Illusion in Cultural Practice
eBook - ePub

Illusion in Cultural Practice

Productive Deceptions

Katharina Rein

  1. 206 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Illusion in Cultural Practice

Productive Deceptions

Katharina Rein

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This volume explores illusionism as a much larger phenomenon than optical illusion, magic shows, or special effects, as a vital part of how we perceive, process, and shape the worldin which we live. Considering different cultural practices characterized by illusionism, this book suggests a new approach to illusion via media theory.

Each of the chapters analyses a specific kind of illusionistic practice and the concept of illusionism it entails in a given context, including philosophy, perception and cognitive theory, performance magic, occultism, optics, physiology, early cinema, cartomancy, spiritualism, architecture, shamanic rituals, and theoretical physics, to show the diversity of shapes that illusionism and illusions can take. The book provides detailed analyses of illusions within performance and ritual magic, philosophy, art history and psychology as well as a first approach to the study of illusions outside of these established fields. It aims to find ways of identifying and analysing a wider range of illusions in the humanities.

This multidisciplinary and comprehensive volume will appeal to scholars and students with an interest in media and culture, theatre and performance, philosophy, sociology, politics and religion.

This publication was supported by the Internationales Kolleg für Kulturtechnikforschung und Medienphilosophie of the Bauhaus-Universität Weimar with funds from the German Federal Ministry of Education and Research.

IKKM Books

Volume 47
An overview of the whole series can be found at
www.ikkm-weimar.de/schriften

Chapter 5 of this book is freely available as a downloadable Open Access PDF under a Creative Commons Attribution-Non Commercial-Share Alike 4.0 license https://www.taylorfrancis.com/chapters/oa-edit/10.4324/9781003188278-8/vanishing-lady-railway-illusions-movement-1-katharina-rein?context=ubx&refId=fe124e6e-8290-43e9-9d48-753bad162c50

Chapter 9 of this book is freely available as a downloadable Open Access PDF under a Creative Commons Attribution-Non Commercial-No Derivatives 4.0 license https://www.taylorfrancis.com/chapters/oa-edit/10.4324/9781003188278-13/talking-rocks-illusory-sounds-projections-otherworld-julia-shpinitskaya-riitta-rainio?context=ubx&refId=3aa829a8-8c0b-4103-870a-6fe5a4393e71

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Illusion in Cultural Practice an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Illusion in Cultural Practice by Katharina Rein in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Médias et arts de la scène & Film et vidéo. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2021
ISBN
9781000481143

Part I The epistemology and aesthetics of illusions

1 Optical illusion and standing appearance in Kant and Johann Heinrich Lambert1

Astrid Deuber-Mankowsky
DOI: 10.4324/9781003188278-3

Our point of departure: Kant’s Opponenten-Rede

In his 1912 biography, Kants Leben, Karl Vorländer accords “a recently published Latin speech” a “significance not to be underestimated” for Kant’s perspectives in aesthetics (Vorländer 1986, 101f.). Vorländer is referencing the Opponenten-Rede that Kant held on 28 February 1777, on the occasion of the second half of the public disputation of Johann Gottlieb Kreutzfeld, who had recently been named Professor of Poetry at the University of Königsberg. As was then customary, Kreutzfeld was obliged to defend an inaugural dissertation before assuming his position. He did so in two parts. He presented the first part, “pro receptione (in facult. philos.)”, on 25 February 1777. The second part, “pro loco (profess. ordo.)”, he defended on the 28th. For the latter presentation, Kant served as the official “opponent” drawn from the circle of faculty who would become Kreutzfeld’s colleagues. Kreutzfeld titled his two-part dissertation, Dissertatio Philologico-Poetica de Principiis Fictionum Generalioribus, that is: Philological-Poetical Dissertation on the General Principles of Fictions.
Kant’s response, which he wrote in longhand on the interstices of the print copy of part two of Kreutzfeld’s dissertation, has received little scholarly attention to date. One reason for this, among others, is that commentators concerned with aesthetic issues typically focus on the third Critique, the Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790). From the perspective of media theory, however, Kant’s early writings offer surprising insights into the interconnectedness of issues in aesthetics, epistemology, and the philosophy of perception. This is especially true of Kant’s Opponenten-Rede and its treatment of concepts such as optical illusion, perspective, and projection – a treatment that owes much to the mathematician, universal scientist, and inventor of diverse scientific instruments, Johann Heinrich Lambert. The discussion between Lambert and Kant reaches its acme in the question of the epistemological status of a technique-generated “standing appearance [Schein]” of a phenomenally given world. This attention to “standing appearances”, which Kant identifies in optical illusions as the very essence of appearance [Schein], makes his discussion with Lambert interesting as part of an early history of pictorial technologies.
As Erich Adickes remarks in the 1913 edition of Kant’s handwritten Nachlass, published as volume XV of the Academy Edition, the existence of Kant’s Opponent-Rede was long known.2 Yet it was not until 1910 that Arthur Warda first published it in the Altpreußische Monatsschrift. The Latin text, though in places somewhat inscrutable, was swiftly translated into German and accompanied by a commentary by Bernhard Adolf Schmidt, published in Kant-Studien under the title, “Eine bisher unbekannte lateinische Rede Kants über Sinnestäuschung und poetische Fiktion” [“A Previously Unknown Latin Speech by Kant on Sensory Illusion and Poetic Fiction”] (Schmidt 1911, 5–21).3 It is to the latter publication that Vorländer refers in his first Kant book.
True to his word in this early work, Vorländer takes up the philosophical significance of Kant’s speech again in his later compendium, Immanuel Kant. Der Mann und das Werk – published twelve years later and at three times the length. Among Kant’s “more ingeniously dashed-off than strictly systematic explorations” Vorländer calls special attention to:
[…] the concept of playful illusion or semblance as a fundamental element of all poetry, the ideas of the magic of the senses and of the elevation of literature, the distinction between natural and poetical love (Petrarch’s sonnets to Laura), between the poet and the philosopher, the separation between the domains of poesy and logic, the conception of the task of the latter.
Despite the obvious relevance of these themes, Vorländer’s 1924 Kant book does not repeat his earlier claim that the speech’s “significance [is] not to be underestimated”. Instead, he clarifies that his aim is not to trace the gradual development of Kant’s aesthetic theory using the recently published Nachlass, but rather to portray Kant “always in the first instance only as philosopher”. With this declaration of intentions, however, Vorländer not only removes the speech from the center of philosophical concern, but simultaneously excludes aesthetic questions from the core domain of philosophy itself.

