The Terror of Natural Right
eBook - ePub

The Terror of Natural Right

Republicanism, the Cult of Nature, and the French Revolution

Dan Edelstein

Share book
  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

The Terror of Natural Right

Republicanism, the Cult of Nature, and the French Revolution

Dan Edelstein

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Natural right—the idea that there is a collection of laws and rights based not on custom or belief but that are "natural" in origin—is typically associated with liberal politics and freedom. In The Terror of Natural Right, Dan Edelstein argues that the revolutionaries used the natural right concept of the "enemy of the human race"—an individual who has transgressed the laws of nature and must be executed without judicial formalities—to authorize three-quarters of the deaths during the Terror. Edelstein further contends that the Jacobins shared a political philosophy that he calls "natural republicanism, " which assumed that the natural state of society was a republic and that natural right provided its only acceptable laws. Ultimately, he proves that what we call the Terror was in fact only one facet of the republican theory that prevailed from Louis's trial until the fall of Robespierre.

A highly original work of historical analysis, political theory, literary criticism, and intellectual history, The Terror of Natural Right challenges prevailing assumptions of the Terror to offer a new perspective on the Revolutionary period.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is The Terror of Natural Right an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access The Terror of Natural Right by Dan Edelstein in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Literature & Literary Criticism. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2009
ISBN
9780226184401
PART I
image
A SECRET HISTORY OF
NATURAL REPUBLICANISM
IN FRANCE (1699–1791)
image
CHAPTER ONE
image
IMAGINARY REPUBLICS
IN THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY, republics existed primarily in books. To be sure, there was Casanova’s Venice and Rousseau’s Geneva, along with Bayle’s United Provinces and a few others (the Swiss cantons, San Marino, and various northern Italian states), but to most observers, these governments were mostly aristocratic and, moreover, were increasingly sidelined to “the fringe of history.”1 The vibrant republics that had inspired Renaissance theorists—Florence in particular—had either disappeared from the political scene or fallen into politico-economic slumber. When eighteenth-century authors wrote about republicanism, it was from a very different perspective than Machiavelli or Harrington: They were describing less a reality than an imagined past or future.
Even as imaginary entities, however, republics had a very real existence. Livy’s Early History of Rome was taught in nearly all French collĂšges—those “nurseries [pĂ©piniĂšres] of republicans,” as Robespierre later called them—lighting up the minds of students with heroic scenes from a bygone world.2 “Everyone knows the history of this republic by heart,” Jaucourt began his EncyclopĂ©die article on the Roman Republic.3 Relegated to books, republics and their glorious citizens obtained a fantastical and alluring hue: Plutarch’s generals and statesmen became imaginary models for adolescents.4 This romancing of republicanism had long worried defenders of monarchy: In Leviathan, Hobbes had expressly warned against “the Reading of the books of Policy, and Histories of the antient Greeks, and Romans; from which . . . men have undertaken to kill their Kings, because the Greek and Latine writers . . . make it lawfull, and laudable, for any man so to do.”5 So concerned were the authorities of the University of Cambridge in 1627 that the new professor of classical history, Isaac Dorislaus, was corrupting the youth with his rousing discussions of Tacitus and the fall of the Roman Republic, they suspended him after only two lectures. Dorislaus would later eat his plate of vengeance cold, assisting the prosecution during the trial of Charles I.6
If nothing new, these attachments to ancient republics became only exaggerated in the age of sensibilitĂ©. Where Don Quixote’s aristocratic delusions stemmed from an overdose of chivalric romances, eighteenth-century readers seem to have experienced similar republican fantasies. While undoubtedly more bovaryiste than his contemporaries, Rousseau’s republicanism derived much more, by his own account, from classical sources than his native city’s traditions: “Ceaselessly occupied with Rome and Athens; living, so to speak, with their great men . . . I believed myself to be Greek or Roman; I became the character whose life I read.” Once over dinner he reenacted the famous gesture that earned Gaius Mucius his nickname of Scaevola—and nearly burnt his right hand in the process.7 After his revelation on the road to Vincennes to visit Diderot, Rousseau “converted” to a life of republican virtue, with a rapturous enthusiasm reminiscent of his earlier (and later) flights of fancy into the pays des chimĂšres.8
The regal splendor of eighteenth-century courts served only to accentuate the delusive nature of these republican fantasies. Louis-SĂ©bastien Mercier depicted in exquisite and humorous detail how confusing it was to come of age in a world centered around a king but enamored with ancient republics:
The name of Rome is the first that caught my attention. As soon as I could grasp rudimentary ideas, I was told the story of Romulus and his she-wolf, and had the Capitol and Tiber described to me. The names of Brutus, Cato, and Scipio pursued me in my sleep; Cicero’s familiar epistles were piled into my memory . . . in such a manner that I was far away from Paris, a foreigner in her walls, living in Rome, which I have never seen, and probably never will.9
As with Rousseau, it was primarily in Livy’s airbrushed portrait of pre-imperial Rome that Mercier discovered the heroic world of republicanism.10 The spellbinding power of this lost Roman world led Mercier (as Hobbes before him) to ponder why, in an absolutist monarchy, students are not only permitted but encouraged to spend their formative years with republican authors who celebrate tyrannicidal acts:
It is certain that the study of Latin imparts a certain taste for republics, and that one wishes to restore the one whose great and long history one reads. . . . It is nonetheless in a monarchy that young people perpetually entertain these strange ideas, which they must quickly lose and forget, for their safety, success, and happiness; and it is an absolute king who pays professors to expound in all seriousness on the eloquent declamations against the power of kings; in such a way that a university student, when he finds himself in Versailles, and has some sense, cannot help but to think of Tarquin, of Brutus, of all the proud enemies of royalty. Then he nearly loses his head . . . and it takes a while for him to acquaint himself with a country that has no tribunes, no decemvirs, no senators, and no consuls.11
