modern philosophy known as the rationalists. It is not for complete beginners, but it is an accessible account of their thought. By concerning itself with metaphysics, and in particular substance, the book relates an important historical debate largely neglected by the contemporary debates in the once again popular area of traditional metaphysics. in philosophy.
Frequently asked questions
How do I cancel my subscription?
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlegoâs features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan youâll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, weâve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz by Roger Woolhouse in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Philosophy History & Theory. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.
Information
1 Introduction
Modern philosophy is usually taken to date from the seventeenth century, and RenĂ© Descartes (1596â1650) is often named as its father. This need not mean that Descartes was the first noteworthy and identifiably âmodernâ philosopher. Thomas Hobbes (1588â 1679) has claims there too. What it does mean is that Descartes more than others was responsible for the style, the shape, and the content of much subsequent philosophyâat first on the Continent, and then in England.1 His distinction between extended and thinking substance, his proofs of his own existence and of that of a good God, his account of the material world as one of extended matter in motion, all stirred up controversy and discussion whose waves rocked the remainder of the seventeenth century and troubled most of the eighteenth, and whose ripples are still discernible today. Contemporary reports, from both sides of the English Channel, testify to one aspect of his importance: his freshness and newness. According to Christian Huygens, the Dutch mathematician, astronomer, and physicist,
What greatly pleased in the beginning when this philosophy began to appear is that one understood what M. des Cartes was saying, while the other philosophers gave us words that made nothing comprehensible, such as qualities, substantial forms, intentional species, etc. He rejected more universally than any other before him this irrelevant paraphernalia. But what especially recommended his philosophy, is that he did not stop short at giving a disgust for the old, but he dared to substitute causes that can be understood of all there is in nature.
(trans. Dugas 1958:312)
(trans. Dugas 1958:312)
It was to the same âjustly-admired gentlemanâ that John Locke said he owed âthe great obligation of my first deliverance from the unintelligible way of talking of the philosophy in use in the schools in his timeâ (1823:4.48).
In these testimonials to Descartesâs influence on the seventeenth century his ânewâ philosophy is contrasted with an âofficialâ, Scholastic, or âschoolâ philosophyâa philosophy filled with ideas which had begun to seem unintelligible. This older philosophy belongs to a broadly Aristotelian tradition, and it is the explicit rejection of this tradition, and of the authority of Aristotle, that marks for Descartes, and for many of his contemporaries and successors, their own sense of their âmodernityâ.
Two people for whom Descartesâs philosophy set a new, post- Aristotelian scene were Benedict Spinoza (1632â77) and Gottfried Leibniz (1646â1716). Leibniz says that Spinoza âonly cultivated certain seeds in the philosophy of Descartesâ (G 2.563) and that his philosophy is âan exaggerated Cartesianismâ (T 359). As for Descartes himself, he is someone âwhose genius is elevated almost above all praiseâ. He âcertainly began the true and right wayâ, and said âexcellent and original thingsâ. Yet Leibnizâs praise had its limits: though going so far as to be âthe entrance hall to the truthâ, Descartesâs philosophy âmissed the markâ and did not quite make it.2 Leibnizâs disagreements with it are deep. Spinoza too had his criticisms of Descartes,3 and Descartesâs own followers were keen, on theological grounds, to dispel any idea that Spinoza might be one of them.4 None of this, however, prevented the development of a tradition which pictures both Spinoza and Leibniz as âCartesiansâ.5
In its discussion of the metaphysical views of these three important seventeenth-century philosophers this book supposes that there are intrinsic relations between them. But it formulates no general conclusions about whether Spinoza and Leibniz are or are not âCartesiansâ. It simply proceeds on the assumptionâan assumption to be judged by its fruitsâthat the very shape or conceptual content, and not the mere verbal dress,6 of many of Spinozaâs ideas have Cartesian ones as a background; and that (whether directly, or indirectly via Spinoza) the same is true of Leibniz.
Spinoza was 18 when Descartes died, and they neither met nor corresponded. In 1663, however, he published an exposition of Descartesâs influential Principles of Philosophy (1644). This wasdesigned as tuition material for a pupil to whom, Spinoza says, âI did not want to teach my own opinions openlyâ (Ep13/C 207), and Spinoza agreed with friends that he should âwarnâŠReaders that I did not acknowledge all the opinionsâŠas my own, since I had written many thingsâŠwhich were the very opposite of what I heldâ (Ep13/C 207). Nevertheless its very existence betokens a deep understanding of, and concern with, Cartesianism. It is no surprise that Spinozaâs own philosophy in his Ethics (1677) shows keen awareness of Descartesâs.