The interest in optical illusions

The concept of illusion Kant employs in his Opponenten-Rede is drawn from aesthetics and was used well into the 1780s to refer to misperceptions or sensory delusions that are accompanied by a consciousness of the non-reality of the represented object (for an extensive discussion, see Strube 1971; for an overview, see Strube 1976).
Over the course of the eighteenth century, the word “illusion”, which simply meant “sensory delusion” in common French parlance, was adapted by French aesthetic theorists such as Abbé Dubos and Diderot and introduced into aesthetic discourse. It made its way into German aesthetics through authors such as Mendelssohn, Lessing, and Sulzer, as well as Kant’s friend and Kreutzfeld’s predecessor Johann Gotthelf Lindner. In 1757, Mendelssohn, for example, characterizes “aesthetic illusion [Illusion]” as an
[…] imitation that has so much similarity to the original [Urbilde] that our senses can convince themselves, at least for a moment, of seeing the original itself.
If an imitation is to be “beautiful”, Mendelssohn continues, “the higher powers of the soul, however, must be convinced that it is an imitation and not nature itself” (ibid., 154). In his 1771 Philosophische Schriften, Mendelssohn corrects himself in connection with Dubos’s description of the “aesthetic state [Zustand]” and admits that the soul allows itself to be carried along and deceived by art. “Only”, he admits,
this magic lasts only as long as is necessary to give our concept of the object the appropriate fire and life. As soon as the relation to the object begins to become unpleasant, however, we remember thousands of obvious factors [revealing] that we are seeing a mere imitation before us.
Illusion, for Mendelssohn, is characterized by a twofold representational process. The soul represents the depicted object through the senses as an object. Illusion is, to that extent, sensory delusion. At the same time, however, the soul remains conscious (through its higher faculties) that it is dealing with a mere representation, a mere sensory illusion. In this manner, the soul assures itself of the supremacy of the understanding over the senses, which constitutes the genuinely educational effect of aesthetic illusion.
Mendelssohn stands squarely within contemporaneous consensus in speaking of illusion in connection with imitations on the “stage, on canvas, in marble” – i.e. in connection with theatre, painting, and sculpture (ibid.). Illusion unites those disciplines in which the assumption that genuine art consists in deceiving the senses has a long tradition. As early as Plato’s Republic, we find the claim that painters, as imitators, have the ability to deceive children and fools. If this was, for Plato, a reason to assert the inferiority of art, the argument had so reversed itself by the eighteenth century (with the popular reception of the story of Zeuxis and Parrhasius4) that, now, skill in figurative art could be measured by the deceptive genuineness of the imitations produced.
In addition to the visual arts, the production of sensory illusion played a central role in rhetoric. It was central to the theory of enthusiasm, according to which speakers could, through their animation, see the things they described as though they were really there before their eyes. The animation and inspiration of the speaker could, on this theory, communicate itself to the public through sympathy, so that the audience would forget where they were in order to allow themselves to be completely carried away by the speech. This state was termed “pathetic illusion” and was considered legitimate when it was furnished with a moral-pedagogical function.5
The transference of the theory of enthusiasm onto the doctrine of aesthetic illusion has the consequence that illusion comes to be associated with the moral improvement of the deluded viewer and thereby morally legitimated.
This conception of aesthetic illusion as a morally legitimate delusion of the senses forms the basis on which Kant, in his speech against Kreutzfeld, distinguishes between illusion as permissible delusion and impermissible deceit. He introduces the concept of illusion in a general prefatory remark that precedes his critical commentary on Kreutzfeld’s discussion of the universal ground of fictional production. Kant thus makes clear from the outset how he himself thinks about the theme of fiction (AA 15.2:903ff.).
