Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 1
eBook - ePub

Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 1

The Dawn of Analysis

Scott Soames

  1. 432 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 1

The Dawn of Analysis

Scott Soames

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This is a major, wide-ranging history of analytic philosophy since 1900, told by one of the tradition's leading contemporary figures. The first volume takes the story from 1900 to mid-century. The second brings the history up to date.
As Scott Soames tells it, the story of analytic philosophy is one of great but uneven progress, with leading thinkers making important advances toward solving the tradition's core problems. Though no broad philosophical position ever achieved lasting dominance, Soames argues that two methodological developments have, over time, remade the philosophical landscape. These are (1) analytic philosophers' hard-won success in understanding, and distinguishing the notions of logical truth, a priori truth, and necessary truth, and (2) gradual acceptance of the idea that philosophical speculation must be grounded in sound prephilosophical thought. Though Soames views this history in a positive light, he also illustrates the difficulties, false starts, and disappointments endured along the way. As he engages with the work of his predecessors and contemporaries--from Bertrand Russell and Ludwig Wittgenstein to Donald Davidson and Saul Kripke--he seeks to highlight their accomplishments while also pinpointing their shortcomings, especially where their perspectives were limited by an incomplete grasp of matters that have now become clear.
Soames himself has been at the center of some of the tradition's most important debates, and throughout writes with exceptional ease about its often complex ideas. His gift for clear exposition makes the history as accessible to advanced undergraduates as it will be important to scholars. Despite its centrality to philosophy in the English-speaking world, the analytic tradition in philosophy has had very few synthetic histories. This will be the benchmark against which all future accounts will be measured.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 1 an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 1 by Scott Soames in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Filosofía & Filosofía moderna. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2009
ISBN
9781400825790
PART ONE
G. E. MOORE ON ETHICS, EPISTEMOLOGY,
AND PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS
CHAPTER 1
COMMON SENSE
AND PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS
CHAPTER OUTLINE
1. The commonsense view of the world
Propositions about ourselves and the world that we all know to be true
The absurdity of denying such knowledge
Implications for philosophy
2. The conception of philosophy as analysis
Examples of analysis: perceptual knowledge and ethical statements
George Edward Moore was born the son of a doctor, in 1873, in a suburb of London. He studied classics—Greek and Latin—in school, and entered Cambridge University in 1892 as a classical scholar. At the end of his first year he met Bertrand Russell, two years his senior, who encouraged him to study philosophy, which he did with great success. He was especially drawn to ethics and epistemology, which remained his primary philosophical interests for most of his career. After his graduation in 1896, he held a series of fellowships at Trinity College for eight years, by the end of which he was recognized as a rising star in the philosophical world. Along with Bertrand Russell and Ludwig Wittgenstein, he would remain one of the three most important and influential philosophers in Great Britain until his retirement from Cambridge in 1939.
Although highly regarded for his many contributions to philosophy, G. E. Moore was probably best known as the leading philosophical champion of common sense. His commonsense view, expressed in a number of his works, is most explicitly spelled out in his famous paper, “A Defense of Common Sense,” published in 1925.1 There, he identifies the propositions of “common sense” to be among those that all of us not only believe, but also feel certain that we know to be true. Examples of commonsense propositions that Moore claimed to know with certainty are given in (1):
1a. that he [Moore] had a human body which was born at a certain time in the past, which had existed continuously, at or near the surface of the earth, ever since birth, which had undergone changes, having started out small and grown larger over time, and which had coexisted with many other things having shape and size in three dimensions which it had been either in contact with, or located at various distances from, at different times;
1b. that among those things his body had coexisted with were other living human bodies which themselves had been born in the past, had existed at or near the surface of the earth, had grown over time, and had been in contact with or located at various distances from other things, just as in (1a); and, in addition, some of these bodies had already died and ceased to exist;
1c. that the earth had existed for many years before his [Moore’s] body was born; and for many of those years large numbers of human bodies had been alive on it, and many of them had died and ceased to exist before he [Moore] was born;
1d. that he [Moore] was a human being who had had many experiences of different types—e.g., (i) he had perceived his own body and other things in his environment, including other human bodies; (ii) he had observed facts about the things he was perceiving such as the fact that one thing was nearer to his body at a certain time than another thing was; (iii) he had often been aware of other facts which he was not at the time observing, including facts about his past; (iv) he had had expectations about his future; (v) he had had many beliefs, some true and some false; (vi) he had imagined many things that he didn’t believe, and he had had dreams and feelings of various kinds;
1e. that just as his [Moore’s] body had been the body of a person [namely, Moore himself] who had had the types of experiences in (1d), so many human bodies other than his had been the bodies of other persons who had had experiences of the same sort.
Finally, in addition to the truisms in (1) that Moore claimed to know about himself and his body, he claimed to know with certainty the following proposition about other human beings:
2. that very many human beings have known propositions about themselves and their bodies corresponding to the propositions indicated in (1) that he [Moore] claimed to know about himself and his body.
The propositions indicated by (1) and (2) constitute the core of what Moore called the “Common Sense view of the world.”2 His position regarding the propositions of common sense is that they constitute the starting point for philosophy, and, as such, are not the sorts of claims that can be overturned by philosophical argument. Part of his reason for specifying these propositions in such a careful, painstaking way, was to make clear that he was not including among them every proposition that has commonly been believed at one or another time in history. For example, propositions about God, the origin of the universe, the shape of the earth, the limits of human knowledge, the difference between the sexes, and the inherent goodness or badness of human beings are not included in what Moore means by the truisms of Common Sense—no matter how many people may believe them.
