Key Ideas in Contract Law
eBook - ePub

Key Ideas in Contract Law

Nicholas McBride

Share book
  1. 128 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Key Ideas in Contract Law

Nicholas McBride

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This book introduces the reader to a number of ideas and issues that underlie the English law of contract-an area of law that is often regarded as forbiddingly dry and technical but which is here made easy to understand and full of interest.
Taking as its starting point the role contract law plays in helping markets to operate, the book explains how contract law regulates the commercial risks people take, while at the same time placing limits on what may be bought and sold, and ensuring that contractual powers are not unacceptably abused. A final chapter discusses how contract law can be used to make gifts of binding promises to other people. The book provides a rigorous and stimulating journey through the ideas underpinning contract law and is essential reading for anyone with an interest in the subject.
'Clearly written and bursting with interesting and novel ideas, this lively book will be a great resource for anyone interested in Contract Law.' Paul S Davies, Professor of Commercial Law, University College London

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Key Ideas in Contract Law an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Key Ideas in Contract Law by Nicholas McBride in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Law & Contract Law. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2017
ISBN
9781509907229
Edition
1
Topic
Law
Subtopic
Contract Law
Index
Law
1
Introduction
This is a short book about contract law, which—for the time being—we can define as the institution that allows people to enter into legally binding undertakings with other people. The book aims to introduce you to a number of key ideas which will help you make sense of the way contract law works, and why it works in the way it does. Chapter 2 explains how contract law is fine-tuned to support the making of exchanges and deals among people trading goods and services with each other. Chapter 3 deals with how contract law manages the risk that entering into a contract involves, that the contract may prove to be a bad deal for one of the parties to the contract. Chapter 4 looks at when the courts will refuse to enforce certain contracts or contractual terms because the contracts or terms in question are unfair or ‘unconscionable’. Chapter 5 discusses the limits of what can be traded in the marketplace and the consequent limits on what sort of contracts people can enter into with each other. And Chapter 6 looks at the interaction between the law of contract and the law of gifts, and in particular when a promise for which nothing was asked in return will be legally binding.
John Maynard Keynes famously observed that ‘The ideas of economists and political philosophers, both when they are right and when they are wrong, are more powerful than is commonly understood. Indeed the world is ruled by little else. Practical men, who believe themselves to be quite exempt from any intellectual influence, are usually the slaves of some defunct economist’ (Keynes 1936, chapter 24).* In the case of contract law, we have been slaves too long to the ideas of a French jurist, Robert Joseph Pothier (1699–1772) and his 1761 work TraitĂ© des obligations. Written about French law, not English law, Pothier’s views on contract law—in particular, what is sometimes called ‘The Will Theory of Contract Law’, according to which contract law exists to give effect to the intention of the parties to an agreement that the agreement be legally binding—were seized upon by English contract scholars in the nineteenth century mainly, it seems to this author, because of an inability to imagine any better theory of contract law. (For an account of the reception of Pothier’s views among English writers on contract law, see Swain 2015, 148–52, 172–200, 264–65.) This book is an attempt to offer the reader something better than warmed-over Pothier; something that does more justice to the details and features of English contract law than the Will Theory can, and puts the reader in the best possible position to understand and evaluate contract law and develop informed opinions as to what the future of English contract law should look like.
*Throughout this book, full references to books and articles referenced in the text can be found by consulting the Bibliography at the back of the book.
2
Markets
In this chapter, I want to set out a very simple idea—that we have a law of contract in order to facilitate the orderly workings of the marketplace, where people can trade whatever can be lawfully traded.
1.ARTIFICIAL TRUST
For markets to exist, two things are essential (see Mises 1949, at 238). First, it must be the case that no one person can produce everything they need to live—so in order to survive, people have to trade with each other. Second, people need to be able to enjoy (i) secure legal control (in other words, private ownership) of the means by which useful things are produced, and the things which are produced with those means, and (ii) the ability to transfer that secure legal control to one another. This then enables people to trade with each other, so that if having secure legal control over my apple would be more useful to you than the secure legal control that you currently have over your orange, and having secure legal control over your orange would be more useful to me than the secure legal control I currently have over my apple, then we can enter into a mutually beneficial trade—your orange for my apple.
