Trends in infancy research: absolute beginners?
Psychology, and in particular developmental psychology, is heir to a longstanding set of philosophical, epistemological questions about the nature and growth of knowledge, and indeed was hailed from the start as the forum in which to test out competing theories (much as computer modelling is claimed to do now). By this account, biology and epistemology meet in the study of developmental psychology. Taking a broad look at Anglo-US and European psychology of the last 150 years, general social preoccupations and moral orientations are reproduced within the history of infancy research. The child study movement of the late nineteenth century and early twentieth century was motivated by questions drawn from evolutionary theory, that is, comparing animals and humans, and different groups of humans, to evaluate the role of heredity. But, from the 1920s until approximately the 1960s, behaviourist ideas shifted attention away from genetic endowment to environmental history, with a corresponding preoccupation with child training. The model of the child was as a passive recipient of experience, with emphasis placed on quality of environment such that parents were seen as responsible for moulding and producing an appropriate moral character. The philosophical framework for this model of the child was empiricism, where the mind is conceived of as a blank slate (Locke) or, in pragmatic varieties, as âblooming, buzzing confusionâ (James). Since the behaviourists were reluctant to attribute any internal structure or organisation to the âorganismâ â consistent with their denial of unobservable mental activity or events (which was in part their âresponseâ to introspectionist approaches) â the acquisition of knowledge was held to occur through conditioning, that is, through selective reinforcement based on environmental contingencies or learning from experience.
While it would be simplistic to treat these as sequential shifts, broadly speaking the 1970s saw a change of model from an incompetent infant assumed to know nothing, to a competent infant depicted as arriving already equipped with, or at least predisposed to acquire, sophisticated skills. This change arose in part from technological developments which could attest to the complex capacities of even newborns, but it also reflected the eclipse of behaviourism and the rise of cognitive psychology. The reversal of perspective (from blank slate to preprogrammed) was evident in the moral tone of righteous indignation with which books like Stone et al.âs (1973) The competent infant are presented. The very term âcompetentâ was used âto stress that, from his [sic] earliest days, every infant is an active, perceiving, learning and information-organising individualâ (Stone et al., 1973: 4). Accounts of this period celebrated the achievements of modern science as miraculously transforming the understanding of infant development: âall at once it seemed possible to obtain empirical answers where previously there had been largely theoretical speculation and inference ⊠in what had previously seemed to be chaotic variability of response and responsiveness took on new meaning and orderâ (Stone et al., 1973: 6). Science promised order in measuring the individual via infant research, and the metaphor of comprehension becomes almost literally a process of grasping the mystery of infancy by means of new techniques. Technology was accorded a key role in revising the image of the newborn:
While new technologies undoubtedly played an important role in generating new research, the driving force behind the âdiscoveryâ of neonatal qualities was not only to do with the accumulation of more facts from the accelerating pace of infancy studies but was also due to the replacement of behaviourism by biologism and cognitivism.
The rhetoric of wonder and (self-)congratulation of the 1970s technical reports was replayed in subsequent popular accounts: âBorn brilliant. Itâs amazing what your newborn can doâ read the November 1989 cover of Practical Parenting, with the inside story starting: âJust arrived â isnât he clever! A newborn baby is much more interesting than anyone could imagine. . . . Take time to study your baby, get to know him and discover the many different ways that make him uniqueâ. A similar account read: âBaby brilliance â the secrets revealed. Exciting new research suggests that babies know more and learn much faster than we think?â (Under Five, November/December 1990). Hence the modern commitment to science as progress, with developmental psychology accumulating facts on the way to complete knowledge, is reiterated within the process of documenting the individual infantâs increasing maturity.
