Philosophic Pride
eBook - ePub

Philosophic Pride

Stoicism and Political Thought from Lipsius to Rousseau

Christopher Brooke

Share book
  1. 304 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Philosophic Pride

Stoicism and Political Thought from Lipsius to Rousseau

Christopher Brooke

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Philosophic Pride is the first full-scale look at the essential place of Stoicism in the foundations of modern political thought. Spanning the period from Justus Lipsius's Politics in 1589 to Jean-Jacques Rousseau's Emile in 1762, and concentrating on arguments originating from England, France, and the Netherlands, the book considers how political writers of the period engaged with the ideas of the Roman and Greek Stoics that they found in works by Cicero, Seneca, Epictetus, and Marcus Aurelius. Christopher Brooke examines key texts in their historical context, paying special attention to the history of classical scholarship and the historiography of philosophy.Brooke delves into the persisting tension between Stoicism and the tradition of Augustinian anti-Stoic criticism, which held Stoicism to be a philosophy for the proud who denied their fallen condition. Concentrating on arguments in moral psychology surrounding the foundations of human sociability and self-love, Philosophic Pride details how the engagement with Roman Stoicism shaped early modern political philosophy and offers significant new interpretations of Lipsius and Rousseau together with fresh perspectives on the political thought of Hugo Grotius and Thomas Hobbes. Philosophic Pride shows how the legacy of the Stoics played a vital role in European intellectual life in the early modern era.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Philosophic Pride an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Philosophic Pride by Christopher Brooke in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophie & Philosophie politique. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2012
ISBN
9781400842414