But if we are to make a trade, we will usually need a third element to be present—we will need to be able to act as though we trust each other. This quality of being able to act as though I trust you, we can call ‘artificial trust’ (following Galanter 1998, 806, and Putnam 2000, 147; Cross 2005 calls this kind of trust, ‘cognitive trust’). As has long been acknowledged (see Hobbes 1651, XIV; and Hume 1738, 3.2.5.8), if this third element of artificial trust is missing, then people’s abilities to make deals with each other become radically attenuated. People would not be able to stagger their exchanges, so that I pay you now for delivery later, or I deliver now and expect payment from you later. My inability to act as though I trust you not to let me down later on, after I have performed my side of our deal, will prevent us from doing this. So if I want to buy a car from you for £1,000, the only way that deal could work—in the absence of our being able to act as though we trust each other not to let each other down in performing our side of the deal—would be for me to hand over £1,000 to you at exactly the same time as you hand over the keys to the car to me. However, if you want me to wash your car for £50, that exchange would become impossible in the absence of our third element as we could not (unlike in the previous example) instantaneously swap your £50 for my services in washing your car. One of us will always have to perform before the other and take the risk of being let down by the other. The same point applies to David Hume’s example of a trade of services, where Farmer A and Farmer B cannot harvest their ripe corn on their own, but need the other’s help to get the corn in. It makes sense for them to trade their services, with Farmer A helping to harvest Farmer B’s corn when it becomes ripe, in return for Farmer B doing the same for Farmer A. But making such a trade will be impossible if Farmer A and Farmer B cannot act as though they trust each other as one of them will inevitably have to perform first and hope that the other does not let them down when it comes to their performing their side of the deal.
This is where contract law comes in. It enables people trading in the marketplace to act as though they trust each other by making the promises they make to each other legally enforceable. The result is that if A orders some goods from B, promising to pay B at the end of the month, B can sell the goods to A on credit (Latin for ‘he believes’) because B knows that A’s promise to pay at the end of the month will be legally enforceable—so if A lets B down and does not pay, B will still be able to extract the promised money from A. B does not have to actually trust A to pay—if B did, then B would not have to worry whether A’s promise to pay was legally binding. All B has to do, to be able to sell to A on credit, is act as though he trusts A to pay—and that is what the law of contract both enables B to do, and aims to enable B to do. As the legal historian Brian Simpson observes, ‘the essential function of contract law is to permit credit, money-credit’ (Simpson 1975, 281). More generally, ‘large-scale, well-functioning markets [cannot] develop without the assistance of law’ and contract law ‘strengthens and extends markets’ (Oman 2016, 35–36; see also Oman 2012) by enabling parties to a deal to act as though they trust that any promises that are made as part of that deal will be performed. In other words, contract law exists to facilitate exchanges of goods and services in the marketplace by fostering artificial trust among the people engaged in making those exchanges.
2.ASPECTS OF CONTRACT LAW
The role contract law plays in creating artificial trust between actors in the marketplace accounts for a number of different aspects of contract law.
THE DOCTRINE OF CONSIDERATION
The doctrine of consideration says, very roughly, that a promise will only be contractually binding if something of value in the eyes of the law has been given in return for the promise. (Note that some promises for which nothing has been given in return (known as ‘gratuitous promises’) can be legally binding—we will deal with these in Chapter 6, where the doctrine of consideration is discussed in much more detail.) Immediately one sees a connection being made here between contract law and the marketplace—according to the doctrine of consideration, a promise will only be contractually binding if something has been given in return for it.
