Principles of Cartesian Philosophy
eBook - ePub

Principles of Cartesian Philosophy

Baruch Spinoza, Harry E. Wedeck

Share book
  1. 200 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Principles of Cartesian Philosophy

Baruch Spinoza, Harry E. Wedeck

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This book provides depth and insight into the philosophical doctrine of Rene Descartes, and compares it to the metaphysics of Spinoza himself.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Principles of Cartesian Philosophy an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Principles of Cartesian Philosophy by Baruch Spinoza, Harry E. Wedeck in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Filosofia & Filosofia moderna. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2014
ISBN
9781497675766
PART I
INTRODUCTION
Before entering upon the propositions themselves and their proofs, it seemed fitting to offer a succinct explanation why Descartes questioned everything, in what manner he discovered the firm foundations of knowledge, and finally by what means he freed himself from all his doubts. All this matter we should certainly have reduced to a mathematical orderliness, had we not considered the prolixity necessary for its presentation a hindrance for a proper understanding of the entire subject that ought to be viewed, as in the case of a picture, by a comprehensive survey.
Descartes, then, proceeding with the utmost caution in the investigation of nature, attempted:
1. to reject all pre-conceived notions;
2. to find the bases for all necessary superstructures;
3. to discover the cause of error;
4. to understand everything clearly and distinctly.
In order to attain the first, second, and third objectives, he proceeds to question everything; not indeed as a skeptic, for whom the final end is nothing but doubt, but with a view to freeing his mind from all pre-conceptions and hence to discover ultimately the solid and irrefutable bases of knowledge that he could not fail to discover, if such exist. For the true principles of knowledge must be so lucid and convincing that they require no proof, exclude all risk of doubt, and make any proof impossible without them. After prolonged doubt, Descartes discovered such principles. Upon their discovery, it was not difficult for him to distinguish truth from falsity, to discover the cause of error, and furthermore to take precautions not to assume what is false and doubtful as truth and certainty.
To reach the fourth and last objective, that is, to understand clearly and distinctly, his principal rule was to review all the simple ideas, of which all the others are composed, and to examine them severally. For if he could perceive simple ideas clearly and distinctly, he would doubtless understand all the other ideas composed of these simple ones, with the same clarity and perspicuity. With these preliminary remarks, we shall briefly explain how Descartes called everything into question, found the true principles of knowledge, and liberated himself from the difficulties of doubt.

Universal Doubt

First of all he considers all things perceived by the senses, namely: heaven, earth, and such notions, and even his own person; all these things he had until then believed to exist in the scheme of Nature. And he doubts their certainty, because his own senses had sometimes deceived him and in his dreams had often convinced him that many things really had an objective existence that he had afterward discovered to be illusory; and finally because he had heard others, even in waking moments, assert that they felt pain in limbs that they had long since lost. Therefore it was not without reason that he was able to doubt the existence even of his own body.
From all these circumstances he was able to deduce rightly that the senses were not a very strong foundation on which to build the superstructure of all knowledge—for they can be called in question—but that certainty depends on other, more convincing principles. To pursue such speculations further, he next considers all the universals, such as material nature in general and its extent, likewise shape, quantity, and so on, and also all the mathematical truths. Although these ideas seemed to him more convincing than all those that he had experienced by the sense, he still found a reason for doubting them; since others too had been mistaken about them, and particularly since a certain old notion had been implanted in his mind that a God existed, all-powerful, by whom he had been created just as he was, and who had perhaps made it possible for him to be deceived about those ideas that seemed very clear to him. By this means he questioned everything.

