How Do We Reason?
eBook - ePub

How Do We Reason?

An Introduction to Logic

Forrest E. Baird

Share book
  1. 264 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

How Do We Reason?

An Introduction to Logic

Forrest E. Baird

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

How do we think? What does a faithful use of logic look like?Without even pausing to think about it, we exercise our capacity for rational thought. But how exactly does logic work? What makes some arguments valid and others not?In this Questions in Christian Philosophy volume, philosopher Forrest Baird offers an introduction to logic. He considers the basic building blocks of human reason, including types of arguments, fallacies, syllogisms, symbols, and proofs, all of which are demonstrated with exercises for students throughout. In addition, he reflects on the relationship between the use of reason and the Christian faith.With this academic but accessible primer, readers will be introduced to the basics of logic—and encouraged to reason better.The Questions in Christian Philosophy Series features introductory textbooks that offer students a Christian perspective on the various branches of philosophy, enabling them as they seek to understand all facets of life including existence, knowledge, ethics, art, and more.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is How Do We Reason? an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access How Do We Reason? by Forrest E. Baird in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Theology & Religion & Philosophy of Religion. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
IVP Academic
Year
2021
ISBN
9780830855162

What is logic? In the broad sense, it is the study of the correct method of reasoning. But in a narrow sense, it is the study of the correct form of arguments. As a subject, logic is not nearly as difficult as many people think—and most people use it all the time. The problem is that language is so vague and serves so many functions that it is often difficult to find the form of an argument embedded within it. One of the chief tasks of logic is to find that form, examine it closely, and determine whether the argument is properly structured.
This book will begin by defining arguments: the parts of arguments, the kinds of arguments, and what makes for a good argument. After this brief introduction, we will look at “full-bodied” language as expressed in everyday sentences and the many ways it is used. We will examine the difference between form and function, between denotation and connotation, and learn to find the arguments embedded within the common uses of language. We will also take time to look at a number of common “informal fallacies.”
Next, we will start to look below the surface of everyday language by examining one very formal way of arguing: categorical syllogisms. These formal arguments will begin to show us the underlying logical structure of arguments as expressed in language. We will also learn how to determine whether these stylized arguments are correct, and we will learn to take ordinary language and turn it into these formal arguments.
In the final unit, we will examine the underlying form of arguments by using symbols. We will develop a set of rules for constructing a logic of sentences and find ways to evaluate these arguments. This will give us the skeleton, as it were, of the argument. We will conclude by going back to arguments in language and translating them into symbols to see how well they are constructed.

1.1 TERMS

Arguments. So what is an argument? In a famous Monty Python skit, Michael Palin goes into an “Argument Clinic.” There, he pays John Cleese to have an argument with him. After some typical Monty Python silliness, the two men get down to arguing:
Palin: I came here for a good argument.
Cleese: No you didn’t; no, you came here for an argument.
Palin: An argument isn’t just contradiction.
Cleese: It can be.
Palin: No it can’t. An argument is a connected series of statements to establish a proposition.
Cleese: No it isn’t.
Palin: Yes it is! It’s not just contradiction.
Cleese: Look, if I argue with you, I must take up a contrary position.
Palin: Yes, but that’s not just saying “No it isn’t.”
Cleese: Yes it is!
Palin: No it isn’t! An argument is an intellectual process. Contradiction is just the automatic gainsaying of any statement the other person makes.
Cleese: No it isn’t.
Palin: It is.
Cleese: Not at all.1
In the middle of this short excerpt from the interminable exchange, Palin gives a very good definition of an argument: “a connected series of statements to establish a proposition.” Notice there are three parts to this definition:
  • 1. “statements”
These statements that are given as a reason to accept a certain proposition are called “premises.” All arguments have at least one premise or reason given for why one should accept something else.
  • 2. “a proposition”
The proposition that the argument is attempting to establish is called the “conclusion.” This is what the speaker wants to prove.
  • 3. “a connected series . . . to establish”
It is not enough to just have statements and propositions in order to have an argument—they must be connected in a certain way. Consider the following:
P1 I am hungry
P2 This is a pen
C Tomorrow is Tuesday2
While we have two statements and a proposition, this is clearly not an argument. What is missing? There is no connection here to establish the proposition “Tomorrow is Tuesday” on the basis of the previous two statements. The “connected series . . . to establish” is the part that makes an argument work. In fact, it is this third point that is the key to logic. Logic is not primarily concerned with the statements and propositions that make up an argument. (Are they true? False? Would most people accept them?) Instead logic is about the connections between these constituent parts of an argument. This connection is called inference, and it is what we will be trying to isolate and test throughout this book.
Propositions, statements, and sentences. The Monty Python skit uses different words for premises and conclusions: statements and propositions. But this is misleading. Both premises and conclusions are made from propositions. Further, statements are just one particular instance of a proposition expressed in a sentence. Let’s unpack this a little to get our definitions straight. What exactly is a proposition?
A proposition is an idea that is true or false.
Now a proposition is conveyed by a statement, but it is not exactly the same thing as a statement. For example, the statement
S1: “Abraham Lincoln is the president of the United States”
was true in 1864, but the same statement is false today. Statements, then, are bound by time, but propositions are not. When statement S1 was expressed in 1864, it was expressing the proposition “Abraham Lincoln is the president of the United States in 1864,” which is still true today. Similarly, the statement
S2: “This country has a president”
is true if you are in the United States, but false if you are visiting England. So statements are bound by place as well as time, but propositions are not. The proposition “The United States has a president” is true even if I h...

Table of contents