Time for Things
eBook - ePub

Time for Things

Stephen D. Rosenberg

Share book
  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Time for Things

Stephen D. Rosenberg

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Modern life is full of stuff yet bereft of time. An economic sociologist offers an ingenious explanation for why, over the past seventy-five years, Americans have come to prefer consumption to leisure. Productivity has increased steadily since the mid-twentieth century, yet Americans today work roughly as much as they did then: forty hours per week. We have witnessed, during this same period, relentless growth in consumption. This pattern represents a striking departure from the preceding century, when working hours fell precipitously. It also contradicts standard economic theory, which tells us that increasing consumption yields diminishing marginal utility, and empirical research, which shows that work is a significant source of discontent. So why do we continue to trade our time for more stuff? Time for Things offers a novel explanation for this puzzle. Stephen Rosenberg argues that, during the twentieth century, workers began to construe consumer goods as stores of potential free time to rationalize the exchange of their labor for a wage. For example, when a worker exchanges their labor for an automobile, they acquire a duration of free activity that can be held in reserve, counterbalancing the unfree activity represented by work. This understanding of commodities as repositories of hypothetical utility was made possible, Rosenberg suggests, by the standardization of durable consumer goods, as well as warranties, brands, and product-testing, which assured wage earners that the goods they purchased would be of consistent, measurable quality.This theory clarifies perplexing aspects of behavior under industrial capitalism—the urgency to spend earnings on things, the preference to own rather than rent consumer goods—as well as a variety of historical developments, including the coincident rise of mass consumption and the legitimation of wage labor.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Time for Things an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Time for Things by Stephen D. Rosenberg in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Economics & Economic History. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2021
ISBN
9780674250529
ONE
Introduction
In 1930, against the backdrop of the Depression, John Maynard Keynes wrote a short essay entitled “Economic Possibilities for Our Grandchildren” in which he cast his gaze beyond the economic ferment of his times to prognosticate about the future of capitalism.1 Abandoning for a moment the short- and medium-run temporalities of his discipline, as well as the economist’s preoccupation with scarcity and dismal trade-offs, Keynes became entranced by a much brighter vision. Economic growth would, in Keynes’s view, eventually bring about an end to toil. A renaissance of human civilization would ensue, a cultural flowering reminiscent of the classical Greek ideal (or perhaps that of bohemian Bloomsbury). However, this one would not be bought at the expense of an army of slaves (or a household full of servants) but rather would be secured through exponential economic growth. Keynes’s reasoning was straightforward enough. He simply took the estimated historical growth rate of capitalist economies and projected it over the following one hundred years. Assuming past rates of productivity improvement would continue unabated for the next century, the economy would, over that period, grow eightfold in per capita terms. “Mankind is solving its economic problem,” Keynes proclaimed—such, he reflected, is the almost magical power of compound growth. Similarly, when Keynes looked back at the trend in work time in industrial capitalism over the previous fifty years, he saw a pattern he had no reason to believe would not continue. Increasing productivity had led to a steep and continuous decline in the length of the work week between 1870 and 1930, with working hours dropping by 30 percent in Europe and the United States. In predicting the future of capitalism, Keynes simply posited the continuation of that trend.
