PART 1
Is Multiculturalism
Bad for Women?
SUSAN MOLLER OKIN
U
NTIL THE past few decades, minority groupsâimmigrants as well as indigenous peoplesâwere typically expected to assimilate into majority cultures. This assimilationist expectation is now often considered oppressive, and many Western countries are seeking to devise new policies that are more responsive to persistent cultural differences. The appropriate policies vary with context: countries such as England, with established churches or state-supported religious education, find it difficult to resist demands to extend state support to minority religious schools; countries such as France, with traditions of strictly secular public education, struggle over whether the clothing required by minority religions may be worn in the public schools. But one issue recurs across all contexts, though it has gone virtually unnoticed in current debate: what should be done when the claims of minority cultures or religions clash with the norm of gender equality that is at least formally endorsed by liberal states (however much they continue to violate it in their practices)?
In the late 1980s, for example, a sharp public controversy erupted in France about whether MagrĂŠbin girls could attend school wearing the traditional Muslim head scarves regarded as proper attire for postpubescent young women. Staunch defenders of secular education lined up with some feminists and far-right nationalists against the practice; much of the Old Left supported the multiculturalist demands for flexibility and respect for diversity, accusing opponents of racism or cultural imperialism. At the very same time, however, the public was virtually silent about a problem of vastly greater importance to many French Arab and African immigrant women: polygamy.
During the 1980s, the French government quietly permitted immigrant men to bring multiple wives into the country, to the point where an estimated 200,000 families in Paris are now polygamous. Any suspicion that official concern over head scarves was motivated by an impulse toward gender equality is belied by the easy adoption of a permissive policy on polygamy, despite the burdens this practice
imposes on women and the warnings disseminated by women from the relevant cultures.
1 On this issue, no politically effective opposition galvanized. But once reporters finally got around to interviewing the wives, they discovered what the government could have learned years earlier: that the women affected by polygamy regarded it as an inescapable and barely tolerable institution in their African countries of origin, and an unbearable imposition in the French context. Overcrowded apartments and the lack of private space for each wife led to immense hostility, resentment, even violence both among the wives and against each otherâs children.
In part because of the strain on the welfare system caused by families with twenty to thirty members, the French government has recently decided to recognize only one wife and to consider all the other marriages annulled. But what will happen to all the other wives and children? Having ignored womenâs views on polygamy for so long, the government now seems to be abdicating its responsibility for the vulnerability that its rash policy has inflicted on women and children.
The French accommodation of polygamy illustrates a deep and growing tension between feminism and multiculturalist concern for protecting cultural diversity. I think weâespecially those of us who consider ourselves politically progressive and opposed to all forms of oppressionâhave been too quick to assume that feminism and multiculturalism are both good things which are easily reconciled. I shall argue instead that there is considerable likelihood of tension between themâmore precisely, between feminism and a multiculturalist commitment to group rights for minority cultures.
A few words to explain the terms and focus of my argument. By
feminism, I mean the belief that women should not be disadvantaged by their sex, that they should be recognized as having human dignity equal to that of men, and that they should have the opportunity to live as fulfilling and as freely chosen lives as men can.
Multiculturalism is harder to pin down, but the particular aspect that concerns me here is the claim, made in the context of basically liberal democracies, that minority cultures or ways of life are not sufficiently protected by the practice of ensuring the individual rights of their
members, and as a consequence these should also be protected through special
group rights or privileges. In the French case, for example, the right to contract polygamous marriages clearly constituted a group right not available to the rest of the population. In other cases, groups have claimed rights to govern themselves, to have guaranteed political representation, or to be exempt from certain generally applicable laws.
Demands for such group rights are growingâfrom indigenous native populations, minority ethnic or religious groups, and formerly colonized peoples (at least when the latter immigrate to the former colonial state). These groups, it is argued, have their own âsocietal culturesâ whichâas Will Kymlicka, the foremost contemporary defender of cultural group rights, saysâprovide âmembers with meaningful ways of life across the full range of human activities, including social, educational, religious, recreational, and economic life, encompassing both public and private spheres.â
2 Because societal cultures play so pervasive and fundamental a role in the lives of their members, and because such cultures are threatened with extinction, minority cultures should be protected by special rights. That, in essence, is the case for group rights.