CHAPTER ONE

Justus Lipsius and the Post-Machiavellian Prince

In his fine 1991 study of neostoic ideology and the painting of Peter Paul Rubens, the classicist Mark Morford wrote that Justus Lipsius ‘is now little known except to students of Seneca and Tacitus and to intellectual historians of the northern Renaissance’.1 Given the growing number of studies devoted to Lipsius and his various legacies since Morford’s book appeared, we might want to add students of early modern political thought and some scholars of literature to his list. Outside these particular corners of the academy, however, levels of Lipsius consciousness remain fairly low. He returned to the heart of European political life, in a manner of speaking, when the Justus Lipsius Building in Brussels opened in 1995, providing a new home for the European Union’s Council of Ministers. One might have thought it appropriate that such a building be named for a distinguished Belgian political writer who argued against the excesses of patriotism and in support of a European peace based on principles of mutual toleration, and whose books circulated extensively throughout the greater part of the territory of today’s EU. According to an EU press release, however, the building was in fact named for the Brussels street that used to connect rue de la Loi and rue Belliard and had been demolished to make way for its construction.2
Who was Justus Lipsius? He was born in 1547 in Overijse in Brabant.3 He studied at the Jesuit college in Cologne from 1559 and was for a short while, from 1562 to 1564, a novice member of the order. Having obtained a bachelor’s degree in arts, he moved to Louvain in 1564 to study law, though at this time he seems to have concentrated instead on his humanist studies, developing a reputation as an acute Latin philologist and publishing four books of Variae lectiones in 1568. In that year he joined Cardinal Granvelle’s staff and travelled through Italy to Rome, where he studied the Tacitus manuscripts in the Vatican Library. A period of migration followed. Lipsius was back in Louvain in 1570, but he left again in 1571, visiting Liùge, Vienna, and Leipzig before being appointed in 1572 to the chair in history at the university in Jena, a Lutheran foundation. He returned to Cologne to marry the recently widowed Anna van den Calstere in 1573, and in 1574 he published his great edition of Tacitus and left his post at Jena to return to Louvain, where he finally completed his law degree. Moving to a chair at the new Calvinist college in Leiden in 1578, Lipsius there published his two most significant original works, the philosophical dialogue De constantia in two books in 1583 and the six books of Politica in 1589. The publication of the Politica provoked a sharp public exchange in 1590–91 with Dirck Koornhert, who had accused Lipsius of favouring the methods of the Spanish Inquisition and of Machiavellism (‘ille machiavellisat’). In the wake of this controversy, Lipsius left Leiden in 1591, reconverted to Catholicism in Mainz, and took up a chair in ancient history and Latin in Louvain the following year. His great work of this final period was his edition of Seneca, published in 1605; he also compiled two handbooks of Stoic philosophy, the Manuductio, on ethics, and the Physiologia Stoicorum, on physics; there were other works on ancient Rome, especially on its military affairs, and a new book on politics, the Monita et exempla, in 1605. Lipsius died in Louvain in March 1606; legend has it that he rejected the consolation of Stoicism on his deathbed and gestured at a crucifix, insisting ‘haec est vera patientia’.
The scholarship on Justus Lipsius as a moral and political thinker dates above all from the publication in 1914 of LĂ©ontine Zanta’s La renaissance du stoĂŻcisme au XVIe siĂšcle. This book charted the translation and dissemination of classical texts and the increasing use of Stoic tropes, arguments, and values in the writings of moralists of the time, and presented in its second part an anatomy of the main ideas of the Neostoic ‘triumvirate’ of Justus Lipsius, Guillaume du Vair, and Pierre Charron, whose books did much to systematise and popularise this Stoic current in the late sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries. Anthony Levi observed in 1964 that the book ‘was a pioneer work, but its assumptions about the stoicism of the moralists have today sometimes to be questioned’.4 That is true enough, but with a long look back it is the first part of this verdict that resonates the most. Zanta was not the first to argue for the historical and intellectual significance of Lipsius and the other Neostoics. Wilhelm Dilthey had earlier paid considerable attention to them as a part of his explorations of changing conceptions of rationality, the transformation of individual consciousness, and the development of the modern scientific worldview,5 and Fortunat Strowski had considered the sixteenth-century Stoic moralists in the second chapter of his classic 1907 study of Pascal’s intellectual contexts.6 Where Strowski offered a sketch, however, Zanta constructed a far more solid framework for the study of sixteenth-century Stoicizing moral theory in her book, paying attention in particular to the more technical Stoic works of Lipsius such as the Manuductio. She also successfully defended her work at the Sorbonne in May 1914, with La renaissance becoming the first thesis on a philosophical subject by a woman to be accepted by a French university for the degree of docteur d’État. Zanta was a significant feminist: she published her Psychologie du fĂ©minisme in 1922, for example, and campaigned for the rights of professional women in the interwar French press. She was also an inspirational figure for the young Simone de Beauvoir.7
