Property Rights
eBook - ePub

Property Rights

The Argument for Privatization

Walter E. Block

Share book
  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Property Rights

The Argument for Privatization

Walter E. Block

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

In this timely book, Walter E. Block uses classical liberal theory to defend private property rights. Looking at how free enterprise, capitalism and libertarianism are cornerstones of economically prosperous civilizations, Block highlights why private property rights are crucial. Discussing philosophy, libertarian property rights theory, reparations and other property rights issues, this volume is of interest to academics, students, journalists and all those interested in this integral aspect of political economic philosophy.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Property Rights an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Property Rights by Walter E. Block in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Business & Business General. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2019
ISBN
9783030283537
Part IPhilosophy
© The Author(s) 2019
W. E. BlockProperty RightsPalgrave Studies in Classical Liberalismhttps://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-28353-7_1
Begin Abstract

1. Property and Exploitation

Walter E. Block1
(1)
Loyola University, New Orleans, LA, USA
Walter E. Block

Keywords

Property rightsExploitationTheories of property
End Abstract

1. Property Rights

Whenever one says “I own a house,” what one normally means is: I have the right to determine how that particular resource—described in objective, physical terms—is to be employed; I am free to employ it for any purpose whatsoever, provided that in so doing I do not impair the physical integrity of resources owned by others; I am likewise entitled to expect that the physical integrity of my resource, my house, remains unaffected by the actions others perform with the physical resources at their disposal. Property rights, then, are commonly conceived of as extending to specific, physical objects. These objects are economic goods and hence have value; otherwise, no one would claim them. Yet it is not to the value attached to a specific resource that property rights extend, but rather exclusively to the physical integrity of such a good. I do not own the value of my house. I own a physically specified house, and I have the right to expect that others will not physically damage it.

2. Physical Property, Yes; Values, No

Plausible as this theory of property is,1 in much of contemporary political economy and philosophy, confusion abounds on the issue of whether property rights concern the value of physical things or, instead, it is the physical things themselves which are of value.2 It is thus necessary to clarify why the common notion of property rights as extending exclusively to physical things is indeed correct, and why the notion of property rights in values is flawed.
First, it should be noted that these theories are incompatible with each other. It is easily recognized that every action of a person may alter the value (or price) of another person’s property. If A enters the labor or the marriage market, this may impair B’s value in these markets. And if A changes his relative evaluation of beer and bread, or if A decides to become a brewer or a baker himself, this may change the property values of the—other—brewers and bakers. According to the view that value-impairments constitute rights violations, it follows that A’s actions may represent punishable offenses. Yet if A is guilty, then B and the brewers or bakers in turn must be entitled to defend themselves against A’s actions. Their right to defend themselves can only consist in their (or their agent) being permitted to physically attack or restrict A and his property: B must be entitled to physically bar A from entering the labor or marriage market; and the brewers or bakers must be allowed to physically hinder A from spending his own money as he pleases, for example, from using his own possessions for the operation of a brewery or bakery. Based on this theory, the physical damaging or restricting of another person’s property use obviously cannot be said to constitute a rights violation. Rather, physical attacks and physical restrictions on the use of private property then have to be classified as lawful defenses. On the other hand, suppose that physical attacks and physical property restrictions constitute rights violations. Then B and brewers or bakers are not allowed to defend themselves against A’s actions. For A’s actions—his entering the labor or marriage market, his changed evaluation of beer and bread, and his opening of a brewery or bakery—affects neither B’s bodily integrity nor the physical integrity of other brewers’ or bakers’ property. If they engage in physical resistance against A’s actions nonetheless, then the right to defense rests with A. In this case, however, it cannot be considered a rights violation that a person’s actions impair the value of another person’s property. No other, third alternative exists.
These two theories of property are not only incompatible, however. The alternative view—that a person may own the value (or price) or scarce physical goods—is also “praxeologically” impossible3; that is, it is a theory that we cannot put into effect even if we wanted to; as well, it is as argumentatively indefensible. For while every person can, in principle, have control over whether or not his actions cause the physical attributes of other persons’ property to change, control over whether or not his actions affect the value of other people’s property rests with other people and their evaluations. Consequently, it would be impossible to ever know in advance if one’s planned actions were permitted or not. One would have to interrogate the entire population to make sure that one’s planned actions would not impair the value of anybody else’s property; as well, one would have to reach a universal agreement on who was permitted to do what, with which goods.
Mankind would be long dead before this was ever accomplished. Hence, the theory breaks down as nonoperational. Moreover, the proposition that a person may own the value of a physical thing involves an internal contradiction. For simply in order to propose this theory it would have to be presupposed that its proponent is allowed to act.
He must do so prior (and simultaneously) to making his proposition or seeking agreement for his proposal regarding how to protect property values from value-intrusive actions. He cannot wait, and suspend acting, until an agreement is reached; rather, he must be permitted to employ at least his own physical body (and its standing room) immediately.
Otherwise he could not even make his proposal. Yet if one is permitted to assert a proposition—and no one could deny this without falling into a contradiction—then this is possible only because there exist objective (physical) borders of property. Every person can recognize these borders as such on his own, without having to agree first with anyone else with respect to one’s subjective system of values and evaluations. Prior to even beginning the intellectual endeavor of proposing property theories, then, as its very own praxeological foundation, there must be an acting (e.g., speaking) man, defined in terms of physical or human resources. Value of utility considerations, agreements, or contracts—all things that contemporary political philosophers and economists typically regard as fundamental to their various theories of justice or property—already presupposes the existence of physically independent decision-making units. Also presupposed is a description of these units in terms of a person’s property relations to definite physical resources—otherwise there would be no one to value or agree on anything, and nothing on which to agree or about which to make contracts. Anyone proposing anything other than a theory of property in physically defined resources would contradict the content of his proposition merely by making it. He could not even open his mouth if his theory were correct; and the fact that he does open it disproves his claim.4