Fourteen years younger than Spinoza, Leibniz was only 4 when Descartes died. They had quasi-personal contact when Leibniz met Descartesâs friend and literary executor, Claude Clerselier, who showed him some of Descartesâs unpublished papers.7 But like any other European philosopher of the time, Leibniz read and studied Descartes, and in the 1690s he too had plans to publish an assessment of Descartesâs Principles of Philosophy8 This assessment would have brought together all the ways in which Descartes, so near to the truth, had yet âmissed the markâ (L 432), and all the criticisms Leibniz had developed over the years, and out of which his own positive views had emerged. His relationship to Descartes is well-summed up in a letter of 1680:
I esteem Mr Descartes almost as much as one can esteem any man, and though there are among his opinions some which seem false to meâŠthis does not keep me from saying that we owe nearly as much to Galileo and to him in philosophical matters as to the whole of antiquity.
As for Spinoza and Leibniz, they both corresponded and met. In 1671, in an exchange of letters on optics,9 Spinoza offered to send Leibniz his recently published Tractatus Theologico-Politicus. Later, in 1675, Leibniz was suggested to Spinoza as someone âvery expert in metaphysical studiesâ (Ep 70/W 339), and hence as someone to whom the manuscript of the Ethics, then circulating among Spinozaâs friends, might usefully be shown. Spinoza, whose Tractatus Theologico-Politicus (1670) had already become infamous, considered âit imprudent to entrust my writings to him so soonâ (Ep 72/W 431), and asked that more be learnt about Leibnizâs character. In the event, Leibniz met with Spinoza in Holland the next year and, he reported, âspoke with him several times and for very longâ (L 167); according to notes he made at thetime, at least some of the discussion concerned the Ethics. Spinoza died the next year, and when the Ethics was eventually published Leibniz made further detailed notes.10 Many of these are critical, as are most of the comments on Spinoza which are scattered through his writings. Like others at the time Leibniz thought that Spinozaâs ideas were dangerous to religion; his view of the nature of God and creation in particular. He often explicitly contrasts his own doctrines with Spinozaâs. A letter he wrote on the publication of Spinozaâs Ethics gives an assessment of the relationship between their ideas:
I have found there a number of excellent thoughts which agree with my own, as some of my friends know who have also learned from Spinoza. But there are also paradoxes which I do not find true or even plausible. As, for example, that there is only one substance, namely God; that creatures [created things] are modes or accidents of God.⊠I consider this book dangerous for those who wish to take the pains to master it.
This book discusses the metaphysics of these three philosophers. Specifically, it focuses on what Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz say about âsubstanceâ. â[F]ailure to understand the natureâ of this is, says Leibniz, âthe cause of [Descartesâs] errorsâ (L 433) and of Spinozaâs âparadoxesâ (L 195). But what is âmetaphysicsâ? What is âsubstanceâ?
The term âmetaphysicsâ originated as the title of some of Aristotleâs books. Though Aristotle himself called the subject matter of these books âfirst philosophyâ, it appears that in early editions of his works they were arranged in order after his book Physics; so they, and hence their subject matter, came to be known as Metaphysics (âafterâ, âaboveâ, or âbeyondâ the Physics). One part of âfirst philosophyâ as conceived by Aristotle was the study of âbeing as beingâ (Met 1003a20), a study which concerns the question what being is. This question, says Aristotle, âwas raised of old and is raised now and always, and is always the subject of doubtâ; and he adds that the question âWhat is being?â âis just the question, what is substance?â (Met 1028b3). The questions are the same because the Greek for the English word âsubstanceâ (Latin: substantia) is ousia, which comes from the Greek verb for âto beâ. One natural way to understand the question what being or substance is, and one which fits much of what Aristotle says, is as a request for an account of what is real. âWhat does reality comprise?â (Stead:66), a recent writer on Aristotle puts it. So, as Aristotle remarks, âsubstanceâ or âbeingâ is âthought to belong most obviously to bodiesâ (Met 1028b9); these are what are most naturally picked out as constitutive of reality. â[W]e say that not only animals and plantsâŠare substances, but also natural bodies such as fire and water and earth.â But whether this initial, âmost obviousâ, thought is right, whether these really are substances, is, says Aristotle, something which âmust be consideredâ (Met 1028b8â16).
To a considerable extent Aristotle thinks the thought is correct, though on the way to this conclusion he gives a lengthy account of just what it is about animals, plants, and natural bodies that constitutes their being or substantiality. Moreover, as he points out, some people have thought otherwise. Various earlier Greek philosophers had thought that reality consists ultimately in something other than these things, something of which these things are merely the surface phenomena. Some had held that there is one basic substance or ultimately real being: according to Thales this is âwaterâ; according to Parmenides it is an everlasting, motionless, and homogeneous âOneâ. Some had held that there is more than one basic substance or ultimately real being: according to Empedocles the world as we know it is produced from four ârootsâ or âelementsââFire, Air, Earth, Waterâworked on by the two principles of Love and Strife; according to the atomists such as Democritus it is a result of the chance movements and collisions of differently shaped indivisible atoms.
