Infrapolitics
eBook - ePub

Infrapolitics

A Handbook

Alberto Moreiras

Share book
  1. 272 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Infrapolitics

A Handbook

Alberto Moreiras

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

The personal is not political, even if politics marks it and, in many cases, determines it. Infrapolitics seeks to understand conditions of existence that are not reducible to political life and that exceed any definition of world bound to political determinations. It seeks to mobilize an exteriority without which politics could only be business or administration, that is, oppression. It demands a change in seeing and an everyday practice that subtracts from political totalization in the name of a new production of desire, of a new emancipation, and of a conception of experience that can breach the general captivation of life.In this book, Alberto Moreiras describes a form of thought aiming to provide content for a form of life and to offer a new theoretical practice for concrete existence. The book provides a genealogy of the notion of infrapolitics and places it within contemporary philosophical reflection, examining its deployment in the wake of postphenomenology and deconstruction, Lacanian analysis, the principle of anarchy, and an egalitarian symbolization of social life. In doing so, Moreiras elaborates Infrapolitics as both a general critique of the political apparatus and as an imperative horizon for existential self-understanding.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Infrapolitics an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Infrapolitics by Alberto Moreiras in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Literature & Latin American & Caribbean Literary Criticism. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

1

The Last God

María Zambrano’s Life without Texture
MarĂ­a Zambrano (1904–1991) studied with JosĂ© Ortega y Gasset at the University of Madrid in the 1920s and was intimately connected to the intellectual events surrounding the Second Spanish Republic. She was at the time something like a radical liberal, in the complicated Spanish tradition, a deep thinker whose early work already contains hints of the poetic and the religious veins that would mark her later work. She was forced into exile during the Spanish Civil War and initiated a pilgrimage through various countries in Latin America (Cuba, Mexico), then Europe (Italy and France), until her return to Spain in the 1980s. During those long years of defeat, poverty, and intense commitment to the tasks of thinking as she saw them, she produced an idiosyncratic oeuvre that is perhaps one of the most important instances of Spanish thought or Spanish philosophy.
This chapter is an attempt to read María Zambrano’s major 1955 book, El hombre y lo divino, as a subdued but significant critical engagement with the thought of Martin Heidegger, or rather with the political implications of Heidegger’s work, particularly Being and Time (1927).1 I am interested in examining two of the conceptual structures that Zambrano offers in El hombre y lo divino against a dual background: the definition of democracy she provides in Persona y democracia: La historia sacrificial (1958) as renunciation and abandonment of the sacrificial structuration of history, and the notion of epochal dissolution of the identity of being and thinking in El hombre y lo divino. The first of those conceptual structures she calls “relación abismada,” which I will translate as “degrounded relation,” and the second is “vida sin textura” or “life without texture.”
For Zambrano, a democratic politics is bound to the precise determination of the abandonment of “sacrificial history.” If the abandonment of the sacrificial structuration of history defines democratic politics, similarly the practice of democracy defines an antisacrificial perspective on action. A democratic politics, regardless of what politics could be in itself, is always bent on the suppression of the divide between what Zambrano called “idols” on the one hand and “victims” on the other (Persona, 42). Beyond the search for power or the search for recognition, if politics is understood as the practice of abandonment of the sacrificial structuration of history, then politics appears as specifically democratic politics. This is what Zambrano proposes. But there can be no abandonment of the sacrificial structuration of history insofar as there is no abandonment of the understanding of politics as primarily subjective militancy. If subjective militancy is at the same time a condition and a result of ontology, to go beyond ontology, beyond the subjectivity of the subject, beyond an understanding of world as the domination of the object by the subject, is the condition and result of an ethical (or, rather, infrapolitical) position that has refused sacrificial politics. Zambrano follows here an intuition that Emmanuel LĂ©vinas would have clearly articulated for twentieth-century thought. In the deeper layers of El hombre y lo divino, Zambrano hears a form of Levinasian saying at the heart of ethico-political articulation.
In the identity of thinking and being—an old notion of philosophy, one of its very first words in the poem of Parmenides—the very principle of sovereign subjectivity that has marked modernity itself is ciphered, perhaps deceitfully (as the Parmenidean phrase requires more than a literal translation). There is in effect no sovereignty without subjectivity, in the same way that there is no subjectivity without sovereignty. To paraphrase Juan Donoso CortĂ©s or Carl Schmitt, every relevant concept of political thought in modernity is anchored in transcendental subjectivity, which turns subjectivity into the matrix of everything that is thinkable on the basis of the identification of subject and substance. Zambrano, in her sustained meditation on the necessary deidentification of thinking and being, is already pointing toward an alternative, nonmodern conception of the political. Only from that alternative conceptualization is it possible to formulate a project for political life based on the abandonment of the sacrificial structuration of history. But to abandon the sacrificial structuration of history is also to abandon every attempt at a politics of sovereignty, every attempt at establishing the political on the basis and ground of an experience or practice of sovereignty. MarĂ­a Zambrano as a thinker of the political thinks the possibility of politics beyond (modern, conventional) subjectivity and beyond sovereignty. The concepts of degrounded relationship and life without texture, which I will attempt to determine in what follows, are essential to this endeavor.