While claims about the âscience inside the childâ, including the infant, resonate until the present day (Meadows, 2015), further technological developments such as ultrasound have rendered the embryo not only visible but also amenable to investigation (Franklin, 1997; Hepper, 2005). Increasingly the foetus, embryo or unborn child becomes a recognisable, knowable entity. Indeed, as commercial companies are now capitalising upon (Roberts, 2012), the ultrasound scan offers parents-to-be a first encounter with their offspring that reinscribes scientific authority even as it constructs the moral personhood of both the parents and the social roles of, in particular, fathers (Draper, 2002). The production of the scan, therefore, although a medicalised procedure involving technology and professional expertise, functions as a cultural ritual, involving specific social and relational practices as well as material artefacts. It is also one that relies upon the primacy of the visual, consistent with the history of the development of occidental knowledge, which as Draper points out, has shifted the domain of knowledge away from the pregnant womanâs sense of her own body and sensation, in favour of an image that is available for all to see (albeit one requiring considerable interpretation), and one whose qualities and capacities are increasingly being specified (see Lupton, 2012).
From the 1970s, as a corollary of the representation of the ever-more-able child, a new research ethos emphasised how the infant takes an active role in moulding the environment in which she participates. The âchild effectsâ work (e.g. Bell and Harper, 1977) investigated what the child elicits from her caregivers, rather than solely her adaptation to them, and began to piece together a picture of reciprocal learning histories of both caregivers and their charges: how each responded to and learned from the responses of the others. Subsequently, infancy research from the mid-1970s became the forum to test out and develop Piagetian theory, since the sensorimotor period was seen as the arena where Piagetian claims are at their most specific (e.g. Butterworth, 1980) such that even though Piagetâs particular arguments about infant capacities are largely discounted, his methods and questions remain central to discussions (along with Gibson, see Thornton, 2008).
The late 1970s to 1980s saw a diversification of research. One strand continued with an unabated cognitivism, combining the test and application of Piagetian theory with cognitive science (Leiser and GilliĂ©ron, 1990). A second strand, influenced by hermeneutics (e.g. Newson and Shotter, 1974), tried to achieve a reprieve-by-synthesis of (cognitive) innativism and (behaviourist) environmentalism, that is, to move beyond the positions which either denied any structure in the childâs head (behaviourism) or put it all in her head (1960sâ1970s cognitivism). After all, if the attributes and capacities were already there, what is it that could be said to develop? The reaction to behaviourism thereby threatened to fall back into innatism, and most developmental psychologists wanted to avoid this.
So notwithstanding the contested claims arising from neurophysiological research and evolutionary psychology (see later in this chapter), most developmental psychological claims about infant capacities waver somewhere in the space between child and the (so-called) environment, which is also the space between child and adult caregiver. The fact that this is represented as a space, or more precisely that child and adult are treated as prior categories, is itself part of the problem because these categories reproduce the divisions they strive to repair.
We will return to the âbetweenâ aspects of this space in
Chapter 3, and it should also be noted that attending to the spaces of early childhood has spawned not only cultural anthropologies of childhood (including infancy, see Keller, 2008), but also the new discipline of childrenâs geographies (Holloway and Valentine, 2004). Indeed, as we will see in subsequent chapters, the current emphasis following from this includes attention to communication, including its material, embodied, processual and performative characteristics, which (drawing on dialogical approaches) include analysis of the processes by which infant behaviour is interpreted (see Bertau, 2014). Similar ideas have given rise to a focus on adult expectations, attributions and framing of child activity which are taken up in
Chapter 3. Yet alongside this infancy research has witnessed a neo-cognitive return via neuroscience that warrants a return to innatist hardwiring, albeit as located within the âwetwareâ of the developing brain, and so this also imports an affective as well as malleable or flexible twist. But before we look
at this, we need to explore how infancy research continues the theoretical frameworks that initially gave rise to it, reproducing and reworking them according to changing sociocultural conditions and concerns.
Hangovers: continuity of questions addressed by infancy research
The last 30 years have seen both an acceleration and intensification of research focused on prenatal and very early childhood, led by technological developments enabling brain imaging (fMRI), and neurochemical analysis. Notwithstanding these tumultuous changes, some strange repetitions or fixations remain in the framing of developmental inquiries.
Throughout the study of infancy, research has been organised around a recurring set of preoccupations which include: first, depicting infancy (and now embryonic development) as the evolutionary baseline; second, treating infancy as providing insight into adult development; and thereby, third, demonstrating the association between research and its application.
