Presuppositions and Cognitive Processes
eBook - ePub

Presuppositions and Cognitive Processes

Understanding the Information Taken for Granted

Filippo Domaneschi

Share book
  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Presuppositions and Cognitive Processes

Understanding the Information Taken for Granted

Filippo Domaneschi

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This book breaks new ground towards an understanding of the mental processes involved in presupposition, the comprehension of information taken for granted. Various psycholinguistic experiments are discussed to support the idea that involved in ordinary language comprehension are complex and demanding cognitive processes. The author demonstrates that these processes exist not only at the explicit level of an utterance but also at a deeper level of computing, where the background information taken for granted as already known and shared between interlocutors is processed. The author shows that experimental research can suggest new theoretical models for presupposition, thus this book will be of interest to researchers and students of psycholinguistics, the philosophy of language and experimental pragmatics.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on ā€œCancel Subscriptionā€ - itā€™s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time youā€™ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlegoā€™s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan youā€™ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, weā€™ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Presuppositions and Cognitive Processes an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Presuppositions and Cognitive Processes by Filippo Domaneschi in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Languages & Linguistics & Psycolinguistics. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Ā© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s) 2016
Filippo DomaneschiPresuppositions and Cognitive ProcessesPalgrave Studies in Pragmatics, Language and Cognition10.1057/978-1-137-57942-3_1
Begin Abstract

1. Experimental Pragmatics

Filippo Domaneschi1
(1)
University of Genoa, Genoa, Italy
Abstract
In this chapter I provide a map of the current debate in experimental pragmatics. First, I present the core ideas of the Gricean intention-based semantics; I claim that this traditional semantic framework has led to an abandonment of the classic code model of verbal communication in favour of an inferential account of communication. I go on to describe the four main levels of meaning that characterize an utterance in a particular context of use: the sentence meaning, what is said, presuppositions, and implicatures. Next, the field of cognitive pragmatics is introduced and I distinguish between neuropragmatics and experimental pragmatics. I then describe the main areas of investigation in experimental pragmatics. I conclude by pointing out that the debate in experimental pragmatics has been characterized by the common assumption that presuppositions are a second level pragmatic phenomenon and I try to suggest some reasons to explain the lack of an experimental research line on presuppositions.
Keywords
PragmaticsInferential model of communicationImplicit communicationExperimental pragmaticsPresuppositions
End Abstract

1.1 Pragmatics: The Inferential Model of Communication

In our everyday lives we constantly communicate with other human beings. Communication comes about in a number of different ways besides purely verbal: by means of gestures, glances, smiles, whistles, clothes worn, and so on. However, because of its complexity and specificity, verbal language is considered the highest form of communication. Indeed, since the origins of Western thought, it has been one of the most frequently studied.
The use of language pervades our everyday lives: when we order a coffee at a bar, when we talk to our friends, when we greet someone, or have a job interview, we communicate with other human beings using the words and expressions of our chosen language (e.g. Italian, English, Spanish, Chinese, etc.). In most cases, linguistic communication takes place without too many complications. Sometimes, however, ordinary conversations are subject to misconceptions or difficulties of understanding. For instance, someone might say:
  1. (1)
    ā€œMark is ready.ā€
Are we be able to say if (1) is either true or false? Obviously not, as the statement is incomplete. To determine whether it is true or false, it is necessary to establish exactly in what respect Mark can be considered ready (e.g. to take an examination? to get married?). To give another example, someone might say:
  1. (2)
    ā€œJohn is very tall.ā€
What do we understand? Not very much. Our first concern is to establish ā€œwith respect to who or to whatā€ John can be considered ā€œvery tallā€. For example, John might be considered tall if compared with a class of five-year-old children, but not so tall if judged in the changing room of a basketball team.
What, then, is the missing ingredient that enables us fully to understand statements (1) and (2)? The answer is that we must first understand the use made of each statement by the speaker in context. This pertains to the field of linguistics called pragmatics: the study of the use of language in context.
Herbert Paul Grice (1913ā€“1988) is recognized as one of the founding fathers of contemporary pragmatics, together with John Langshaw Austin, Peter Strawson, and John Searle. His analyses consist of two distinct components: (i) intention-based semantics, where the meaning of an utterance can be accounted for in terms of the speakerā€™s communicative intentions, and (ii) a theory of conversation based on the principle of cooperation and the notion of implicature, grounded on the distinction between implicit and explicit meaning.
Grice developed a theory of meaning that represents a landmark not only of linguistics and philosophy of language, but also for other disciplines concerned with communication (e.g. semiotics, sociology, discourse analysis, etc.). Moreover, although Grice never used the term ā€œpragmaticsā€, his theory of meaning is the starting point of the contemporary debate in philosophy of language on the boundary between semantics and pragmatics. In the following, some of the core aspects of the Gricean theory of meaning are described, including how it has led to the adoption of an inferential account of communication in lieu of the traditional code model.

