Socio-Economic Models in Geography (Routledge Revivals)
eBook - ePub

Socio-Economic Models in Geography (Routledge Revivals)

Richard J. Chorley, Peter Haggett, Richard J. Chorley, Peter Haggett

Share book
  1. 304 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Socio-Economic Models in Geography (Routledge Revivals)

Richard J. Chorley, Peter Haggett, Richard J. Chorley, Peter Haggett

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

First published in 1968, this book explores the theme of geographical generalization, or model building. It is composed of seven of the chapters from the original Models in Geography, published in 1967. The first chapter broadly outlines this theme and examines the nature and function of generalized statements, ranging from conceptual models to scale models, in a geographical context. The following six chapters deal with socio-economic building in geography. They focus on demographic and sociological models as well as looking at special aspects of models in human geography in reference to economic development, urban geography and settlement location, industrial location, and agricultural activity.

This book represents a robustly anti-idiographic statement of modern work in one of the major branches of geography.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Socio-Economic Models in Geography (Routledge Revivals) an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Socio-Economic Models in Geography (Routledge Revivals) by Richard J. Chorley, Peter Haggett, Richard J. Chorley, Peter Haggett in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Physical Sciences & Geography. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2013
ISBN
9781136155840
Edition
1
Chapter One
Models, Paradigms and the New Geography
P. Haggett, and R. J. Chorley
Models are undeniably beautiful, and a man may justly be proud to be seen in their company. But they may have their hidden vices. The question is, after all, not only whether they are good to look at, but whether we can live happily with them.
KAPLAN, 1964, p. 288.
In concluding the previous volume in this series, we attempted to review the paths taken by various workers in moving towards what they saw to be the ‘frontier’ in geographical research. We argued there that the quest for a model or models was a recurrent theme in their search. This volume is a direct outcome of that conclusion in that specific workers were asked to discuss the role of model-building within their own special fields of geographical research. While we would not wish to pre-judge their findings, it will be evident from the format and arrangement of the chapters that there is: (1) some measurable contrast between their approaches to geography, various as they are, and those that characterize the great part of established geographical patterns of thinking, as evidenced by existing textbooks and syllabuses; and (2) a community of common ideas that link all contributors into what Price (1963, p. 62) would characterize as an ‘invisible college’ of geographical practitioners. Whether this communality is sufficient to form the basis of what Manley (1966) has termed a ‘New Geography’ is not for us to judge. However, it is perhaps significant that the greater part of the volume is based on work produced since 1945, and much of it since 1960. In this opening chapter we discuss what we believe to be the significance of this new search for a model-based geography.
Facts, Models and Paradigms
The nature of facts
Information in geography is capable of treatment in terms of general information theory. In this context factual information only has relevance within some more general frame of reference, and such a basic operation as the definition of a relevant fact can only be made on the basis of some theoretical framework. There are also different levels of organization of relevant information. Some information can be relevantly organized only at a small scale, whereas the orderly large-scale patterns of other information are blurred or swamped altogether on the local scale. One can therefore view geographical information registration and analysis, from one point of view at any rate, as a problem in the separation of regional and local information patterns from the more randomly-organized information which, as ‘noise’, obscures them (Chorley and Haggett, 1965). Of course, one may choose to regard the noise as the more significant element and to ask whether it is useful to try to recognize any order in reality. This results in the stress being placed on the variety of geographical information available and in attempts to subdivide information. However, it is becoming increasingly popular to ask what kinds of order are exhibited by geographical information and on what scales of space and time each operates. In short, the ‘simple’ registration of facts is being recognized not only as unsatisfactory but as an impossibility. Hanson (1958, pp. 8–19) has pointed out that what is observed depends not only on the context in which a particular phenomenon is set, but in the manner in which one is prepared to view it. In the words of Sigwart: ‘That there is more order in the world than appears at first sight is not discovered till the order is looked for’ (Quoted by Hanson, 1958, p. 204). Figure 1.1 gives a striking illustration both of the close apparent relationship between order and disorder, and of the subjective approach necessary to identify what it believed to be orderly.
