Kantian Theory and Human Rights
eBook - ePub

Kantian Theory and Human Rights

Andreas Follesdal, Reidar Maliks, Andreas Follesdal, Reidar Maliks

Share book
  1. 210 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Kantian Theory and Human Rights

Andreas Follesdal, Reidar Maliks, Andreas Follesdal, Reidar Maliks

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Human rights and the courts and tribunals that protect them are increasingly part of our moral, legal, and political circumstances. The growing salience of human rights has recently brought the question of their philosophical foundation to the foreground. Theorists of human rights often assume that their ideal can be traced to the philosophy of Immanuel Kant and his view of humans as ends in themselves. Yet, few have attempted to explore exactly how human rights should be understood in a Kantian framework. The scholars in this book have gathered to fill this gap. At the center of Kant's theory of rights is a view of freedom as independence from domination. The chapters explore the significance of this theory for the nature of human rights, their justification, and the legitimacy of international human rights courts.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Kantian Theory and Human Rights an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Kantian Theory and Human Rights by Andreas Follesdal, Reidar Maliks, Andreas Follesdal, Reidar Maliks in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Politics & International Relations & Politics. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

1
Kantian Theory and Human Rights

Reidar Maliks and Andreas Follesdal
Human rights and the courts and tribunals that protect them are increasingly part of our moral, legal, and political circumstances. Commonly understood as instituting inalienable and fundamental rights that persons are entitled to by their humanity, international treaties and conventions and the bodies they establish have come to include civil, political, social, and cultural rights as human rights.1 These international human rights, as we shall refer to them, and the various judicial bodies together make up the contemporary human rights regime. They have, inter alia, the practical function of setting limits to state sovereignty. These treaties thereby provide a justification for international monitoring and other forms of intervention against states that transgress them.2 Their power in justifying political action render human rights and their courts controversial and a source of frequent disputes. Many controversies have to do with their justification. The moral foundation of human rights was not part of the legal conventions that established them. The philosopher Jacques Maritain, who was among the drafters of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, described the approach this way:
So long as minds are not united in faith or philosophy, there will be mutual conflicts between interpretations and justifications. In the field of practical conclusions, on the other hand, agreement on a joint declaration is possible, given an approach pragmatic rather than theoretical, and cooperation in the comparison, recasting and fixing of formulae, to make them acceptable to both parties as points of convergence in practice, however opposed the theoretical viewpoints.3
But while the framers managed to create a consensus, this strategy of avoidance left the difficulty of making sense of human rights to judges on human rights courts, to lawmakers in domestic and international fora, and to critics in the public sphere.
It is a striking feature of the bourgeoning field of human rights philosophy that many of the most significant contributions reach for Kant in justifying human rights. James Griffin considers human rights as a way of protecting the supreme value of moral personhood, which he takes from Kant’s writings on ethics.4 John Rawls builds his notion of an international society of peoples protecting rights on Kant’s writings on international law.5 JĂŒrgen Habermas employs Kant’s egalitarian and universalist concept of dignity to explain the legal status of rights.6 Thomas Pogge’s notion of human rights as moral claims on the global institutional order continues the spirit of Kant’s cosmopolitanism.7 This use of the Enlightenment thinker is perhaps not surprising, considering Kant’s prominence as a philosopher and the universalism and egalitarianism, which is the foundation of almost all he wrote. The turn to Kant is also understandable, considering his pioneering international and cosmopolitan theory, based on the view that nations are connected in a community where “a violation of right on one place of the earth is felt in all”.8
Few of those who build on Kant’s foundation stop to explore what he really thought, however. Most of those who refer to Kant today have no ambition to provide a philosophically accurate insight into his philosophy. Kant is used only as a means (as it were) to the end of understanding a contemporary phenomenon better. This is neither surprising nor regrettable. Although Kant is remarkably prescient, the problems facing an eighteenth-century thinker were different, and it would be unreasonable to expect his answers to speak directly to contemporary questions. Indeed, many of his views, such as his defense of state sovereignty, seem at odds with the current practice. Such differences should not be a reason to dismiss Kant out of hand. To the contrary, his arguments are a source of interest because they can lead us to see and assess the current human rights regime in a better light.