The Nonprimacy of Politics in Democratic Politics

In terms of the political as the practice of sovereignty, could any possible primacy of politics over history (including economic history) be considered absolute or relative? If the autonomy of the political is relative, then politics would still be subordinate to history in the last instance. If it is absolute, then politics would be the norm of action. But an absolutely primary politics, that is, an absolutely sovereign politics, would have to rely on the total immanence of its own conditions and would in fact be normless: that is, it would provide something like a normless norm for action. A politics without a norm, that is, a politics that would itself be the normative standard, without recourse to alterity or to a heterogeneous grounding, can only be a politics of force, and it would have become an ontology (as in the Nietzschean case, where the will to power is the ontological principle of Nietzsche’s “grand politics”).
Or is it possible that a norm for politics can be found outside history itself, and thus also outside force? That norm beyond history would not be an ontology, but it would register at some infraontological level, at the level of desire perhaps, a normative affect regulating something like Walter Benjamin’s hatred of mythic violence, what Jacques Derrida refers to as the final indeconstructibility of the call for justice, or Alain Badiou’s communist invariant. If something like that transhistorical or transpolitical norm were to exist, if politics can emerge through it as heteronormative, that is, always dependent upon an affect that would be exterior to itself, then it would be necessary to conclude that politics is always a partisan politics precisely to the very extent that it will not let itself be reduced to force or to an ontology of force. Can politics be thought without partisanship? Is partisanship, as expression of an affect that is only secondarily or derivatively political, an unconditional, irreducible determinant of any theory of the political? Partisanship, understood as the heteronomous recourse of every political positioning (I love my people, which is why I side politically with them, not the other way around), would therefore be the negation of the autonomy of the political, or autonomy’s limit.
Zambrano, as mentioned, states in Persona y democracia that a democratic politics is bound to the abandonment of “sacrificial history.” If the abandonment of the sacrificial structuration of history defines democratic politics, the practice of democracy defines an antisacrificial perspective on action. A democratic politics is always bent on the suppression of the divide between “idols” on the one hand, and “victims,” on the other; it is based on the refusal of the fact that the existence of idols must always feed off the existence of victims. Only democracy, Zambrano says, among all the political systems, can shelter the possibility of marching toward an abandonment of sacrificial history. There is no possibility of social justice without an abandonment of sacrificial history. The abandonment of sacrifice and the accomplishment of social justice, premised on equality, are then the goals of democracy, and they define the promise of politics from a democratic perspective. This cuts across other divisions of the political field, such as Carl Schmitt’s friend/enemy division, or the division of the social between the part of the whole and the part of no-part proposed by Jacques RanciĂ©re.
If politics is exhaustively contained in the friend/enemy division, then politics is defined by power: politics seeks power—its acquisition or its continued possession—as the power of one group over other groups, even if the need for group alliance is already a partisanship and introduces elements themselves alien to power. If politics marks the fundamental act of appearance of a claim to existence by the part of no-part, that is, of those who are negated by the ideological articulation of social totality, then politics is defined by recognition: the part of no-part wants to be recognized as such by the social totality, or it wants to be recognized as the social totality (the proletariat as universal class, or the people as general will). If politics is understood as the practice of abandonment of the sacrificial structuration of history, then politics appears as specifically democratic politics. Through each of those determinations there emerges the thought, only superficially paradoxical, that the only possible nonpartisan understanding of the political is precisely the understanding of the political as always already partisan. How can we link those three definitions of the political? We can imagine a complex interaction between demands for power, demands for recognition, and demands for the end of sacrifice in any concrete situation. At their limit, however, the three definitions are incompatible. The demand for power must subordinate one group to another group, since its limit is the existence of the enemy, and the enemy must be kept in check, which reveals this practice of the political as profoundly sacrificial, and thus antidemocratic; the demand for a democratic end of sacrificial history must give up power, insofar as it can only absorb the radical power of the nonapplication of power; and the demand for recognition is never just either a demand for power or a demand for democracy and social justice. The three definitions exceed each other, and, in their mutual excess, they organize something like an aporia of the political. Politics would finally be the infinite negotiation between those three ultimately incompatible demands: for power, for recognition, and for an end to social sacrifice.
But, if so, then only democracy can organize, even if aporetically, the simultaneous pursuit of the three demands, since no other system can countenance the end of the sacrificial structuration of history. Democracy can authorize, however, unconditional demands for power and recognition—not any demands for power and recognition, of course, just some: the absolute power of the people, for instance; or the total recognition of the proletariat as class, which is the political abolition of class; or the total recognition of gender, which is the political abolition of gender. Only in the horizon of democracy is it possible to think of the total subsumption of power, recognition, and the end of sacrifice. But this would be the end of the political, and thus necessarily also the end of democracy, and the end of the end of sacrifice: hence the aporetic character of democratic politics and, a fortiori, of any politics. As aporetic, the political instance appears as always already heteronormative, never sovereign, not self-contained. Zambrano will make it depend on an experience of the “pure sacred,” of the fondo oscuro, of a contact with a last god that is to be understood as the very void of any pleroma or compact fullness.