3. Exploitation

The notion of property in values is praxeologically impossible (nonoperational) if formulated as a theory of justice, that is, as a system of rules that applies universally to each and every person alike. It becomes operational if—and only if—it is employed instead as a theory of exploitation. It is at least logically coherent as a system of rules that privileges one person or group of persons at the expense of another, underprivileged person or group. No one could act, if everyone owned the value attached to what he regarded as his.
Acting is possible, however, if B owns the value of the resources presently at his disposal and is entitled to determine what others, A, may or may not do with resources they control so as to not impair his, B’s, property values. This would perforce include A’s compensatory delivery to B of resources presently possessed by A. On the other hand, A is then entitled to own neither the value nor the physical integrity of his possessions and has no claim against B except that B allows him to do anything as long as it is to B’s advantage.
Although praxeologically possible, such a system of rules does not even qualify as a potential human ethic, because it fails to meet the universalizability criterion. By adopting this system, two distinct classes of persons are created—super-humans or exploiters such as B, and sub-humans or the exploited such as A—to whom different “law” applies. Accordingly, it fails from the outset as a universal, human ethic. It is not—not even in principle—universally acceptable and thus cannot qualify as law. In order to be considered lawful, a rule must apply universally, for everyone equally. The idea of property in values, then, is not only praxeologically impossible—if universalized—but also inhumane—if not universalized.

4. Examples

From this conclusion far-reaching consequences follow: (1) Discrimination; (2) defamation and libel suits; (3) comparable worth, parity, and affirmative action policies; and (4) the notorious “ex-lover seeks compensation for no longer being loved” suits would then have to be regarded as scandalous if at times amusing perversions of law and justice. Likewise, institutions such as (5) licensing laws; (6) zoning regulations; (7) anti-trust laws; and (8) insider trading laws represent legal outgrowths of the property-in-values theory.
Ultimately, they all involve restricting A’s control over specified resources by correspondingly expanding B’s control over them. This holds true even though A had not physically damaged, and was not in the process of physically damaging, any of B’s possessions in doing whatever A wants to do with the means presently at this own disposal. B’s claim against A is based not on physical losses caused by A, but rests solely on B’s assumption that A’s actions, unless restricted, impose a value loss on him. In this theory B owns the value of his property and hence is entitled to reassure his value-integrity by imposing physical restrictions on A’s actions. One party seeks material compensation from another for the crime of non-material value damages suffered from having one’s expectations regarding another’s actions disappointed. Disappointed hopes, of which life offers an unlimited supply, are used by one person as a justification for trying to physically enrich himself at the expense of another.
Let us now illustrate the exploitative character of each of these legal practices in some more detail.

4.1. Discrimination

Strictly speaking discrimination is the refusal to deal with, trade with, live next to, buy from, sell to, engage in any commercial or non-commercial activity whatsoever, with another person. In discriminating against B, A undoubtedly reduces B’s economic well-being, compared to what it would have been had A not so discriminated.5 The value of B’s physical property, as well as his “human capital,”6 falls below the level otherwise attainable. Nevertheless, since B can only own his person plus his physical property, he can have no just claim against A for shunning him.
There exists a categorical distinction between physical invasion and the refusal to deal with, or discrimination.7 A’s actions are that of a boycott and do not constitute physical intrusion. But many commentators, unfortunately, fail to make this vital distinction. All too often it is thought, for example, that rape and discrimination against women are on a continuum. Or that lynching blacks is different only in degree to ignoring them. But a moment’s reflection will show that these activities are night and day compared to each other. The physical assault of B on A (as “retaliation” against A’s prior discriminatory action) always involves losses in value terms. But it also robs A temporarily or permanently of the very means to recover such losses. In contrast, while discrimination may likewise be unpleasant, in leaving B’s physical possessions unimpaired, it strictly limits B’s value losses. For example, if no one will hire ugly women to be secretaries, the wages they command will tend to decline. But at lower compensation levels, these females—their physical integrity and hence their job skills being unimpaired—will become more of a bargain in the labor market. This, presumably, will counter the negative effect of the initial discrimination. They will not be consigned to unemployment, the first result, but will rather find jobs, albeit at lower wages than absent discrimination. However, once on the payroll, they will be able to demonstrate their “true” productivity (perhaps even in excess of that of their more beauteous competitors) and can in this way recoup at least in part their initial salary losses. In sharp contrast, had physical invasion been directed against them (or, as a retaliatory action, against their more beautiful competitors), none of these ameliorative reactions could have come into play.8

4.2. Defamation and Libel

Most commentators have argued that one has a legitimate ownership right to one’s reputation. But this is not so. For the simple reason that one’s reputation consists of the thoughts of other people.9 That is, A’s reputation consists solely of the thoughts of B, C, D, and B’s reputation of those of A, C, D, and so on. But since no one can own the thoughts of other people, one cannot, paradoxically, own one’s own reputation.
While there can be no universal right to one’s reputation, and libel and defamation do not constitute exploitation per se, the right of a person to engage in libelous or defamatory action is not unrestricted. For while everyone has an unrestricted right concerning his thoughts, the right of free speech is not absolute. For example, no one has the right to tell another person “unless you hand over t...

Table of contents