Common-Sense Morality and Consequentialism
eBook - ePub

Common-Sense Morality and Consequentialism

Michael A. Slote

Share book
  1. 166 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Common-Sense Morality and Consequentialism

Michael A. Slote

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Originally published in 1985 and now re-issued with a new preface, this study assesses the two major moral theories of ethical consequentialism and common-sense morality by means of mutual comparison and an attempt to elicit the implications and tendencies of each theory individually. The author shows that criticisms and defences of common-sense morality and of consequentialism give inadequate characterizations of the dispute between them and thus at best provide incomplete rationales for either of these influential moral views. Both theories face inherent difficulties, some familiar but others mentioned for the first time in this work. The argument proceeds by reference to historical figures like Bentham, Ross and Sidgwick and to contemporary thinkers such as Williams, Nagel, Hare and Sen.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Common-Sense Morality and Consequentialism an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Common-Sense Morality and Consequentialism by Michael A. Slote in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Filosofia & Filosofia etica e morale. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2020
ISBN
9781000073423

NOTES

CHAPTER I COMMON-SENSE MORALITY AND CONSEQUENTIALISM

1 Any moral theory that makes right and wrong action depend entirely on results or consequences is act-consequentialist. A theory holding that an act is right if and only if it produces the best state(s) of affairs may go on to claim that certain considerations of justice are relevant to the goodness of overall states of affairs. Such a theory will be act-consequentialist but not act-utilitarian. Cf. Amartya Sen, ‘Utilitarianism and Welfarism’, Journal of Philosophy, 76, 1979, pp. 463–89; and Samuel Scheffler, The Rejection of Consequentialism, Oxford University Press, 1982, ch. 2 and pp. 72ff.
2 I shall not be discussing those cases where desire for the optimal course of events may lead one to qualify act-consequentialism into some form of act-and-motive consequentialism. (Cf. R. M. Adams, ‘Motive Utilitarianism’, Journal of Philosophy, 73, 1976, pp. 467–81.) Because other forms of consequentialism are not immediately relevant to the main conclusions of the present chapter, I shall for the moment drop the word ‘act’ in speaking of act-utilitarianism and act-consequentialism. Note too that the connection between benevolence and optimality assumed in the main text will be called into question in Chapter III, below.
3 See Williams’s ‘A Critique of Utilitarianism’ in Smart and Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against, Cambridge, 1973; T. Nagel’s ‘The Limits of Objectivity’, in S. McMurrin, ed., The Tanner Lectures on Human Value, I, Cambridge University Press, 1980, pp. 119ff.; and S. Scheffler, op. cit., passim. Nagel also discusses some of the reasons why the impersonal standpoint itself is so appealing in ethics and elsewhere.
4 See W. D. Ross, The Foundations of Ethics, Oxford University Press, 1939, pp. 72ff., 272ff. Cf. Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, London, Macmillan, 1962, 7th edn., pp. 431f.
5 One can imagine either that one kills oneself, knowing that the organs will be thus used, or that with superior technology and equipment one actually brings about the requisite operation on oneself.
6 E.g., by Robert Nozick in Anarchy, State, and Utopia, New York, Basic Books, 1974, p. 30; by Thomas Nagel, op. cit. ; and by S. Scheffler, op. cit., esp. ch. 4 and p. 121. I am especially indebted to Scheffler’s formulation of these particular problems.
7 Interestingly, Scheffler never remarks on the self-other asymmetry of ordinary deontological restrictions and in fact always formulates those restrictions in symmetric form. He says, e.g., that they are restrictions against ‘harming some undeserving person’. I have found only one place where the asymmetry slips in unnoticed (p. 100).
8 In deprecating oneself, one may ‘do oneself an injustice’, but this is presumably .not the morally relevant sense of the notion.
9 On the other hand, a kind of moral-theoretic methodological conservatism may indicate that we not abandon common-sense morality until we are given strong reasons to do so.
10 The distinction, roughly, is between an asymmetry concerning omissions and one concerning commissions. But Nagel (op. cit.) has argued that deontological restrictions concern even what one intentionally allows. According to Nagel, roughly, one may not deliberately allow someone to die as a means to prevent other deaths (or to prevent other people intentionally allowing people to die). I have stated the asymmetry regarding the allocation of harms and benefits so that it lies outside even this broad, intentional-omission-including notion of deontological constraints, by speaking of the difference between ignoring benefits (harms) to oneself and to others – where such ignoring may not involve intentionally or deliberately failing to prevent harms or benefits, but simply not bothering about them. The self-other asymmetry is thus not entirely limited to the usual area of side-constraints or deontological restrictions.
11 However, consider the qualification mentioned in note 2, above.
12 On this point see, e.g., Sidgwick, op. cit., p. 246.
13 See, e.g. Nozick, op. cit., p. 30n. ; for some problems about defining the morally relevant sense of ‘innocent’, also see Nozick, op. cit.
14 See J. Thomson, ‘Killing, Letting Die, and the Trolley Problem’, The Monist, 59, 1976, pp. 204–17.
15 Arguments of both these sorts can be found in Jonathan Bennett’s ‘Morality and Consequences’, in S. McMurrin, ed., The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, II, Cambridge University Press, 1981, pp. 45–116.
16 See his ‘Doing Good: the Right and the Wrong Way’, Journal of Philosophy, 79, 1982, pp. 439–55.
17 See Scheffler, op. cit.
18 See Bernard Williams, op. cit., section 5.
19 See Scheffler, op. cit.
20 Don’t say: ‘but the consent in the first case is of another person and one should not take another person’s consent as seriously (as literally) as one takes one’s own.’ That is just our asymmetry in another guise. Also, I have ruled out of consideration any religious injunctions against suicide that might make the cases seem more similar. Perhaps, I should say that the asymmetry I am speaking of is one of common-sense secular morality.
21 In The Object of Morality, London, Methuen, 1976, p. 26.
22 By the same token, sociobiological explanations of ordinary morality that focus on the evolutionary effects of altruism seem also to be incapable of motivating or accounting for the self-other asymmetry. If the gene-survival value of altruism explains the existence of moral imperatives concerning others, why shouldn’t the survival value of self- concern have generated similar imperatives concerning one’s behaviour towards oneself?