Zambrano and Heidegger on Forgetting

Zambrano thinks of subalternity as the possibility of an understanding of the political beyond transcendental subjectivity, beyond the sovereignty of the subject of politics (or of history), beyond the conditions under which we have thought of the political in modernity and through modernity. Zambrano’s notion of democratic politics as the abandonment of the sacrificial structuration of history shows that such an understanding forces us to determine the heteronomy of the political in favor of a partisan stance, that is, in favor of an always already previous ethical engagement. El hombre y lo divino can be comprehensively understood as a book that wants to narrate, impossibly, the history of a forgetting. I would now like to move toward the exposition of the two conceptual structures that I mentioned as particularly relevant to understand Zambrano’s contribution to political thinking, namely, “degrounded relation” and “life without texture,” as presented in El hombre y lo divino.
In twentieth-century philosophy the thematization of forgetting is intimately linked to Heidegger’s Being and Time. But for Heidegger what is at stake in the history of philosophy is the history of the forgetting of being. Zambrano, roughly thirty years later, does not concern herself with being. What she is interested in is the forgetting of God, and with it the forgetting of the dimension of the sacred, the forgetting of the dimension of the divine as such. For Zambrano, as for LĂ©vinas, God is beyond being. God, the sacred, the divine—such is for Zambrano the constellation of an epochal forgetting, the register of a radical insufficiency in the philosophical and spiritual experience of her historical time. Zambrano wrote her book, or finished it, during the years she spent in Rome. The repeated mention in her book of a white Pythagorean chapel, then recently excavated by archaeologists in a neighborhood close to her place of residence, is far from being incidental—just as her references to the Roman Empire’s universalism are also not incidental. Zambrano wonders if the “fortunes of the [Pythagorean] white chapel” are ready to declare, in 1955, their “oculto sentido,” or “hidden sense” (116–17). Would it be a counterimperial sense? What is the secret that Rome preserves, on the side of the vanquished? And why thematize the forgetting of God to think, not even democracy, but the possibility of a radically antisovereign, antisacrificial politics? Hasn’t God been precisely the ultimate guarantor of ontotheology? Hence the very ground of sovereignty? Is there something like a god without sovereignty?
How does one deal with forgetting? To the very extent that the forgetting is such, that is, that it is a true forgetting, it is inaccessible to the memory of the thinker. At most one could rescue traces, if there remains a memory of the forgetting itself, rather than a memory of its object. To think the trace of the forgetting of the divine, is that a theological or a philosophic enterprise? Is one to think theologically or to think philosophically the forgetting of the divine, not as forgetting of the divine but as forgetting as such? What could be the point of a treatise on the forgetting of the divine historically and politically? In 1955, in Rome, at the heart of Latin, Christian, Catholic Europe? To think about the forgetting of the divine is a task different from the task Heidegger had indicated as essential: to think through the forgetting of being. The forgetting of the divine is also immediately the forgetting of the transpolitical sovereignty of the ontotheological god. Must we go back to the source of secularization to reestablish a proper ontotheological norm? Or is ontotheology, which is absolutely founded on the notion of sovereign presence, itself already a forgetting of the divine in Zambrano’s sense? If politics in modernity results from the secularization of ontotheological postulates, a politics based on the critique of ontotheology as a forgetting of the divine does not presuppose the return to any notion of transpolitical sovereignty. Rather, it seeks the destruction of the concept of a secularized sovereignty.