Republican fantasies, in Mercier’s account, reveal themselves to be just that—the illusory dreams of an adolescent boy, who, in Mably’s words, “ruined his mind reading the beloved history of the Greeks and Romans, who now only make good novel or theater heroes.”12 These dreams were not restricted to boys: adolescent girls, most notably Manon Phlipon, the future Mme Roland, and Charlotte Corday, also indulged in Roman republican fantasies.13 Whether or not it was thought possible to create a republic in France, “the heroism of nascent republics” (to borrow HelvĂ©tius’s phrase) did not cease to enchant.14 The few French subjects who would rather have been citizens of a French Republic even before 1789 also seem to have acquired their political views from books on Roman history: Camille Demoulins allegedly carried a copy of the abbĂ© Vertot’s Histoire des rĂ©volutions arrivĂ©es dans le gouvernement de la RĂ©publique romaine, a bastardized version of Livy, in his pocket as a schoolboy.15 As his later speeches and writings reveal, Desmoulins was very familiar with the classical-republican tradition: He was one of few Jacobins not to use “Machiavellian” as a synonym for “deceitful,” but instead cited the Machiavelli of the Discorsi.16 Even revolutionaries, such as Saint-Just, who had revealed few republican feelings before August 10, 1792, burst into austere Roman discourse as soon as they made the switch.17
While there may not have been a “republican party” in prerevolutionary France, there certainly seems to have been a republican cultural imagination that would be fired up by revolutionary events, even if it did not contribute to their advent. But what are we to make of the fact that republicanism occupied the same lieu de mĂ©moire as romanced, and often fanciful, histories of antiquity? To begin with, this close proximity obliges us to look at works of the imagination if we are to complete the eighteenth-century history of republicanism. This fictional context, however, also affects the way we study it: The “imaginary” life of republicanism was certainly much looser and freer than the traditional grammar and narrative of political thought demanded.
These imaginative reworkings of republicanism did not necessarily constitute “utopian” projections. The essential republican keywords (for example, virtue, corruption, mƓurs, equality, liberty) remained present, as did the central institutions (notably religious festivals, pedagogical institutions, and citizen armies). The parts stayed the same: It was their relations that changed, and with them, the shape of the republican discourse and story. If the distinction between imaginary republics and utopian representations sometimes appears slim, as in the case of FĂ©nelon’s Boetica, the label “utopian” does not confer any advantages, at least for the present study: Not only does it trivialize the republican dimension of these political projects, but it also implies that contemporary readers could not have distinguished the clearly fantastical traits from the more relevant and familiar. As Dena Goodman emphasized, literature in the Enlightenment participated in the wider empirical trend of “experimentation.”18 Under the cover of utopian states, authors could express ideas that were more subversive than fantastic. Fiction, for the philosophes, offered an opportunity to explore “possible worlds”—a Leibnizian notion that has recently regained favor in literary theory—that rested on certain fundamentally different premises, but that nonetheless obeyed logic and causality.19 This experimental strategy was famously employed in one of the most widely read works of the eighteenth century, FĂ©nelon’s Aventures de TĂ©lĂ©maque, analyzed below. Through such literary, political, and philosophical texts, a cultural and legal imagination emerged that would inform the institutions and laws of the new French state, once the Revolution had made it possible to imagine the state anew.20
The State of Nature and the Golden Age:
From Montaigne to FĂ©nelon
Where ancient Rome and the Peloponnesian city-states generally provided both the fodder and backdrop for eighteenth-century debates on political theory, a different classical referent lay at the heart of the more experimental and imaginative Enlightenment reworkings of classical republicanism: the myth of the golden age.21 A fixture of various cultural discourses in the early-modern period, this myth had also become associated with the condition in which the New World “savages” lived.22 Montaigne’s essay “On Cannibals” was only the most famous text to invoke this Greek myth in reference to their “state of nature.”23 Although this specific expression became current only with Hobbes, American societies were certainly perceived in Montaigne’s time as living in a condition ruled by nature alone: The cannibales “are still in that happy state of desiring only as much as their natural needs demand.”24 But unlike the Hobbesian version of the state of nature (discussed in the introduction), the inhabitants of this “ñge dorĂ©â€ obeyed the laws of nature: “Natural laws, not yet bowdlerized by our own, command them.”25 Montaigne was so impressed by their “primitive rules given by Nature” (in Virgil’s words, which he quotes) that he compared the entirety of his Essais to their natural condition, in a prefatory text: “Had I been placed among those nations which are said to live still in the sweet freedom of nature’s first laws, I assure you I should very gladly have portrayed myself here entire and wholly naked.”26
As in Ovid’s celebrated description of the golden age, the state of nature that Montaigne perceived in Brazil is defined primarily by negation: It knows neither writing nor arithmetic, riches nor poverty, contracts nor inheritances, agriculture nor metallurgy, wine nor wheat. Certain important differences with the classical referent do stand out: The inhabitants of the golden age were vegetarians, whereas the cannibales, of course, were not. They digested their enemies after vanquishing them in war, another unknown activity during the Age of Gold. Other differences are more subtle. Where Ovid had underscored the absence of laws and judges in the golden age,27 Montaigne added a more pointed political commentary: The cannibales had “no name for a magistrate or for political superiority.”28 This insistence on the fact that sovereignty—a key political issue after the publication of Jean Bodin’s Les Six livres de la RĂ©publique in 1572, eight years before the first edition of the Essais—was missing from the state of nature is reinforced at the end of the essay, when Montaigne relates two observations allegedly made by the cannibales ...

Table of contents