Although he did not attempt any precise characterization of what makes certain propositions truisms of Common Sense, while excluding from this class other commonly believed propositions, the position he defended was designed and circumscribed so as to make the denial of his Common Sense truisms seem absurd, or even paradoxical. Of course, he fully recognized that none of the propositions in (1) are such that their denials are contradictory; none are necessary truths—i.e., propositions that would have been true no matter which possible state the world had been in. Nevertheless the propositions in (1) about Moore would have been very hard for him to deny, just as the corresponding propositions about other human beings, mentioned in (2), would be hard for them to deny. This is not to say that no philosophers have ever denied such propositions. Some have. However, Moore maintains that if any philosopher ever goes so far as to deny that there are any true propositions at all of the sort indicated in (1), and mentioned in (2), then the mere fact that the philosopher has de nied this provides a convincing refutation of his own view. Assuming, as Moore does, that any philosopher is a human being who has lived on the earth, had experiences, and formed beliefs, we can be sure that if any philosopher has doubted anything, then some human being has doubted something, and so has existed, in which case many claims about that philosopher corresponding to the claims Moore makes about himself surely must be true. Moore expresses this point (in what I take to be a slightly exaggerated form): “the proposition that some propositions belonging to each of these classes are true is a proposition which has the peculiarity, that, if any philosopher has ever denied it, it follows from the fact that he as denied it, that he must have been wrong in denying it.”3
But what about Moore’s claim that he knows the propositions in (1) to be true, and his further, more general, claim (2)—that many other human beings know similar propositions about themselves to be true—can these claims be denied? Certainly, the things claimed to be known aren’t necessary truths, and their denials are not contradictory. Some philosophers have denied that anyone truly knows any of these things, and this position is not obviously inconsistent or self-undermining. Such a philosopher might consistently conclude that though no one knows the things wrongly said in (2) to be known, these things may nevertheless turn out to be true after all. Though scarcely credible, this position is at least coherent. However, such a philosopher must be careful. For if he goes on to confidently assert, as some have been wont to do, that claims such as the proposition that human beings live on the Earth, which has existed for many years, are commonly believed, and constitute the core of the commonsense conception of the world, then he is flirting with contradiction. For one who confidently asserts this may be taken to be implicitly claiming to know that which he asserts—namely that certain things are commonly believed by human beings generally. But that means he is claiming to know that there are human beings who have had certain beliefs and experiences; and it is hard to see how he could do this without taking himself to know many of the same sorts of things that Moore was claiming to know in putting forward the propositions in (1). Finally, unless the philosopher thinks he is unique, he will be hard pressed to deny that others are in a position to know such things as well, in which case he will be well on his way to accepting (2).
Considerations like these were offered by Moore in an attempt to persuade his audience that the commonsense view of the world, as he understood it, should be regarded as so obviously correct as to be un-contentious. In this, it must be said, he was very persuasive. It is very hard to imagine anyone sincerely and consistently denying the central contentions of Moore’s commonsense point of view. Moore himself was convinced that no one ever had. For example he says:
I am one of those philosophers who have held that the ‘Common Sense view of the world’ is, in certain fundamental features, wholly true. But it must be remembered that, according to me, all philosophers, without exception, have agreed with me in holding this [i.e., they have all believed it to be true]: and that the real difference, which is commonly expressed in this way, is only a difference between those philosophers, who have also held views inconsistent with these features in ‘the Common Sense view of the world,’ and those who have not.4
After all, Moore would point out, philosophers live lives that are much like those of other men—lives in which they take for granted all the commonsense truths that he does. Moreover, this is evidenced as much in their profession of skepticism as in anything else. In propounding their skeptical doctrines, they address their lectures to other men, publish books they know will be purchased and read, and criticize the writings of others. Moore’s point is that in doing all this they presuppose that which their skeptical doctrines deny. If he is right about this, then his criticism of their inconsistency is quite a devastating indictment. Reading or listening to Moore, many found it hard not to agree that he was right.
Despite its obviousness, Moore’s view was, in its own way, extraordinarily ambitious, and even revolutionary. He claimed to know a great many things that other philosophers had found problematic or doubtful. What is more, he claimed to know these things without philosophical argument, and without directly answering the different skeptical objections that had been raised against such knowledge. How he was able to do this is something we will examine carefully in the next chapter.
For now, I wish to emphasize how Moore’s stance is to be contrasted with a different, more skeptical, position that philosophers have sometimes adopted toward the claims of common sense. The skeptic’s position is that of being the ultimate arbiter or judge of those claims. The philosopher who takes this stance prides himself on not taking pre-philosophical knowledge claims at face value. Given some pre-theoretically obvious claims of common sense—e.g., that material objects are capable of existing unperceived, that there are other minds, and that perception is a source of knowledge about the world—the skeptical philosopher typically asks how we could possibly know that these claims are true. He regards this question as a challenge to justify our claims; if we in the end can’t give proofs that satisfy his demands, he is ready to conclude that we don’t kn...

Table of contents

Citation styles for Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 1

APA 6 Citation

Soames, S. (2009). Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 1 ([edition unavailable]). Princeton University Press. Retrieved from https://www.perlego.com/book/734248/philosophical-analysis-in-the-twentieth-century-volume-1-the-dawn-of-analysis-pdf (Original work published 2009)

Chicago Citation

Soames, Scott. (2009) 2009. Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 1. [Edition unavailable]. Princeton University Press. https://www.perlego.com/book/734248/philosophical-analysis-in-the-twentieth-century-volume-1-the-dawn-of-analysis-pdf.

Harvard Citation

Soames, S. (2009) Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 1. [edition unavailable]. Princeton University Press. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/734248/philosophical-analysis-in-the-twentieth-century-volume-1-the-dawn-of-analysis-pdf (Accessed: 14 October 2022).

MLA 7 Citation

Soames, Scott. Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 1. [edition unavailable]. Princeton University Press, 2009. Web. 14 Oct. 2022.