To think the forgetting of the divine defines for Zambrano a task very different from the one Heidegger would have determined as the philosophical necessity of his time: to think the forgetting of being. In his 1942–43 lectures on Parmenides, Heidegger came to link the thought of the forgetting of being with the destruction of an imperial thinking of the political, which for him exhausted the European thinking of the political, and which he associated with the curialization of the Greek legacy through the Latin translation of the fundamental concepts of the first beginning of philosophy in Greece (Parmenides, 43, 46). Western politics, in other words, is for Heidegger predetermined by the ecclesiastical internalization of the Roman concept of imperial hegemony. For Heidegger, in 1942–43, as the battle of Stalingrad was coming to an end, and with it the might of the Wehrmacht and of Nazi power, the enterprise of thinking about the forgetting of being, by now tragic for him, had become the enterprise of thinking through a nonimperial configuration of the political. Thinking the forgetting of being was for Heidegger in a very precise form—after he himself had taken the issue to catastrophic extremes through his Nazi commitments—thinking a nonimperial possibility of the political. Zambrano, a few years later, may have been attempting something similar, but at the same time radically different, from the thought of the forgetting of God. She wanted to think that nonimperial possibility, which for Zambrano has a name that remained alien to Heideggerian thought, namely, democracy, beyond its metaphysical and sacrificial theorizations rooted in the history of the West. Zambrano’s fundamental category is the category of degrounded relation: for Zambrano, the forgetting of God can be thought only starting from the historical understanding of a degrounded relation to the divine.
El hombre y lo divino contains some hidden references to Heidegger’s 1947 “Letter on Humanism.” As is well known, “Letter on Humanism” attempts an account of the present—not just any present, since the essay was written in 1946—through “a thinking that abandons subjectivity” (207). This might sound faintly ridiculous today, when everywhere a vague and at the same time precise notion of subjectivity, suffering but triumphant, rules as the unthought in our presuppositions. Its critique is a constant motive in Heidegger, linked as it is for him to the moment of consummation and exhaustion of the history of metaphysics. In contemporary political thinking—a genuine and faithful descendant of metaphysical thought—subjectivity rules explicitly as the impassable horizon of any possible thinking of the political, and it is no exaggeration to say that, against Heidegger, most contemporary thinking thinks of subjectivity as the true house of Being, as the home where contemporary humanity might find refuge against the onset of homelessness, understood as that which is “coming to be the destiny of the world” (219). But subjectivity is for Heidegger homelessness itself and the site for the most devastating effects of technical thought. Take, for instance, nationalism, still fundamentally important in 1946, or expand it to any identity ideology: “Every nationalism is metaphysically an anthropologism, and as such subjectivism. Nationalism is not overcome through mere internationalism; it is rather expanded and elevated thereby into a system. Nationalism is as little brought and raised to humanitas by internationalism as individualism is by an ahistorical collectivism. The latter is the subjectivity of man in totality. It completes subjectivity’s unconditioned self-assertion, which refuses to yield” (221). Man, the human, conceived from subjectivity, remains caught up in “essential homelessness” (221). Is that true also for Zambrano? It certainly is true. But Zambrano takes her path in divergence from Heidegger’s.
In “The Question Concerning Technology” (1954), a text strictly contemporary of El hombre y lo divino, Heidegger quotes Friedrich Nietzsche on the political importance of philosophy: “The time is coming when the struggle for dominion over the earth will be carried on. It will be carried on in the name of fundamental philosophical doctrines” (Nietzsche quoted by Heidegger, “Question,” 101). Heidegger adds: “‘Fundamental philosophical doctrines’ does not mean the doctrines of scholars but the language of the truth of what is as such, which truth metaphysics itself is in the form of the metaphysics of the unconditional subjectness of the will to power” (“Question,” 101). Both the Nietzschean will to power and the Hegelian-Marxist kind of transcendental subjectivity (“The essence of materialism [consists] 
 in a metaphysical determination according to which every being appears as the material of labor. The modern metaphysical essence of labor is anticipated in Hegel 
 as the self-establishing process of unconditioned production, which is the objectification of the ac...

Table of contents