This book aims to bring together two fields of growing current interest, to aid us in understanding better a striking international development of our time, and the thinker who, perhaps more than anyone else, was its progenitor. The essays are animated by the idea that if we get a better grip on Kant’s philosophy of right, we can energize the creative endeavor of developing philosophical theories of human rights, inspired by his particular way of thinking about the relation between rights and the rule of law. It is, perhaps, not by chance that the steep increase in theories of human rights has been matched by a renaissance in studies of Kant’s political philosophy. Writings by Arthur Ripstein, Pauline Kleingeld, B. Sharon Byrd and Joachim Hruschka have contributed to shining a light on what has been a relatively underexplored theory.9 These recent contributions join a small stream of valuable scholarship from decades back, including that of Howard Williams.10
Three features characteristic of Kant’s thinking frequently crop up in the following chapters and help explain why so much recent scholarship may indeed properly be called ‘Kantian’. These features concern rights, legitimacy, and institutions. First, legal rights are central. Kant tended to think of legal rights as grounded in noninstrumental terms: they are not just means or strategies to achieve other ends we desire, such as well-being or happiness for the greatest number. Rights are not even considered mere instruments for achieving freedom. Rather, freedom is constituted by the rights and duties that enable individuals to be subject to the rule of law instead of arbitrary power. Second, political and legal authorities that establish human rights through law derive their legitimacy from being capable of justification to individuals. This is based on Kant’s view of individuals as free, equal in dignity, and capable of being their own masters. Third, the public institutions at the domestic and the international level are considered part of the same system. Thus, municipal law cannot be seen in abstraction from the international and cosmopolitan political community in which states are situated. Nor can international human rights law neglect the rights to independence of existing political communities.
The contributions explore these Kantian principles in different directions. The following is an overview of the book’s chapters. The first three chapters center on the nature and justification for human rights in a Kantian framework. In chapter two, Howard Williams explores Kantian underpinnings for a theory of ‘multirights’, i.e. human rights institutions at intersecting national and international levels. The chapter stresses the holistic character of Kant’s a priori view of right and law where private and domestic, international and cosmopolitan laws are intertwined with one another. This holistic doctrine is applicable to our present developing regimes of domestic and international law, especially in the European context, where the boundaries between the two are increasingly being eroded. The chapter demonstrates that the Kantian perspective is sensitive to the historical—generally national—origins of legal order, whilst seeking to present law from a universalistic standpoint. In conclusion, Williams shows how the Kantian account of right can be deployed to advance the regime of multirights. Kant’s concept of innate right provides a foundation for cosmopolitan right, underpinning a multilevel system of law.
In chapter three, Ariel Zylberman looks at what he calls Kant’s juridical idea of human rights. He argues that a right in a strict juridical sense bears three distinguishing marks. It is a relational claim against another, a claim that is logically correlated with the other’s duty. A right is noninstrumentally justified as a first-order claim to independence against others. And a right is necessarily attached to a second-order power to enforce the right—a power that need not be exercised by the right holder. Thirdly, for Kant, human rights are a priori rights—those rights which play a unique discursive function as the constitutive conditions of any claim of right. A human right is noninstrumentally justified as an enforceable, direct requirement of a person’s original right to independence.
In chapter four, Sofie Mþller explores human rights jurisprudence through the framework of Kant’s legal metaphors, particularly as they are deployed in the Critique of Pure Reason and in comparison with the Doctrine of Right. Instead of conceiving of the legal analogies as serving a merely expository purpose, Mþller investigates which concepts of laws and judgment we find in these analogies. Part of Kant’s legal imagery in the first Critique is the parallel between original acquisition of property in theories of natural right and the original acquisition of the forms of intuition and the categories of understanding. This metaphor from the Critique of Pure Reason is comparedto Kant’s later exposition of the original acquisition of property as being only provisional in a state of nature in the Doctrine of Right. In particular, Kant’s use of the notion of a state of nature as parallel to the pre-critical state of reason shows a significant continuity between the two works.