The ancient Greek interest in metaphysics, and its core question about substance or being, is shared by the philosophers of the seventeenth century. In fact it is one of their central concerns. According to Leibniz, âthe consideration of substance is of the greatest importance and fruitfulness for philosophyâ (NE 151); and these words could serve as a motto not only for his work but also for that of Descartes and Spinoza. He also says, in an article âOn the correction of metaphysics and the concept of substanceâ, that unlike Descartesâs account, which led to error, his âis so fruitful that there follow from it primary truths, even about God and minds and the nature of bodiesâtruths heretofore known in part though barely demonstrated, and unknown in part, but ofthe greatest utility for the future in the other sciencesâ (L 433). Leibnizâs estimation of the importance of the concept of substance is correct. What he says follows from his account is the heart of nearly the whole of his philosophy; and Spinozaâs great work, the Ethics, is essentially nothing less than a lengthy elaboration of the definition of substance with which it all but opens. As for Descartes, though his writings are not so clearly structured as a metaphysics of substance, he certainly develops one at length, and many of his philosophical views connect with it; without it, Spinoza and Leibniz would not have written as they did.
Besides sharing an interest in the question what substance or being is, the philosophers of the seventeenth century also retain the original Aristotelian idea of metaphysics as âfirstâ or foundational philosophy. This is vividly presented in the preface to Descartesâs Principles of Philosophy, where the whole of philosophy is portrayed as a tree: âThe roots are metaphysics, the trunk is physics, and the branches emerging from the trunk are all the other sciencesâ (CSM 1.186). The idea of metaphysicsââthis regal scienceâ (L 432)âas the foundation or source of other branches of knowledge is taken up by Leibniz too. Sciences such as physics depend on it: âthe laws of mechanicsâŠflowâŠfrom metaphysical principlesâ (trans. MacDonald Ross:146); they âcannot be advanced without metaphysical principlesâ, principles without which âgeneral physics is entirely incompleteâ (trans. MacDonald Ross:154).
Given the actual origin of the term âmetaphysicsâ, it is just a coincidence that a main concern of âfirst philosophyâ, as understood and developed not only by Aristotle but also in the seventeenth century, can be thought of as metaphysical or beyond physics in the sense of being more basic, abstract and general than physics. Physics, we might say, tells us about the details of the worldâs phenomena; metaphysics about what underlies those phenomena, what the reality, being, or substantiality of the world basically or ultimately consists in. Thus, to understand the detailed workings of the world, all the phenomena and appearances which it presents to us, is to understand them in terms of the properties and activities of the substances which constitute the world. But, in the context of the philosophy of the seventeenth century, it is a particularly nice coincidence. That century saw the emergence and development of what we now know as modern science. It saw the publication of Johannes Keplerâs New Astronomyor Celestial Physics (1609), William Harveyâs Anatomical Essay on the Motion of the Heart and Blood (1628), Galileo Galileiâs Dialogues on the Two Chief Systems of the World (1632), and Isaac Newtonâs The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (1687). It saw the development of the telescope and the microscope. It saw the foundation of scientific societies such as the Royal Society of London for the Advancement of Experimental Knowledge (1660s); and it saw the work of occupants of the âHall of Scientific Fameâ, such as Robert Boyle, Robert Hooke, and Christian Huygens. Later chapters of this book will show how the metaphysics of Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz not only provide general background conceptions of the world as described in detail by the more particular sciences, but also contribute quite directly to the theoretical foundations of seventeenth-century physics and mechanics.
Even though the rejection of Aristotle marks for the philosophers of the seventeenth century their own sense of their âmodernityâ, they hardly free themselves from the Scholastic tradition completely. Leaving aside the fact that Leibniz even wished to reins...
Table of contents
Citation styles for Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz
APA 6 Citation
Woolhouse, R. (2002). Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz (1st ed.). Taylor and Francis. Retrieved from https://www.perlego.com/book/1622192/descartes-spinoza-leibniz-the-concept-of-substance-in-seventeenth-century-metaphysics-pdf (Original work published 2002)
Chicago Citation
Woolhouse, Roger. (2002) 2002. Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz. 1st ed. Taylor and Francis. https://www.perlego.com/book/1622192/descartes-spinoza-leibniz-the-concept-of-substance-in-seventeenth-century-metaphysics-pdf.
Harvard Citation
Woolhouse, R. (2002) Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz. 1st edn. Taylor and Francis. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/1622192/descartes-spinoza-leibniz-the-concept-of-substance-in-seventeenth-century-metaphysics-pdf (Accessed: 14 October 2022).
MLA 7 Citation
Woolhouse, Roger. Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz. 1st ed. Taylor and Francis, 2002. Web. 14 Oct. 2022.