images
1.1 A photograph of melting snow taken on impulse by a photographer in China just before the last war. The pattern makes no sense until it is organized as a full-face and shoulders, similar in style to a late-medieval representation of Christ; the upper margin cutting the brow and illuminated from the right (Source: Partly from Porter, 1954).
The distinction between the idiographic and nomothetic approaches to the real world was recognized by Aristotle, although not in the terms which we currently employ, when he pointed out that poetry is more philosophical and of graver import than history because it is concerned with what is pervasive and universal, whereas history is addressed to what is special and singular (Nagel, 1961, p. 547). Today the distinction is made commonly between the ‘humanities’ which are primarily concerned with the unique and nonrecurrent, and the ‘sciences’ which seek to establish general statements for repeatable events and process. Contemporary geography obviously lies athwart this apparent gulf, which must either be bridged or must lead to the dismemberment of the existing discipline. The dichotomy between the general and the particular was clearly stated by Francis Bacon in his Maxims of the Law; ‘For there be two contrary faults and extremities in the debating and sifting of the law, which may be noted in two several manner of arguments: some argue upon general grounds, and come not near the point in question; others, without laying any foundation of a ground or difference of reason, do loosely put cases, which, though they go near the point, yet being put so scattered, prove not, but rather serve to make the law appear more doubtful than to make it more plain’. Indeed, the distinction between the idiographic and nomothetic views of geography, so strongly put by Bunge (1962), may be useful in highlighting many of the current shortcomings in the subject, but is less valuable from the more purely philosophical standpoint. Bambrough (1964, p. 100), for example, points out that all reasoning is ultimately concerned with particular cases, and that laws, rules and principles are merely devices for bringing particular cases to bear on other particular cases. ‘The ideal limiting case of representation is reduplication, and a duplicate is too true to be useful. Anything that falls short of the ideal limit of reduplication is too useful to be altogether true’ (Bambrough, 1964, p. 98). In short, every individual is, by definition, different, but the most significant statement which can be made about modern scholarship in general is that it has been found to be intellectually more profitable, satisfying and productive to view the phenomena of the real world in terms of their ‘set characteristics’, rather than to concentrate upon their individual deviations from one another.
The nature of models
The catholic view of models taken in this volume derives largely from Skilling (1964). He argued that a model can be a theory or a law or an hypothesis or a structured idea. It can be a role, a relation or an equation. It can be a synthesis of data. Most important from the geographical viewpoint, it can also include reasoning about the real world by means of translations in space (to give spatial models) or in time (to give historical models).
The need for idealization. The traditional reaction of man to the apparent complexity of the world around him has been to make for himself a simplified and intelligible picture of the world. ‘He then tries to substitute this cosmos of his own for the world of experience, and thus to overcome it’ (Chorafas, 1965, p. 1). The mind decomposes the real world into a series of simplified systems and thus achieves in one act ‘an overview of the essential characteristics of a domain’ (Apostel, 1961, p. 15). This simplification requires both sensual and intellectual creativity (Keipers, 1961, p. 132). ‘The mind needs to see the system in opposition and distinction to all others; therefore the separation of the system from others is made more complete than it is in reality. The system is viewed from a certain scale; details that are too microscopical or too global are of no interest to us. Therefore they are left out. The system is known or controlled within certain limits of approximation. Therefore effects that do not reach this level of approximation are neglected. The system is studied with a certain purpose in mind; everything that does not affect this purpose is eliminated. The various features of the system need to be known as aspects of one identical whole; therefore their unity is exaggerated’ (Apostel, 1961, pp. 15–16). According to this view, reality exists as a patterned and bounded connexity which has been explored by the use of simplified patterns of symbols, rules and processes (Meadows, 1957, pp. 3–4). The