CHAPTER II MORAL AUTONOMY

1 The obligation not to kill one individual even as a means to saving five different individuals entails, except, possibly, under certain conditions of moral conflict, a permission not to kill one to save five. But in speaking above and elsewhere of (the whole class of) common-sense moral permissions I mean to exclude such obligation-based permissions and to be speaking of what are more naturally thought of as permissions, namely, permissions not tied to specific obligations, where what one is permitted to do one is also permitted not to do.
2 It would be a mistake to object that if the actually selfish agent were to sacrifice his own well-being, then such self-sacrifice would be among his projects and justifiable accordingly. For one thing, the counterfactual claim involved here cannot be sustained. We can say that he would make the sacrifice only if he were unselfish, but not that if he made the sacrifice, he would be unselfish. Cf. ‘Time in Counterfactuals’, Philosophical Review, 87, 1978, pp. 3–27.
3 See especially his ‘A Critique of Utilitarianism’ in Smart and Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against, Cambridge University Press, 1973, section 5.
4 See, for example, Scheffler, The Rejection of Consequentialism, Oxford, 1982, esp. pp. 20, 25, 125. Also my own previous ‘The Morality of Wealth’, in Aiken and La Follette, eds, World Hunger and Moral Obligation, Englewood Cliffs, N. J., Prentice-Hall, 1977, esp. pp. 125f., which makes, in addition, an appeal to something like Williams’s notion of integrity. Obviously the claim that a moral principle unreasonably interferes with the moral individual’s deepest identity, or integrity, is akin to the claim that it demands too much in the way of sacrifice (is objectionably demanding).
5 The qualification ‘innocent’ is essential if we wish to express the common-sense moral view of our permissions to pursue projects or commitments. One’s project cannot permissibly be genocide or success in the Mafia. On this compare Scheffler, op. cit., p. 18; and ‘The Morality of Wealth’, pp. 126ff. The notion of innocence needs further specification, but can, I think, serve our present purposes undefined.
6 It may in some sense be psychologically impossible for a certain individual to become interested in the history of philosophy, but this needn’t interfere with our judgment that a career in that area is morally permissible to him, any more than the fact that a certain individual is irredeemably selfish prevents him from being permitted to act unselfishly on a given occasion.
7 See ‘Ifs and Cans’ in Philosophical Papers, Oxford, Clarendon, 1961, pp. 157ff.
8 Austin, in passing, gives some examples of ordinary language quantifications implicitly involving non-conditional ‘ifs’, but never explicitly draws our attention to this fact about them. The examples are, in fact, closely related to those discussed here.
9 The permission to pursue any project one wants is not, therefor...

Table of contents