In practice, two types of promise will normally be said to be ‘supported by consideration’ and therefore contractually binding. The first is a promise to reward someone if they act in a particular way, with the result that that someone is induced to act in that way. So, for example, if I promise to pay you £100 if you wash my car, and you are induced by my promise to wash my car, my promise to pay you £100 will be contractually binding—your washing my car has provided the consideration needed to make my promise binding. (Note that there is no need for my promise to be in writing or accompanied by any kind of formality to be legally binding—the joke that ‘A verbal contract isn’t worth the paper it’s written on’ is just that: a joke.) The second kind of promise is made as part of an agreement under which both of the parties to the agreement promise to do things for each other. The promises made under this agreement will normally be contractually binding, with the promises made by one of the parties providing consideration for the promises made by the other party and vice versa. The agreement reached by the parties is known as a ‘bilateral contract’, because both parties to the agreement will be contractually bound to perform the promises they made to the other party. Contrast that with the situation where in return for my promise to pay you £100, you have washed my car. As only one of us (me) is legally bound to do something for the other (you) in this situation, lawyers say that there exists here a ‘unilateral contract’.
It has been questioned whether consideration should be found in the case of a bilateral executory contract—where you and I have reached an agreement under which I promise to deliver 1,000 widgets (an imaginary item of commerce) to you at the end of the month and you promise to pay £500 per widget when they are delivered, but neither of us have yet done anything to perform our sides of the agreement. Why, it has been asked (see Atiyah 1990, 22–25, 167–70, 191–92) should the law find that we are each bound by our promises, even though neither of us have done anything to rely on the other’s promises, and one of us may be attempting to pull out of the agreement just five minutes after it was entered into? However, it can easily be seen that contract law would fail in its mission to facilitate the orderly workings of the marketplace were it not to find that bilateral agreements are legally binding as soon as they are entered into. In a world where such agreements were not automatically binding, but had to be relied on or part-performed before they could be said to be binding, the chains of contracts that go into the production of something as simple as a pencil would become much more vulnerable to being broken by a party who forms one link in the chain trying to argue that he is entitled to back out of what now appears to him to be a bad deal (see Rudden 1989, 84–89).
OBJECTIVITY
The principle of objectivity in contract law says that if I enter into a contract with you, I am not bound to do what I intended to promise to do when I entered into that contract, but I am instead bound to do what I reasonably gave you the impression I was promising to do when I entered into that contract. More generally, I will not be allowed to argue, ‘Term x isn’t part of the contract I entered into with you because I never intended to agree to that.’ If I reasonably gave you the impression that I was agreeing to term x being part of our contract, then I will normally be bound by that term. Again, one can easily see how contract law would fail in its mission to facilitate the orderly workings of the marketplace were it not to give effect to the objective principle. If you reasonably thought that you had made a deal with me on terms x, y and z, you would still be unable to act as though you trusted me to adhere to those terms if it were the case that I could at any time say that I was not bound by one of those terms because I had not intended to agree to that term being part of my contract with you.
Two limits on the objective principle for determining the terms of a contract should be mentioned. First, you can only argue that term x is part of a contract you made with me if you reasonably thought that I was agreeing to term x’s being part of the contract. If you knew all along that I was not agreeing to this, you cannot argue that term x is part of our contract even if a reasonable person watching our negotiations would have concluded that it was. For example, in Hartog v Colin & Shields [1939] 3 All ER 533, the defendants proposed to sell 30,000 hare skins to the claimants. The defendants offered to sell the hare skins at a price of 10 pence per piece; that is, 10 pence per hare skin, resulting in a total price of £3,000. In the course of the subsequent negotiations, the defendants made a slip and offered to sell the hare skins for 10 pence per pound, which was effectively an offer to sell the hare skins for £1,000 as three hare skins weighed a pound. The claimants immediately accepted this very generous offer and attempted to hold the defendants to the deal. The Court of Appeal held that they could not: the claimants never seriously thought that the defendants were agreeing to sell the hare skins for 10 pence per pound.