Discovery of the Basis of All Knowledge

To discover the true principles of knowledge, he investigated next whether he had called into question everything that could come within his thought: thus he would examine whether there was not something left perhaps that he had not yet doubted. If indeed he found anything, by such a method of doubting, that could not be called in question for any of the preceding reasons, or for any other reason, he rightly considered that he could accept it as a basis on which to build the superstructure of all his knowledge. And although he now appeared to doubt everything—for he had doubted equally both the notions that he had received through the senses, and those that he perceived through comprehension only—still there was something left to be examined, namely, himself who doubted thus; not in so far as he was composed of a head, hands, and other members of the body, all matters of doubt; but only in so far as he doubted, thought, and so on.
After a careful examination, he realized that he could entertain doubt on this point for none of the previously mentioned reasons. For, whether the thinking process persists in sleep or in wakefulness, he still thinks and is; whether others were in error about other subjects, or even himself, none the less they existed, since they were in error. Nor could he imagine any author of his own nature, however cunning, who could deceive him in this regard; for it must be granted that he himself existed as long as he supposed himself to be deceived. Finally, whatever other cause for doubt might be conceived, none could be adduced that did not at the same time make him overwhelmingly certain of his own existence. Furthermore, adducing more reasons for doubt meant adducing also more proofs to convince him of his own existence. So much so, that wherever he turned to doubt, he was none the less constrained to exclaim: I doubt, I think, therefore I am.
With the discovery of this truth he likewise found the basis of all the sciences; and even a standard and rule for all the other truths, namely: Whatever is perceived as clearly and distinctly as this truth is true.
That no other basis for knowledge than this is possible is abundantly and more than sufficiently clear from what has preceded, since all the other notions can most readily be called in question, but this one cannot be questioned in any manner whatever. However, in regard to this principle, it must first of all be observed that the statement I doubt, I think, therefore I am is not a syllogism, whose major premise has been omitted. For, if it were a syllogism, the premises ought to have been clearer and better known than the conclusion itself, therefore I am: and so I am would not be the first basis of all knowledge; besides, it would not be a certain conclusion, for its truth would depend on universal premises that the author had long since called in question. So I think, therefore I am is a single proposition, equivalent to this one: I am a thinking being.
Furthermore, to avoid confusion in what follows (for the matter must be perceived clearly and distinctly), we must understand what we are. For, once this is clearly and distinctly understood, our being will not be confused with others. To deduce this therefore from what precedes, our author thus continues.
He recalls in memory all the thoughts that he once had regarding himself: that his soul was a subtle body similar to wind, fire, or air, pervading the thicker parts of the body; that his body was more familiar to him than his soul, and that he had a clearer and more distinct perception of it. He found that all this was manifestly at variance with what he had until then understood. For it was possible for him to doubt his body, but not his existence in so far as he could think. Moreover, not perceiving this clearly or distinctly, he consequently had to reject it as false, according to the method that he had proposed for himself. Hence, since he could not, considering what he already knew of himself, recognize the relation of these questions to himself, he proceeded to investigate further what properly belonged to his being, what he had been unable to doubt, and on account of which he was forced to affirm his existence.
Such are the following notions: He must beware of self-deception; he wanted to comprehend many concepts; he questioned everything that he could not comprehend; up to this time he had posited one truth only; he denied everything else, rejecting it as false; even in spite of himself he imagined many things; finally, he observed many things that appeared to come from the senses. Since, equally evidently, his existence rested on each one of these assertions and since he was unable to view any one of them as among the ideas that he had questioned, and finally since they could all be conceived under the same attribute, it followed that they were all truths and belonged to his nature. And so, in saying I think, he understood all these modes of thought: doubt, understanding, affirmation, denial, wishing, not wishing, imagination, and feeling.
It must first of all be observed—and this will be very useful in what follows, where the distinction between mind and matter is discussed:
1st. These modes of thought are clearly and distinctly comprehended without other questions that are still in doubt.
2nd. The clear and distinct concept that we have of these modes of thought is rendered obscure and confused, if we wish to add to them something that still remains in doubt.

Release from All Doubts

Finally, to reach assurance on what he had questioned and to remove all doubt, he proceeded to inquire into the nature of the most perfect Being and on its existence. For, upon discovering the existence of a most perfect Being, by whose power all things are produced and conserved, and whose nature refutes the possibility of his being an impostor, the reason for doubt, that he entertained through his ignorance of his true cause, will be eliminated. For he will know that the faculty of distinguishing the true from the false was not given to him by a God supremely good and veracious to produce deception. And so the mathematical truths and all those things that appear very evident to him will not admit of any suspicion whatever. Then he advances a step forward to eliminate the other causes of doubt and inquiries: How does it happen that we are sometimes mistaken? When he discovered that this arises from our own use of free will in giving assent even to what we perceived only confusedly, he was at once able to conclude that he could avoid error in the future, provided he gave assent to clear and distinctive perceptions only. Each one may easily achieve this of his own accord, since he has the power of restraining his will and confining it within the limits of the understanding. But as, in early youth, we acquire many preconceptions from which we are not easily liberated, he proceeds, in order to free us so that we accept nothing that we do not clearly and distinctly perceive, to review all the simple notions and ideas, of which all our thoughts are composed; to examine each one separately, in order to discover whatever is obscure in each of them. Thus he will be in a position to make an easy distinction between what is clear and what is obscure, and from clear and distinct thoughts, and so to discover easily the real distinction between the soul and the body: what is clear and what is obscure in the perceptions that we experience by the senses; and lastly, the difference between sleep and wakefulness. Thereupon, he could no longer doubt his wakeful periods or be deceived by the sense; and thus he emancipated himself from all the doubts previously considered.
But, before I stop at this point, I must, it appears, give a satisfactory reply to those who argue as follows: Since the existence of God is not known to us by itself, it does not seem that we can ever be certain of anything: nor will the existence of God ever be known to us. For from uncertain premises (and we saw that everything is uncertain as long as we are unaware of our origin) no certainty can be reached.
To resolve this difficulty, Descartes replies thus: From the fact that we do not yet know whether perhaps the author of our origin has treated us such as to be deceived, even in what appears to us most evident, we cannot in the slightest degree doubt what we know clearly and distinctl...

Table of contents