1.1.1 Natural versus. Non-Natural Meaning

Griceā€™s theory of meaning starts from a traditional philosophical question: why does a sign mean something? In ā€œMeaningā€ (1957), Grice discussed the problem of the conditions for meaning. From the outset, he adopted a semiotic point of view to address both linguistic and non-linguistic signs (e.g. gestures, images, sounds, etc). The Gricean analysis of meaning is focused mainly on the level of the use of signs: the level of utterancesā€”the action performed by a person who utters a linguistic sign (e.g. a sentence) or a non-linguistic sign (e.g. a gesture)ā€”is always considered.
Grice started his analysis with a survey of the different uses of the verb ā€œto meanā€ in English. He did so first in the paper ā€œMeaningā€ and then in ā€œMeaning Revisitedā€, where he drew a distinction between natural and non-natural meanings. At the beginning of ā€œMeaningā€ he provides the following examples:
  1. (3)
    Those spots mean measles.
  2. (4)
    The recent budget means that we shall have a hard year.
  3. (5)
    Those three rings on the bell (of the bus) mean that the ā€œbus is fullā€.
  4. (6)
    That remark, ā€œSmith couldnā€™t get on without his trouble and strifeā€ meant that his wife was indispensable.
Grice points out that the same linguistic expression ā€œto meanā€ is used with different meanings in the ordinary sentences (3), (4), (5), (6). In fact, in (3) and (4) the verb ā€œto meanā€ performs a factive function, as it implies that what is described is true (i.e. that the person has measles, or that we shall have a hard year). In other words, (3) and (4) have the form ā€œx means yā€ and convey that x entails yā€”that is, a proposition A semantically entails a proposition B iff in all worlds in which A is true, B is true too. For this reason, speakers that utter (3) commit themselves with the claim that the diagnosis is true; or, to be more precise, uttering ā€œThose spots mean measlesā€ is equivalent to uttering ā€œIf it is true that there are spots then it is necessarily true that there is measlesā€. In fact, it would seem contradictory to utter ā€œThose spots mean measles nevertheless she doesnā€™t have measlesā€. Cases (5) and (6) present different uses of the expression ā€œto meanā€. For instance, in utterance (5) the verb ā€œto meanā€ does not perform a factive function: those who utter (5) are not directly committed to claiming that the bus is actually full. For this reason, it might be possible to claim ā€œThose three rings on the bell (of the bus) mean the bus is full although the bus is emptyā€ without falling into contradiction. Likewise, utterance (6) does not convey any implication. This is because the utterance ā€œSmith couldnā€™t get on without his trouble and strifeā€ does not necessarily imply that ā€œSmith found his wife indispensableā€ is true. The same sentence may actually mean something else: for example, ā€œSmith used to pick quarrels with total strangersā€.
How is it possible to explain the difference between the use of ā€œto meanā€ in (3) and (4) and the use of the same linguistic expression in (5) and (6)? Grice distinguishes between two kinds of meaning: utterances (3) and (4) are examples of a natural use of meaningā€”that a sign has a natural meaning when it means something simply because things in the world are in a certain way; conversely, utterances (5) and (6) are examples of non-natural meaning of the verb ā€œto meanā€: in this case, a sign means something only because someone intends to communicate something to an audience by using a sign. With this distinction between natural and non-natural meanings, Grice intends to distinguish between signs that are causally connected with their meanings (e.g. ā€œindexesā€ in Peirceā€™s classification of signs) and those that have no such connection but are driven by conventions and express the intention of a specific agent (see Peirce 1931ā€“1935: 1.346, 2.228, 4.531).

1.1.2 Intention-Based Semantics: The Inferential Model

Having established the distinction between natural and non-natural meanings, Grice devoted his theory to the latter. Non-natural meanings are connected with the idea that communication consists of a mutual process of production and recognition of communicative intentions between speakers, and that intentions ground the conventional aspect of meaning.
By reducing the notion of meaning to the notion of intention (which is why his theory is typically termed intention-based semantics), Grice goes beyond the code model of communication: that is, the traditional idea that linguistic communication consists of a symmetric process of encoding and decoding messages. The code model is said to be rooted in Aristotelian philosophy and its most original developments are found in the Lockean theory of language (Locke 1690: book iii, ch. II, 1) and twentieth-century structuralist semiotics, especially in the work of Jakobson (1960), whose model of communication was partly influenced by the mathematical theory of communication. According to the code model, natural language is constituted by socially fixed connections between expressions and meanings (signifiers and signifieds), which are sufficient for understanding the message. Therefore, during verbal communication, speakers access the mental representations of their interlocutors through a simple operation of decoding the content of the message.
On the contrary, Grice claims that understanding the meaning communicated by a speaker is the result of an inferential process made by hearers on the basis of l...

Table of contents