The next two chapters center on the scope of rights in directions often thought utterly at odds with Kant’s original account. In chapter five, Luke J. Davies provides a Kantian defense of the right to health care. First, in the case of preventative care, Davies suggests that its provision is a straightforward exercise of the state’s obligation to protect our external freedom. That is, preventative health care is a necessary (though insufficient) condition for the protection of the means we already have. Second, in the case of emergency care, Davies claims that the state’s obligation to maintain those citizens who cannot maintain themselves applies when a citizen requires immediate, life-saving medical interventions. Third, the argument for a more general entitlement is based on the obligation of the state to maintain itself in perpetuity, which requires institutions that increase the freedom of its citizens and which rules out that the freedom of some can come at the cost of the basic freedom of others. The benefit of the Kantian approach to the right to health care is that it takes as basic exactly the principle that libertarian objectors to the right employ: the state’s requirement to secure the freedom of choice of each.
In chapter six, Özlem Ayse ÖzgĂŒr argues that even in the absence of supporting social institutions, people have affirmative rights to a certain measure of security and economic well-being. Her position involves the idea that everybody whose right to subsistence is threatened can claim that the rest have a collective duty to provide her with a system for accessing this right. She argues that our individual duty to relieve undeserved pain is shaped in accordance with this collective duty and that duties associated with human rights are collective duties of justice. Since civil, political, and socioeconomic rights give rise to collective duties of justice, it is a mistake to consider socioeconomic rights as mere manifesto rights on the grounds of the different nature of duties.
The next three chapters explore what might make international human rights courts legitimate, or more so. In chapter seven, Svenja Ahlhaus explores a democratic paradox of international human rights courts and defends a Kantian solution. She makes three interrelated claims. First, international human rights courts constitute a democratic paradox, because they simultaneously protect and restrict citizens’ democratic rights by interfering from outside in domestic political systems. Hence, democratic theorists have normative reasons both to favour and to oppose them. Second, she analyzes the most elaborated attempt to solve this paradox as presented by Richard Bellamy, and argues that his neo-republican intergovernmentalist framework does not offer an adequate solution. Third, she argues that one can still solve the democratic paradox of IHRCs within neo-republican theory if one follows James Bohman’s Kantian-inspired cosmopolitan framework.
In chapter eight, Markus Patberg considers the democratic legitimacy of international human rights courts from the perspective of Kantian democratic theory. The analysis starts from the observation that the current discussion about the legitimacy of international human rights review neglects the issue of legitimate institution building. Patberg addresses this deficit on the basis of a dualist conception of democracy that distinguishes between popular sovereignty in normal and extraordinary politics, i.e. between institutionalized democracy and the democratic politics of institution building. The main thesis is that the extraordinary dimension of democracy is essential to the legitimacy of international human rights courts and that the peoples of the member states enjoy the right to decide upon the creation of these institutions. Patberg frames this as an issue of constituent power beyond the state, which is to be understood as a democratic entitlement of the peoples of the member states to establish and reform political institutions in the global realm.
In chapter nine, Reidar Maliks explores the legitimacy of international human rights courts from a Kantian perspective. The chapter takes its point of departure in a critique of two recent Kantian attempts to understand the legitimacy of human rights courts. Contrary to a political view, maintained by Armin von Bogdandy and Ingo Venzke, and a moral view maintained by Martti Koskenniemi, Maliks argues for a view associated with the rule of law. According to this view, court legitimacy requires matching legislative organs that perform the twin functions of developing the law and checking courts from overstepping their boundaries. This functional differentiation between institutions of legislation and application is essential to maintain the generality of the law, and therefore to secure that no one is subject to arbitrary power. The implication is that the growth of the international judiciary should be...

Table of contents