Some proponents of group rights argue that even cultures that âflout the rights of [their individual members] in a liberal societyâ
3 should be accorded group rights or privileges if their minority status endangers the cultureâs continued existence. Others do not claim that all minority cultural groups should have special rights, but rather that such groupsâeven illiberal ones that violate their individual membersâ rights, requiring them to conform to group beliefs or normsâhave the right to be âleft aloneâ in a liberal society.
4 Both claims seem clearly inconsistent with the basic liberal value of individual freedom, which entails that group rights should not trump the individual rights of its members; thus I will not address the additional problems they present for feminists here.
5 But some defenders of multiculturalism confine their defense of group rights largely to groups that are internally liberal.
6 Even with these restrictions, feministsâeveryone, that is, who endorses the moral equality of men and womenâshould remain skeptical. So I will argue.
GENDER AND CULTURE
Most cultures are suffused with practices and ideologies concerning gender. Suppose, then, that a culture endorses and facilitates the control of men over women in various ways (even if informally, in the private sphere of domestic life). Suppose, too, that there are fairly clear disparities in power between the sexes, such that the more powerful, male members are those who are generally in a position to determine and articulate the groupâs beliefs, practices, and interests. Under such conditions, group rights are potentially, and in many cases actually, antifeminist. They substantially limit the capacities of women and girls of that culture to live with human dignity equal to that of men and boys, and to live as freely chosen lives as they can.
Advocates of group rights for minorities within liberal states have not adequately addressed this simple critique of group rights, for at least two reasons. First, they tend to treat cultural groups as monolithsâto pay more attention to differences between and among groups than to differences within them. Specifically, they accord little or no recognition to the fact that minority cultural groups, like the societies in which they exist (though to a greater or lesser extent), are themselves gendered, with substantial differences in power and advantage between men and women. Second, advocates of group rights pay little or no attention to the private sphere. Some of the most persuasive liberal defenses of group rights urge that individuals need âa culture of their own,â and that only within such a culture can people develop a sense of self-esteem or self-respect, as well as the capacity to decide what kind of life is good for them. But such arguments typically neglect both the different roles that cultural groups impose on their members and the context in which personsâ senses of themselves and their capacities are first formed and in which culture is first transmittedâthe realm of domestic or family life.
When we correct for these deficiencies by paying attention to internal differences and to the private arena, two particularly important connections between culture and gender come into sharp relief, both of which underscore the force of this simple critique of group rights. First, the sphere of personal, sexual, and reproductive
life functions as a central focus of most cultures, a dominant theme in cultural practices and rules. Religious or cultural groups often are particularly concerned with âpersonal lawââthe laws of marriage, divorce, child custody, division and control of family property, and inheritance.
7 As a rule, then, the defense of âcultural practicesâ is likely to have much greater impact on the lives of women and girls than on those of men and boys, since far more of womenâs time and energy goes into preserving and maintaining the personal, familial, and reproductive side of life. Obviously, culture is not only about domestic arrangements, but they do provide a major focus of most contemporary cultures. Home is, after all, where much of culture is practiced, preserved, and transmitted to the young. On the other hand, the distribution of responsibilities and power at home has a major impact on who can participate in and influence the more public parts of the cultural life, where rules and regulations about both public and private life are made. The more a culture requires or expects of women in the domestic sphere, the less opportunity they have of achieving equality with men in either sphere.
The second important connection between culture and gender is that most cultures have as one of their principal aims the control of women by men.
8 Consider, for example, the founding myths of Greek and Roman antiquity, and of Judaism, Christianity, and Islam: they are rife with attempts to justify the control and subordination of women. These myths consist of a combination of denials of womenâs role in reproduction; appropriations by men of the power to reproduce themselves; characterizations of women as overly emotional, untrustworthy, evil, or sexually dangerous; and refusals to acknowledge mothersâ rights over the disposition of their children.