There is, Kant claims early on, “a kind of illusion [fallendi] that is clearly not disreputable” (AA 15.2:906). It flatters the ear, stimulates the mind through an “illusory appearance [fictis rerum speciebus]”, and elevates it (AA 15.2:906). This sort of deception Kant terms “playful appearance”. It eschews any “evil intent” (AA 15.2:906). Moreover, the author of such illusion not only does not mean to incite error, he seeks to present “the truth, clothed in the dress of appearance, which does not obscure its inner essence, but sets it adorned before [our] eyes” (AA 15.2:906). Thus, the appearance does not deceive through ornamentation and adornment, but uses the perspicuity of the senses to allow “the colorless image of truth, painted in sensible colors, to enter into appearance” (AA 15.2:907). Kant calls this play of appearances “illusion [illusio]” and distinguishes it from the “appearance that deceives [fallit]”, which he connects with the concept of deceit (fraude) (AA 15.2:907, 908). Illusion is not only permissible, it pleases “in high measure” (AA 15.2:907); whereas deceptive illusion, once discovered, arouses resentment.
Up to this point, Kant’s remarks align with textbook versions of fine arts’ provisions for aesthetic illusion. He departs from the standard version, however, by abruptly introducing optical illusion [illusionibus opticis] as an example of illusion thus theorized. In contrast to the cheap conjuring tricks and deceptions of the entertainer, according to Kant, optical illusion is not meant to deceive its recipients. Entertainers are in the business of misrepresenting appearance as truth, and their arts retain their fascination only so long as the deceptive appearance is not seen through. The moment the viewer understands the appearance, they also understands they have been tricked. The result is simultaneous awe and “indignation at being won over by the slyness of the deceiver” (AA 15.2:908).
In the case of optical illusions, by contrast, the viewer is protected from error since the appearance is readily seen through. The art here consists in keeping the mind in motion “fluctuating, as it were, at the borderline between error and truth” (AA 15.2:907). In this way, the appearance endures even as the optical delusion is seen through. Illusion is thus distinguished by the fact that the conditions of the appearance can be seen through, as in the case of optical illusion, without the appearance ceasing to have effect. And just as suddenly as Kant introduced the concept of optical illusion, he continues by asserting the connectedness of optical appearance and the literary arts [Dichtung].
Kant expounds his understanding of optical illusion in Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View by means of three concrete examples. First, “the perspectival drawing of the interior of a temple”; second, the painting of the peripatetic school, of which it is said “they appear to move when one looks at them a long time”; and third, “the Amsterdam town hall painting of a staircase behind a half-opened door, that misleads visitors into trying to climb it” (AA 7:150).
From his examples, it is clear that Kant is not thinking of a “natural phenomenon” when discussing optical illusion, but instead of the technique of perspective. But what is the connection between single-point perspective and literature [Dichtung]? And how is it that these arts, by employing optical illusion in ways that fool our senses, “wrest the prize from most other arts”, as Kant claims in the Opponenten-Rede (AA 15.2:909)?

Lambert’s explanation of phenomenology as the science of appearance [Schein]

The concept of optical illusion, the reference to perspectival technique, and the mooted connection with the literature indicate that Kant’s concept of illusion is indebted not only to fine arts’ primers but also to Johann Heinrich Lambert’s “Phenomenology or Science of Appearances” [“Phänomenologie oder Lehre des Scheins”], with which Lambert concluded the second volume of his 1764 work, The New Organon – or Thoughts on the Investigation and Identification of Truth and its Distinction from Error and Appearance [Neues Organon oder Gedanken über die Erforschung und Bezeichnung des Wahren und dessen Unterscheidung vom Irrtum und Schein].6 Lambert (1728–77) lived in Berlin from 1765 on as a member of the Academy of Sciences and independent scho...

Table of contents