Relativity
eBook - ePub

Relativity

The Special and the General Theory

Albert Einstein

Share book
  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Relativity

The Special and the General Theory

Albert Einstein

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

After completing the final version of his general theory of relativity in November 1915, Albert Einstein wrote a book about relativity for a popular audience. His intention was 'to give an exact insight into the theory of relativity to those readers who, from a general scientific and philosophical point of view, are interested in the theory, but who are not conversant with the mathematical apparatus of theoretical physics.' The book remains one of the most lucid explanations of the special and general theories ever written. In the early 1920s alone, it was translated into ten languages, and fifteen editions in the original German appeared over the course of Einstein's lifetime. The theory of relativity enriched physics and astronomy during the 20th century.

ABOUT THE AUTHOR:
Albert Einstein, a gentleman who belongs to the elite league of Newton, Tesla, Maxwell and considered to be the greatest scientist of 20th century. Born in Germany, and worked as a clerk in the patent office before revolutionizing the world of physics, Einstein with his incredible achievements in scientific world has become synonymous to the word genius. He provided the world, two of the most brilliant concepts of physics through his theories of relativity, and won the Noble Prize in Physics for his work on Photoelectric Effect, which eventually become the foundation stone for tremendous developments in electronic technologies and quantum theory. Einstein is not only celebrated as the greatest physicists of all the time but he was also a wonderful human being and philosopher. World War II and presence of Adolf Hitler in Germany forced him to stay in the US during the period, where he consistently tried hard to warn and evade the application of nuclear fission as a weapon of mass destruction. He collaborated and interacted with many extraordinary minds of his time contributing to the world of physics and humanity as a whole. His unmatched intellectual imagination collaged with his immense interest in music, philosophy and humanity makes him the greatest personality that scientific world and mankind have ever seen.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on ā€œCancel Subscriptionā€ - itā€™s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time youā€™ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlegoā€™s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan youā€™ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, weā€™ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Relativity an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Relativity by Albert Einstein in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Physical Sciences & Relativity in Physics. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2018
ISBN
9788193540176
Ā 
Ā 
Ā 
Part 1
The Special Theory of Relativity
Ā 
Ā 
Ā 
Ā 
1. Physical Meaning of Geometrical Propositions
symbol15.webp
Ā 
Ā 
Ā 
In your schooldays most of you who read this book made acquaintance with the noble building of Euclidā€™s geometry and you remember ā€” perhaps with more respect than love ā€” the magnificent structure, on the lofty staircase of which you were chased about for uncounted hours by conscientious teachers. By reason of your past experience, you would certainly regard everyone with disdain who should pronounce even the most out-of-the-way proposition of this science to be untrue. But perhaps this feeling of proud certainty would leave you immediately if someone were to ask you: ā€œWhat, then, do you mean by the assertion that these propositions are true?ā€ Let us proceed to give this question a little consideration.
Geometry sets out from certain conceptions such as ā€˜planeā€™, ā€˜pointā€™, and ā€˜straight lineā€™, with which we are able to associate more or less definite ideas, and from certain simple propositions (axioms) which, in virtue of these ideas, we are inclined to accept as ā€˜trueā€™. Then, on the basis of a logical process, the justification of which we feel ourselves compelled to admit, all remaining propositions are shown to follow from those axioms, i.e. they are proven. A proposition is then correct (ā€˜trueā€™) when it has been derived in the recognised manner from the axioms. The question of ā€˜truthā€™ of the individual geometrical propositions is thus reduced to one of the ā€˜truthā€™ of the axioms. Now it has long been known that the last question is not only unanswerable by the methods of geometry, but that it is in itself entirely without meaning. We cannot ask whether it is true that only one straight line goes through two points. We can only say that Euclidean geometry deals with things called ā€˜straight linesā€™, to each of which is ascribed the property of being uniquely determined by two points situated on it. The concept ā€˜trueā€™ does not tally with the assertions of pure geometry, because by the word ā€˜trueā€™ we are eventually in the habit of designating always the correspondence with a ā€˜realā€™ object; geometry, however, is not concerned with the relation of the ideas involved in it to objects of experience, but only with the logical connection of these ideas among themselves.