Zanta’s book helped to recover Lipsius the Christian Stoic moralist—the Lipsius above all of De constantia—forging a path along which subsequent scholars of the history of ethics would follow. Lipsius the political theorist—the Lipsius of the Politica—was by contrast comparatively neglected. J. W. Allen’s 1928 study, A History of Political Thought in the Sixteenth Century, for example, contains no mention of Lipsius or of any of the other major Neostoic authors, nor any consideration of the influence or function of ancient Stoicism concerning the political thinking of the period.8 Jason Lewis Saunders’s 1955 book-length study of Lipsius, the first in English, presented a biographical sketch of his writing career and detailed expositions of the main arguments of the Stoic writings on ethics and physics in De constantia, the Manuductio, and the Physiologia Stoicorum, but passed over the Politica and the other explicitly political writings altogether.9 It is not difficult to come up with reasons why it might have been so easy for the Politica to be substantially ignored. First, in comparison with De constantia especially, Politica appears to be a considerably less original work. The bulk of the text is made up of quotations from classical authorities, giving the work something of the feel of a commonplace book. (It was this aspect of the book that provoked Montaigne’s description of it as ‘ce docte et laborieux tissu’, and opinion differs down to the present over whether this was intended as a compliment or not.)10 Second, and in contrast to all three of the works that Saunders examined in his book, for example, Politica does not advertise itself as having anything in particular to do with Stoicism, making it a less attractive object of study for those interested above all in Lipsius as the protagonist in a ‘Stoic revival’. The author most frequently quoted in the Politica, for example, is Tacitus, who was no kind of Stoic; Stoicism itself is unmentioned throughout.
The scholar who did the most to draw attention to Lipsius’s political thought was the historian Gerhard Oestreich, who died in 1978 and whose final book, Neostoicism and the Early Modern State, was published posthumously.11 For Oestreich, Lipsius’s importance was many-sided. His books, in particular De constantia and the Politica, provided the definitive statement of a political ideology that found its inspiration in a number of mostly Latin texts and foregrounded themes of power, self-inspection, discipline, toleration, and moderation. ‘Lipsius proclaimed the modern state, based on order and power, from amid the ruins caused by the religious wars’, Oestreich wrote. ‘The spirit it embodied and its exceedingly practical orientation derived from the Neostoic philosophy of the state, which was itself eminently practical’.12 As well as helping to give shape to this ideology, Lipsius was also a prominent propagandist for it, and Oestreich stressed his role as a popular teacher, especially during his period in Leiden; his seven hundred correspondents, scattered all over Western Europe; and the fact that his books were sixteenth-century bestsellers, going rapidly through many editions and being translated into all the major European languages.13 At the heart of Oestreich’s account lies a reading of the Politica, whose contents are summarised in the third chapter of Neostoicism. His epitome gives particular attention to the fourth book, on actual constitutional practice,14 with its discussions of religious uniformity, the rise and fall of governments, and ‘the troublesome question of prudentia mixta or “reason of state”’,15 as well as to the fifth book, on military affairs, above all to its account of discipline.16 Indeed, Oestreich considered this book central to the interpretation of the Politica, for in his view, ‘The Leiden professor saw military force (vis) as the real foundation of the state.’17
Oestreich’s claims for the historical significance of Lipsius’s project were not small. In his view, the new emphasis on discipline on the part of the writers who contributed to the Netherlands movement played a key role in the military revolution that transformed first European warfare and then the internal organisation of the European states themselves. Prince Maurice of Orange had been one of Lipsius’s students in Leiden in 1583–84, Oestreich observed, and he ‘always referred to Lipsius as his teacher.’18 Neostoicism was credited with being one of the major forces behind the consolidation of absolutist ideology, to the extent that it might be said to mark the moment when the national security state came to supplant the free city republic as the focus of political theorists’ attention and loyalties.19 Max Weber had argued for the importance of a Protestant ethic associated above all with Calvinism for understanding the increasing intensification of processes of rationalisation in early modern Europe that helped to stabilise early capitalist relations of production,20 and Otto Hintze had gone on to suggest that there was an affinity between Calvinism and modern raison d’état arguments.21 Oestreich offered a variation on the theme, suggesting that it might have been Neostoic ideology that had helped to spread an ethic of duty that bordered on asceticism, and that in the context of the early modern absolutist monarchies, furthermore, it made more sense to ascribe significant social and economic effects to this secular ideology than to any religious doctrine.22 Oestreich’s presentation of Lipsius and his interpretation of the political content of Neostoicism has been a very influential one, and his work continues to be cited down to the present (recently, for example, in Charles Taylor’s large book on the history of the possibility of a secular society).23 His position, however, is an increasingly awkward one. In particular, his critics are not persuaded that his argument about Lipsius’s political thought has much to do with Stoicism at all, that his grander historical claims are sound, or that the historiographical tradition within which he was working was free from the taint of National Socialist ideology.
In the introduction to his recent edition and translation of the Politica, Jan Waszink expresses scepticism about the contribution of Stoic philosophy to Lipsius’s argument. In this work, he notes, important Neostoic themes such as the reconciliation of Christian and Stoic doctrine or the desirability of suppressing the emotions do not make any noteworthy appearance; ‘[t]he Neostoic key virtue of Constantia is given no particular prominence’; and Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius are ‘entirely absent’.24 Indeed, Waszink canvasses the mischievous suggestion that Lipsius’s book might reasonably be considered an anti-Stoic argument, for a central claim of Stoic political theory was the identification of what was honourable (honestum) with what was useful (utile), which is one that Lipsius seems to deny. At the start of the famous discussion of ‘mixed prudence’ in 4.13, he asks whether it is ‘allowed that I mix it [prudence] a little, and add a bit of the sediment of deceit?’, and he answers that it is (‘ego puto’), ‘in spite of the disapproval of some Zenos, who only approve that straight road which leads with virtue to honour’ and who ‘do not think it permissible that Reason, given by the...

Table of contents