Infancy as evolutionary baseline
The study of infancy was explicitly undertaken to illuminate the old philosophical debates about the nature and development of knowledge: What is innate? What is acquired? What is the role of experience in the construction of knowledge? As Wordsworth put it, in his 1807
Ode, intimations of immortality: âBut trailing clouds of glory do we come/From God, who is our home:/Heaven lies about us in our infancy!â These philosophical concerns were transformed into specific empirical, psychological questions, such as the extent of early plasticity of the nervous system, and age limits on learning capacities. We continue to see these questions in policy discussions on early intervention, where politicians make large claims about the efficacy of early interventions, in the form of education and parent training, as routes to end child poverty and promote social mobility, as Baroness Tyler put it, in a House of Lords debate on this topic in February 2015, âThe link between early intervention and social mobility is well established. We have the evidence by the bucketloadâ, (
www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/ld201415/ldhansrd/text/150108-0001.htm). While the specific assumptions underlying such claims that link brains, employment and economic prosperity will be discussed in
Chapter 6, it is worth noting how these apparently abstract, epistemological questions are translated into very material and political practices. Developmental psychology positioned itself as the testing ground for age-old epistemological preoccupations, and in so doing it took on board the nineteenth-century framework of comparative psychology, comparing rates of development or states of knowledge between different (age and cultural) groups and species. Different approaches emerged to investigate these questions. Some, now classical, research studies engaged in the experimental study of sensory deprivation in animals, from which it was claimed relevant extrapolations could be made. Examples of this work included Colin Blakemoreâs report that cats raised in visual environments consisting only of vertical and horizontal stripes behaved as though they are blind to diagonals (Blakemore and Cooper, 1970) and Harry Harlowâs (1959) maternal deprivation studies with rhesus monkeys (to be discussed in
Chapter 7).
A second, supposedly less interventionist, approach was the ethological study of animals (Blurton Jones, 1972), especially those designated as the primate evolutionary ancestors to humans. This comparative framework could also extend (by a worrying set of associations) to the study of human societies still living in the âecological nicheâ within which Homo sapiens is said to have evolved, that is, hunter-gatherer societies. Note the implied relation suggested between these two groups â with resonances of the nineteenth-century hierarchisation of societies (Gould, 1984). Ethological approaches were also applied to the analysis of infant and child behaviour in terms of observational techniques claiming to provide neutral descriptions of clusters of actions rather than preconceived interpretative categories (Hinde, 1983), so combining observation with a comparative anthropological perspective.
Later neonatal research claimed to move away from comparative evolutionary explanations. Early infant behaviours, such as the neonatal stepping and rooting responses previously designated as âreflexiveâ (Bremner, 1988), instead became interpreted as having specific individual functions. The stepping was said to help the foetus turn in the intrauterine environment, which, it was hypothesised, in the early stages of prenatal development might prevent adhesion to the wall of the womb and later facilitate engagement of the head in the cervix in preparation for labour. The tone of this interpretation was that we have outpaced species evolution in ontogenetic development, that is, that spontaneous foetal activity arises as adaptation to the womb and that there are continuities between prenatal and neonatal behaviour. Perhaps these ideas have now entered into our commonsense everyday understanding. However, the emphasis on the function of behaviour in specific contexts still harks back to evolutionist assumptions about adaptation and survival value which structured the agenda of infancy research in particular directions. Overall, the commitment to an evolutionary framework prioritised âthe biologicalâ and accounted for the heavy emphasis on physical, and especially perceptual, abilities in the early infancy literature. This âbiologicalâ orientation also assumed that perception is more âbasicâ, and therefore simpler to investigate. This trend was maintained within the arena of artificial intelligence â although here the emphasis on vision and sensory research was also related to other, military, interests (Bowers, 1990).
Although evolutionary psychology has flourished from the 1990s, this lays claim to more complex forms of interactionism rather than genetic or biological determination (Buss and Reeve, 2003). Yet popular sociobiological accounts of mate preference, gendered predispositions to monogamy and polygamy an...