It is not difficult to understand why, in spite of this, we feel constrained to call the propositions of geometry ā€˜trueā€™. Geometrical ideas correspond to more or less exact objects in nature, and these last are undoubtedly the exclusive cause of the genesis of those ideas. Geometry ought to refrain from such a course, in order to give to its structure the largest possible logical unity. The practice, for example, of seeing in a ā€˜distanceā€™ two marked positions on a practically rigid body is something which is lodged deeply in our habit of thought. We are accustomed further to regard three points as being situated on a straight line, if their apparent positions can be made to coincide for observation with one eye, under suitable choice of our place of observation.
If, in pursuance of our habit of thought, we now supplement the propositions of Euclidean geometry by the single proposition that two points on a practically rigid body always correspond to the same distance (line-interval), independently of any changes in position to which we may subject the body, the propositions of Euclidean geometry then resolve themselves into propositions on the possible relative position of practically rigid bodies.1 Geometry, which has been supplemented in this way, is then to be treated as a branch of physics. We can now legitimately ask as to the ā€˜truthā€™ of geometrical propositions interpreted in this way, since we are justified in asking whether these propositions are satisfied for those real things we have associated with the geometrical ideas. In less exact terms we can express this by saying that by the ā€˜truthā€™ of a geometrical proposition in this sense we understand its validity for a construction with rule and compasses.
1. It follows that a natural object is associated also with a straight line. Three points A, B and C on a rigid body thus lie in a straight line when the points A and C being given, B is chosen such that the sum of the distances AB and BC is as short as possible. This incomplete suggestion will suffice for the present purpose.
Ā 
Of course the conviction of the ā€˜truthā€™ of geometrical propositions in this sense is founded exclusively on rather incomplete experience. For the present we shall assume the ā€˜truthā€™ of the geometrical propositions, then at a later stage (in the general Theory of Relativity) we shall see that this ā€˜truthā€™ is limited, and we shall consider the extent of its limitation.
Ā 
2. The System of Co-ordinates
symbol15.webp
On the basis of the physical interpretation of distance which has been indicated, we are also in a position to establish the distance between two points on a rigid body by means of measurements. For this purpose we require a ā€˜distanceā€™ (rod S) which is to be used once and for all, and which we employ as a standard measure. If, now, A and B are two points on a rigid body, we can construct the line joining them according to the rules of geometry. Then, starting from A, we can mark off the distance S time after time until we reach B. The number of these operations required is the numerical measure of the distance AB. This is the basis of all measurement of length.2
2. Here we have assumed that there is nothing left over, i.e. that the measurement gives a whole number. This difficulty is got over by the use of divided measuring-rods, the introduction of which does not demand any fundamentally new method.
Every description of the scene of an event or of the position of an object in space is based on the specification of the point on a rigid body (body of reference) with which that event or object coincides. This applies not only to scientific description, but also to everyday life. If I analyse the place specification ā€˜Times Square, New York,ā€™3 I arrive at the following result. The earth is the rigid body to which the specification of place refers; ā€˜Times Square, New Yorkā€™ is a well-defined point to which a name has been assigned and with which the event coincides in space.4
3. Einstein used ā€˜Potsdamer Platz, Berlinā€™ in the original text. In the authorised translation this was supplemented with ā€˜Trafalgar Square, Londonā€™. We have changed this to ā€˜Times Square, New Yorkā€™, as this is the most well known/identifiable location to English speakers in the present day. [Note by the janitor.]
4. It is not necessary here to investigate further the significance of the expression ā€˜coincidence in spaceā€™. This conception is sufficiently obvious to ensure that differences of opinion are scarcely likely to arise as to its applicability in practice.
This primitive method of place specification deals only with places on the surface o...

Table of contents