9 Think of Athena, sprung from the head of Zeus, and of Romulus and Remus, reared without a human mother. Or Adam, made by a male God, who then (at least according to one of the two biblical versions of the story) created Eve out of part of Adam. Consider Eve, whose weakness led Adam astray. Think of all those endless âbegatsâ in Genesis, where womenâs primary role in reproduction is completely ignored, or of the textual justifications for polygamy, once practiced in Judaism, still practiced in many parts of the Islamic world and (though illegally) by Mormons in some
parts of the United States. Consider, too, the story of Abraham, a pivotal turning point in the development of monotheism.
10 God commands Abraham to sacrifice âhisâ beloved son. Abraham prepares to do exactly what God asks of him, without even telling, much less asking, Isaacâs mother, Sarah. Abrahamâs absolute obedience to God makes him the central, fundamental model of faith for all three religions.
Although the powerful drive to control womenâand to blame and punish them for menâs difficulty in controlling their own sexual impulsesâhas been softened considerably in the more progressive, reformed versions of Judaism, Christianity, and Islam, it remains strong in their more orthodox or fundamentalist versions. Moreover, it is by no means confined to Western or monotheistic cultures. Many of the worldâs traditions and cultures, including those practiced within formerly conquered or colonized nation-statesâwhich certainly encompasses most of the peoples of Africa, the Middle East, Latin America, and Asiaâare quite distinctly patriarchal. They too have elaborate patterns of socialization, rituals, matrimonial customs, and other cultural practices (including systems of property ownership and control of resources) aimed at bringing womenâs sexuality and reproductive capabilities under menâs control. Many such practices make it virtually impossible for women to choose to live independently of men, to be celibate or lesbian, or to decide not to have children.
Those who practice some of the most controversial of such customsâclitoridectomy, polygamy, the marriage of children or marriages that are otherwise coercedâsometimes explicitly defend them as necessary for controlling women and openly acknowledge that the customs persist at menâs insistence. In an interview with
New York Times reporter Celia Dugger, practitioners of clitoridectomy in CĂ´te dâIvoire and Togo explained that the practice âhelps insure a girlâs virginity before marriage and fidelity afterward by reducing sex to a marital obligation.â As a female exciser said, â[a] womanâs role in life is to care for her children, keep house and cook. If she has not been cut, [she] might think about her own sexual pleasure.â
11 In Egypt, where a law banning female genital cutting was recently overturned by a court, supporters of the practice say it âcurbs a girlâs
sexual appetite and makes her more marriageable.â
12 Moreover, in such societies, many women have no economically viable alternative to marriage.
In polygamous cultures, too, men readily acknowledge that the practice accords with their self-interest and is a means of controlling women. As a French immigrant from Mali said in a recent interview: âWhen my wife is sick and I donât have another, who will care for me? . . . [O]ne wife on her own is trouble. When there are several, they are forced to be polite and well behaved. If they misbehave, you threaten that youâll take another wife.â Women apparently see polygamy very differently. French African immigrant women deny that they like polygamy and say that not only are they given âno choiceâ in the matter, but their female forebears in Africa did not like it either.
13 As for child or otherwise coerced marriage: this practice is clearly a way not only of controlling who the girls or young women marry but also of ensuring that they are virgins at the time of marriage and, often, of enhancing the husbandâs power by creating a significant age difference between husbands and wives.
Consider, too, the practiceâcommon in much of Latin America, rural Southeast Asia and parts of West Africaâof pressuring or even requiring a rape victim to marry the rapist. In many such culturesâincluding fourteen countries in Central and South Americaârapists are legally exonerated if they marry or (in some cases) simply offer to marry their victims. Clearly, rape is not seen in these cultures primarily as a violent assault on the girl or woman herself but rather as a serious injury to her family and its honor. By marrying his victim, the rapist can help restore the familyâs honor and relieve it of a daughter who, as âdamaged goods,â has become unmarriageable. In Peru, this barbaric law was amended for the worse in 1991: the codefendants in a gang rape now are all exonerated if just one of them offers to marry the victim (feminists are fighting to get the law repealed). As a Peruvian taxi driver explained: âMarriage is the right and proper thing to do after a rape. A raped woman is a used item. No one wants her. At least with this law the woman will get a husband.â
14 It is...