The conclusion Keynes drew from his brief exercise in futurology was that the productivity gains yielded by capitalism would, in the long run, inevitably lead the economy to enter into a stationary (or “steady”) state, in which material wants would be satiated. Further increases in productivity would then have the effect of reducing the need for labor, radically diminishing the length of the working week. The result would be an utter transformation in the moral fabric of capitalism, returning pecuniary motive to the marginal place it held in previous eras of history and opening up new possibilities for human flourishing. Keynes predicted that in the coming era of abundance, “we shall once more value ends above means and prefer the good to the useful.” To be sure, there would be a period of adjustment during which people would have to cultivate the skills and sensibility necessary for them to be able to fully enjoy their liberation. Indeed, Keynes thought that such is the cultural momentum, under capitalism, behind work for work’s sake, that people might for a while voluntarily arrest the decline in work hours. He imagined people resisting working for fewer than fifteen or so hours each week, for no good reason other than to keep themselves busy. But they would certainly not choose to work more than that, for “three hours a day is quite enough to satisfy the old Adam in most of us” (Keynes 1930, p. 369). In effect, capitalism, conceived of as a system of self-exploitation and the fetishistic pursuit of monetary gain would abolish itself—or, more precisely, would evolve into something utterly different—simply by virtue of following its natural developmental trajectory. The Faustian pact made at the dawn of the modern era, having achieved its goals, was thus destined to be undone. “Purposive man,” to use Keynes’s phrase, would be laid to rest, having served his purpose admirably.2
In 2005, a group of eminent economists, including such luminaries as Robert Solow, Joseph Stiglitz, and Gary Becker, was invited to contribute essays to a book intended to evaluate Keynes’s predictions about the future of capitalism (Pecchi and Piga 2008). The historical data analyzed by these economists showed that Keynes’s growth projections were, if anything, on the conservative side. His predictions for growth, based on a long-run estimate of about 2 percent per year, yielded an upper bound eightfold increase in per capita wealth over the next hundred years. Fabrizio Zilibotti found, however, that in the fifty-year period between 1950 and 2000, average world economic growth was 2.9 percent per year, quadrupling per capita output.3 Projected over one century, that rate of growth would produce a seventeenfold increase in the standard of living, twice as much as the upper bound predicted by Keynes. Most of the growth in the earlier part of the period took place in advanced capitalist economies. In Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD) nations, between 1950 and 1970, population-weighted growth levels reached an impressive 4 percent per year.4 And yet despite the impressive rate of per capita growth, Keynes’s prediction of the dawning of a new era in which human beings would be progressively freed from necessary labor, and therefore increasingly able to pursue life-enhancing practices, was not, by the early 2000s (when the economists examined the issue), even remotely close to being realized. By the late 1940s full-time weekly working hours had stabilized at around forty across the industrial capitalist world and failed, thereafter, to fall much further, despite tremendous growth in output per hour of work in the second half of the century. Indeed, there is evidence that toward the end of the twentieth century, work time in some parts of the industrial world increased, even as productivity gains marched relentlessly onward.5
Economists offer a range of explanations for the failure of Keynes’s prediction, some of which are close to being circular. One explanation is that work is itself a source of utility—surely that must be so, the reasoning goes, or else why would people not choose to cut their hours? Alternatively, material wants must indeed be insatiable—why else would people choose income over leisure? Other explanations offered are more substantive: consumption under conditions of affluence becomes driven by status-seeking one-upmanship, and the demand for positional goods (which index relative position in a status hierarchy) can never be exhausted; growing inequality induces a widespread fear of downward social mobility and so increases the incentive to work in order to close the income gap; higher income creates new needs, such that needs are not fixed but rather change with economic growth. These explanations surely have something to them. No one could sensibly deny that some people find some value in activities for which they happen to be paid, nor would it be wise to underestimate concerns about status and the role of conspicuous consumption in status competition. However, the explanations offered do not, for reasons set out in the next chapter, satisfactorily account for the dramatic degree to which Keynes’s vision of the future failed to come to pass.6 Indeed, the very fact that there is such disagreement between the economists on why, in the wake of growing affluence, work failed to retreat more than it did, indicates the difficulty of the puzzle.
Closely related to the question of why work hours failed to decrease more as productivity went up is the question of why consumption continued to increase so relentlessly. Productivity gains, in lieu of reduced work time, were turned into higher real income, which was used to fund more consumption. Why is consumption, like production, seemingly unbounded under capitalism? There is clearly a plausible explanation for the unending expansion of capitalist production: Capitalists try to outcompete one another by increasing productivity, seeking to turn lower costs into a bigger market share by cutting prices and expanding output. Yet it is not at all clear why effective demand should keep up with expanded output—why, in Keynes’s terms, the demand for commodities should prevail over the demand for free time, even though the relative value of those commodities should, it seems, decline with growing affluence. This ongoing growth in consumption is especially puzzling given evidence that suggests that the relation between wealth and well-being is far from being a simple linear one in which added increments of wealth add increments of well-being.