simplified statements of this structural interdependence have been termed ‘models’. A model is thus a simplified structuring of reality which presents supposedly significant features or relationships in a generalized form. Models are highly subjective approximations in that they do not include all associated observations or measurements, but as such they are valuable in obscuring incidental detail and in allowing fundamental aspects of reality to appear. This selectivity means that models have varying degrees of probability and a limited range of conditions over which they apply. The most successful models possess a high probability of application and a wide range of conditions in which they seem appropriate. Indeed, the value of a model is often directly related to its level of abstraction. However, all models are constantly in need of improvement as new information or vistas of reality appear, and the more successfully the model was originally structured the more likely it seems that such improvement must involve the construction of a different model.
Characteristics of models. The term ‘model’ is conventionally employed in a number of different ways. It is used as a noun implying a representation, as an adjective implying a degree of perfection, or as a verb implying to demonstrate or to show what something is like (Ackoff, Gupta and Minas, 1962, p. 108). In fact models possess all these properties.
The most fundamental feature of models is that their construction has involved a highly selective attitude to information, wherein not only noise but less important signals have been eliminated to enable one to see something of the heart of things. Models can be viewed as selective approximations which, by the elimination of incidental detail, allow some fundamental, relevant or interesting aspects of the real world to appear in some generalized form. Thus models can be thought of as selective pictures and ‘a direct description of the logical characteristics of our knowledge of the external world shows that each of these pictures gives undue prominance to some features of our knowledge and obscures and distorts the other features that rival pictures emphasize. Each of them directs such a bright light on one part of the scene that it obscures other parts in a dark shadow’ (Bambrough, 1964, p. 102). As Black (1962, p. 220) wrote of scale models, ‘
 only by being unfaithful in some respect can a model represent its original’.
Another important model characteristic is that models are structured, in the sense that the selected significant aspects of the ‘web of reality’ are exploited in terms of their connections. It is interesting that what is often termed a model by logicians is called by econometricians a ‘structure’ (Suppes, 1961, p. 165; Kaplan, 1964, p. 267). Science has profited greatly from this pattern seeking, in which phenomena are viewed in terms of a kind of organic relationship.
This model feature leads immediately to the suggestive nature of models, in that a successful model contains suggestions for its own extension and generalization (Hesse, 1953–54, pp. 213–214). This implies, firstly, that the whole model structure has greater implications than a study of its individual parts might lead one to suppose (Deutsch, 1948–49), and, secondly, that predictions can be made about the real world from the model. Models have thus been termed ‘speculative instruments’, and Black (1962, pp. 232–233) has described a promising model as ‘one with implications rich enough to suggest novel hypotheses and speculations in the primary field of investigation’. Similarly, Toulmin (1953, pp. 38–39) regards a good model as experimentally fertile, suggesting further questions, taking us beyond the phenomena from which we began, and tempting us to formulate hypotheses. The ‘intuitive grasp’ (Gestalt knowledge) of the capacities and implications of a model is thus the key to the exploitation of its suggestive character.
Selectivity implies that models are different from reality in that they are approximations of it. A model must be simple enough for manipulation and understanding by its users, representative enough in the total range of the implications it may have, yet complex enough to represent accurately the system under study (Chorafas, 1965, p. 31). In another sense, too, models represent compromises in that each has a circumscribed range of conditions within which it has relevance (Skilling, 1964, p. 389A).
Because models are different from the real world they are analogies. The use of hardware models is an obvious example of the general aim of the model builder to reformulate some features of the real world into a more familiar, simplified, accessible, observable, easily-formulated or controllable form, from which conclusions can be deduced, which, in turn, can be reapplied to the real world (Chorley, 1964, pp. 127–128).
Reapplication is a prerequisite for models in the empirical sciences. Although some mathematical model builders disclaim responsibility for the degree to which their idealizations may represent the real world, claiming that their responsibility is discharged com...

Table of contents