Second, what happens if two parties both think they have reached an agreement, but they have different views as to what they agreed, and both views are reasonable? Arguably, this was the case in Raffles v Wichelhaus (1864) 2 H & C 906. The contract there was for the sale and purchase of 125 bales of cotton at 17 pence per pound, where the cotton was due to arrive in Liverpool ‘ex Peerless from Bombay’—that is, on board a ship called Peerless that was coming from Bombay. Unfortunately, there were two such ships. The purchaser of the cotton had been thinking of a ship called Peerless that left Bombay in October 1862 and arrived in Liverpool in February 1863. The seller had been thinking of an identically named ship that left Bombay in December 1862 and arrived in Liverpool in April 1863. It is not known what happened when the purchaser turned up quayside in February 1863 to discover none of the cotton he had purchased emerging from ‘his’ Peerless. He might have been quite relieved as the going price for cotton was then about 16 pence per pound, and undertaking to purchase it at 17 pence per pound had turned out to be a bad deal (see Baird 2013, 9). But we do know what happened when the April Peerless arrived and the seller unloaded 125 bales of cotton only to find the purchaser was absent. The seller sued the purchaser for the price of the cotton, and the purchaser argued that he was not bound to pay because he had been expecting to purchase cotton arriving on the February Peerless. The outcome of the case was inconclusive. The seller argued that the purchaser’s belief as to which Peerless the cotton would be arriving on was irrelevant to the purchaser’s liability, but the court agreed with the purchaser that it might be and sent the case for trial. However, most academics are of the opinion that there was no contract in Raffles—the two parties had different views as to what they had agreed, and both parties’ views were equally reasonable given the fact of there being two ships named Peerless, both sailing from Bombay.
STRICT LIABILITY
Contractual liability is unusual in that it is usually strict liability—a contracting party who has undertaken to do x under a contract cannot escape liability for failing to do x by showing that it was not his fault that he failed to do x. For example, under section 9 of the Consumer Rights Act 2015, a term will be implied into a contract between a business and a consumer purchasing goods from that business that the goods will be of ‘satisfactory quality’. So if you buy a car from a dealer, and the car turns out to be no good, you can require the dealer to replace the car, or give your money back, or cover the cost of purchasing an equivalent car from another dealer—and whatever remedy you seek, it will never be a defence for the dealer to say ‘It’s not my fault the car was no good! It was the manufacturer’s fault!’
Again, the market-based perspective on contract law being advanced here makes sense of this aspect of contract law. Someone buying a car would find it more difficult to act as though he trusted a dealer to sell him a car of ‘satisfactory quality’—the only thing the consumer is interested in getting—if all the law gave him on purchasing the car was an assurance that should the car turn out to be no good, he would be able to sue the dealer if the dealer was at fault for the fact that the car was no good. Only an assurance of being able to sue the dealer whenever the car turns out to be no good will reassure a consumer who is wondering whether or not to purchase a car from that dealer.
However, there are limits to strict liability in contract law. It would be a foolish doctor who guaranteed to cure her patient, and in the case of a business that contracts to do work for a consumer, the most the law will require the business to do is to ‘perform the service with reasonable care and skill’ (Consumer Rights Act 2015, section 49). And as we will see in Chapter 3, there are certain limited circumstances in which a contracting party can escape liability for failing to do what she contracted to do on the ground that a change in circumstances made it impossible or difficult for her to fulfil her side of the deal she made.
STANDARD FORM CONTRACTING
It has been estimated (Zamir 2013, 2096) that 99 per cent of all contracts take the form of standard form contracts—that is, contracts that are formed by A presenting B with a standard form setting out the terms on which they are willing to contract on a ‘take it or leave it’ basis, with B opting to ‘take it’. (Whenever you purchase goods in a store or online, you are effectively entering into a standard form contract with the seller.)
This does not mean that A entirely gets to dictate the terms of the contract between him and B. Under the objective principle, A will find it difficult to argue that he reasonably thought that B was agreeing to be bound by a term in A’s standard form that is so oppressive that B would be surprised to hear that such a term was in A’s standard form. So that term will not form part of the A–B contract unless A can argue that he made reasonable efforts to bring B’s attention to that term before B agreed to deal with A (Thornton v Shoe Lane Parking Co [1971] 2 QB 163) or B did something, such as signing A’s standard form, to make A think that B was agreeing to deal with A on all of A’s standard terms regardless of what they said (L’Estrange v F Graucob Ltd [1934] 2 KB 394). In such cases, A’s claim that he reasonably thought B was agreeing to the onerous term in A’s standard form will become much more plausible. But being able to get me to agree to deal with you on your terms obvious...

Table of contents