The question of why and how the production and consumption of commodities should have come in modern times to so dominate human beings is a venerable one in the history of social theories of capitalism. It was posed in perhaps its most general and powerful form by Karl Marx, for whom the most fundamental contradiction in capitalism is between the degree of freedom made possible by advances in the forces of production and the form of life actually realized (and realizable) under capitalism. The capitalist system, for Marx, represented a kind of false necessity (albeit, in his more teleological moments, a developmentally necessary one) that history was destined to transcend.
From a different perspective, the question also underlies Max Weber’s theory of the historical and cultural underpinnings of capitalism. For Weber, the growth dynamic of capitalism is precisely what separates it from the comparatively static economies of “traditional” societies. While Weber was interested in the spirit that drives the unremitting increases in productivity under capitalism, the other side of the equation is that which allows for the absorption of an ever-increasing volume of products (Weber [1930] 1992). Weber suggested that the methodical, rational mode of economic action and organization that underlay the ascent of modern capitalism was driven by a quest for psychological reassurance by way of the accumulation of objectified value, rendered visible as money. Money provided a metric by which success, and therefore virtue, could be measured.7 But crucially, instrumental reason could not be monetized—therefore quantified in a general, public form, one amenable to comparative assessment—unless a ready market could be found for the things it produced. How could the productivity of capitalist A, making widgets, be compared to capitalist B, making pots, if their products were not converted through sales into money? A condition of possibility for the economy becoming a domain within which the Protestant ethic (and its secularized spiritual descendants) could express itself was thus a dynamic consumer market, capable of absorbing the ever-greater volume of products churned out by a system of production ever more regimented by instrumental reason, and converting it into a generalized, quantitative sign of value.
Bringing the concerns of Marx together with those of Weber, the question of the unbounded and irrational character of capitalist modernity was also a central concern for later generations of Marxists, most prominently those belonging to the Frankfurt School. They asked: How is it that the accumulation of wealth and refinement of technique, which should be merely a means to the end of the good life, become in effect ends unto themselves? Why, under capitalist modernity, does instrumental rationality become so systemically entrenched, unable to mature (as Keynes thought it would do) to the point of becoming (as reason suggests it should be) just a means to a higher purpose? True to their Marxian roots, the Frankfurt theorists tended to focus on cultural forms generated by the organization of the relations of production—yet they clearly also saw that without mass consumption modern industrial capitalism could not function.
The stakes in the puzzle represented by this configuration of ever-increasing production and consumption are, of course, very high given the extraordinarily urgent environmental problems of our age. Despite much talk about deindustrialization, the shift to services, and the rise of the “knowledge economy” under late capitalism, the capitalist system of production and consumption is pressing harder than ever against the limits of nature. So not only is the materialistic bias of capitalism questionable from the proximate perspective of the well-being it yields, but it in addition threatens the long-term future of the species.
This book is an extended investigation of this puzzle. My objectives are to delineate its conceptual structure, analyze its empirical basis, and build a historically grounded theory in light of which the puzzling pattern of work, productivity, and consumption becomes less puzzling. I follow the tradition, rooted equally, although in very different ways, in Marx and Weber, of doing social theory by thinking about history. While I consider general trends under capitalism in the industrial world, the empirical side of the book focuses on the United States, especially during the middle decades of the twentieth century.
My contention is that the reason why work failed to retreat in the face of relentlessly increasing productivity has much to do with the rise of practices and institutions associated with mass consumer society. Yet to adduce the supposed benefits of consumption as an adequate explanation for the failure of Keynes’s prediction to come true just raises the question of why spending should have seemed more beneficial than free time. After all, it is not unreasonable to expect that as incomes increase, so the demand for leisure will also increase. Canonical economists such as Frank Knight (1921) and Arthur Pigou (1932) certainly thought as much.8 With higher wage rates, the relative value of leisure should, according to these economists, increase, and workers should consequently feel less inclined to offer their labor.9 The prediction that follows from this is that other things being equal, with growing affluence the supply curve of labor should become backward sloping. And yet the historical pattern under industrial capitalism between 1930 and the present day indicates not much evidence in support of that prediction. At the same time, there is evidence from late nineteenth-century America that workers in that period chose to use increasing hourly income to buy back their time—meaning that the supply curve of labor was, in the decades before the turning of the twentieth century, indeed backward sloping (Dora Costa 1998b, 2000a). So it has certainly not always been the case that increasing hourly wages has led to more consumption rather than less work. Yet after a certain point in history that is how things quite consistently went. We are thus left with some unanswered questions. What changed to make consumption as unbounded as production? Why did the value of free time apparently decline in relative terms as affluence increased? What was it about the set of institutions, practices, and moral norms associated with mass consumption that might have caused a shift in aggregate preferences away from free time and toward the accumulation of consumer goods?
I think that the answer to these questions might be found by attending to the problem of wage-labor commensuration and to the development of a form of consumption that seemingly resolves this problem. The problem of wage-labor commensuration is that the legitimacy of wage-labor exchange depends on labor being commensurable with its wage, but it is entirely unclear how the concrete activity of work could be commensurable with the wage, which, after all, is just an abstraction. The possibility of commensuration between wage and work rests, I argue in this book, on goods being framed and construed as stores of potential free activity. When wages are spent on goods that signify hypothetical durations of activity, wage earners receive a form of compensation that seems commensurable with the life activity they give up in labor. The actual time and freedom lost as work is compensated for by the notional free time indexed by consumer goods—and specifically, consumer durables, a category of product that became increasingly important in twentieth-century capitalism. Caught in a cycle of commensuration, wage workers were willing to take their share of rising productivity (realized as increasing hourly wages) as more consumption rather than more free time.
The commensurability of labor and wage made sense in the context of a particular understanding of the grounds on which an economic exchange can be considered fair. On this understanding, economic exchanges are fair when there is an equality between the exchanged substances. The emergence of mass consumption was closely connected to the increasing de facto legitimacy of wage-labor exchange, under this historically particular understanding of economic fairness, applied to wage labor. The fairness of wage labor exchange became possible through the establishment of an objective equivalence between labor and wage goods, as those goods came to signify free activity. This version of economic fairness was most clearly instantiated in the moral economy that underpinned the mid-century “Fordist” period of capitalism.
The Character and Scope of the Argument
The approach taken in this book is interdisciplinary, ranging across all the social sciences and diverse currents of historical research while also drawing on philosophical works. Especially in the theory sections of the book, I discuss a variety of sometimes conflicting paradigms. I ask my readers to consider approaches to social and economic phenomena with which they might be unfamiliar or perhaps might even think self-evidently wrong. The discussion turns on a dime, as it were, from neoclassical economics to Marxian accounts of capitalism, from economic anthropology to sociological theory, from political economy to behavioral psychology. At the same time, the book combines economic analysis, historical synthesis, sometimes quite speculative social theorizing, and interpretation of culture, bringing together methods and approaches that have their homes in different disciplines. But there are good reasons for tromping freely across disciplinary boundaries when considering big questions of the sort that are at the center of this book. When faced with very complex, multifaceted problems, the best approach is to regard the human sciences as a diverse tool kit, and, in order to gain some leverage on the problem, try out as many theoretical approaches and concepts as possible.
My historical analysis focuses on the United States. At the same time, I often refer to advanced capitalist society in general, especially during its postwar Golden Age era, as my unit of analysis. As noted in Chapter 2, the general puzzling pattern of work time, productivity, and consumption is present to varying degrees in every affluent capitalist society. Given its focus on the United States, I c...

Table of contents