CHAPTER ONE
Justus Lipsius and the Post-Machiavellian Prince
In his fine 1991 study of neostoic ideology and the painting of Peter Paul Rubens, the classicist Mark Morford wrote that Justus Lipsius âis now little known except to students of Seneca and Tacitus and to intellectual historians of the northern Renaissanceâ.
1 Given the growing number of studies devoted to Lipsius and his various legacies since Morfordâs book appeared, we might want to add students of early modern political thought and some scholars of literature to his list. Outside these particular corners of the academy, however, levels of Lipsius consciousness remain fairly low. He returned to the heart of European political life, in a manner of speaking, when the Justus Lipsius Building in Brussels opened in 1995, providing a new home for the European Unionâs Council of Ministers. One might have thought it appropriate that such a building be named for a distinguished Belgian political writer who argued against the excesses of patriotism and in support of a European peace based on principles of mutual toleration, and whose books circulated extensively throughout the greater part of the territory of todayâs EU. According to an EU press release, however, the building was in fact named for the Brussels street that used to connect rue de la Loi and rue Belliard and had been demolished to make way for its construction.
2 Who was Justus Lipsius? He was born in 1547 in Overijse in Brabant.
3 He studied at the Jesuit college in Cologne from 1559 and was for a short while, from 1562 to 1564, a novice member of the order. Having obtained a bachelorâs degree in arts, he moved to Louvain in 1564 to study law, though at this time he seems to have concentrated instead on his humanist studies, developing a reputation as an acute Latin philologist and publishing four books of
Variae lectiones in 1568. In that year he joined Cardinal Granvelleâs staff and travelled through Italy to Rome, where he studied the Tacitus manuscripts in the Vatican Library. A period of migration followed. Lipsius was back in Louvain in 1570, but he left again in 1571, visiting LiĂšge, Vienna, and Leipzig before being appointed in 1572 to the chair in history at the university in Jena, a Lutheran foundation. He returned to Cologne to marry the recently widowed Anna van den Calstere in 1573, and in 1574 he published his great edition of Tacitus and left his post at Jena to return to Louvain, where he finally completed
his law degree. Moving to a chair at the new Calvinist college in Leiden in 1578, Lipsius there published his two most significant original works, the philosophical dialogue
De constantia in two books in 1583 and the six books of
Politica in 1589. The publication of the
Politica provoked a sharp public exchange in 1590â91 with Dirck Koornhert, who had accused Lipsius of favouring the methods of the Spanish Inquisition and of Machiavellism (â
ille machiavellisatâ). In the wake of this controversy, Lipsius left Leiden in 1591, reconverted to Catholicism in Mainz, and took up a chair in ancient history and Latin in Louvain the following year. His great work of this final period was his edition of Seneca, published in 1605; he also compiled two handbooks of Stoic philosophy, the
Manuductio, on ethics, and the
Physiologia Stoicorum, on physics; there were other works on ancient Rome, especially on its military affairs, and a new book on politics, the
Monita et exempla, in 1605. Lipsius died in Louvain in March 1606; legend has it that he rejected the consolation of Stoicism on his deathbed and gestured at a crucifix, insisting âhaec est vera patientiaâ.
The scholarship on Justus Lipsius as a moral and political thinker dates above all from the publication in 1914 of LĂ©ontine Zantaâs
La renaissance du stoĂŻcisme au XVIe siĂšcle. This book charted the translation and dissemination of classical texts and the increasing use of Stoic tropes, arguments, and values in the writings of moralists of the time, and presented in its second part an anatomy of the main ideas of the Neostoic âtriumvirateâ of Justus Lipsius, Guillaume du Vair, and Pierre Charron, whose books did much to systematise and popularise this Stoic current in the late sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries. Anthony Levi observed in 1964 that the book âwas a pioneer work, but its assumptions about the stoicism of the moralists have today sometimes to be questionedâ.
4 That is true enough, but with a long look back it is the first part of this verdict that resonates the most. Zanta was not the first to argue for the historical and intellectual significance of Lipsius and the other Neostoics. Wilhelm Dilthey had earlier paid considerable attention to them as a part of his explorations of changing conceptions of rationality, the transformation of individual consciousness, and the development of the modern scientific worldview,
5 and Fortunat Strowski had considered the sixteenth-century Stoic moralists in the second chapter of his classic 1907 study of Pascalâs intellectual contexts.
6 Where Strowski offered a sketch, however, Zanta constructed a far more solid framework for the study of sixteenth-century Stoicizing moral theory in her book, paying attention in particular to the more technical Stoic works of Lipsius such as the
Manuductio. She also successfully defended her work at the Sorbonne in May 1914, with
La renaissance becoming the first thesis on a philosophical subject by a woman to be accepted by a French university for the degree of
docteur dâĂtat. Zanta was a significant feminist: she published her
Psychologie du féminisme in 1922, for example, and campaigned for the rights of professional women in the interwar French press. She was also an inspirational figure for the young Simone de Beauvoir.
7 Zantaâs book helped to recover Lipsius the Christian Stoic moralistâthe Lipsius above all of
De constantiaâforging a path along which subsequent scholars of the history of ethics would follow. Lipsius the political theoristâthe Lipsius of the
Politicaâwas by contrast comparatively neglected. J. W. Allenâs 1928 study,
A History of Political Thought in the Sixteenth Century, for example, contains no mention of Lipsius or of any of the other major Neostoic authors, nor any consideration of the influence or function of ancient Stoicism concerning the political thinking of the period.
8 Jason Lewis Saundersâs 1955 book-length study of Lipsius, the first in English, presented a biographical sketch of his writing career and detailed expositions of the main arguments of the Stoic writings on ethics and physics in
De constantia, the
Manuductio, and the
Physiologia Stoicorum, but passed over the
Politica and the other explicitly political writings altogether.
9 It is not difficult to come up with reasons why it might have been so easy for the
Politica to be substantially ignored. First, in comparison with
De constantia especially,
Politica appears to be a considerably less original work. The bulk of the text is made up of quotations from classical authorities, giving the work something of the feel of a commonplace book. (It was this aspect of the book that provoked Montaigneâs description of it as âce docte et laborieux tissuâ, and opinion differs down to the present over whether this was intended as a compliment or not.)
10 Second, and in contrast to all three of the works that Saunders examined in his book, for example,
Politica does not advertise itself as having anything in particular to do with Stoicism, making it a less attractive object of study for those interested above all in Lipsius as the protagonist in a âStoic revivalâ. The author most frequently quoted in the
Politica, for example, is Tacitus, who was no kind of Stoic; Stoicism itself is unmentioned throughout.
The scholar who did the most to draw attention to Lipsiusâs political thought was the historian Gerhard Oestreich, who died in 1978 and whose final book,
Neostoicism and the Early Modern State, was published posthumously.
11 For Oestreich, Lipsiusâs importance was many-sided. His books, in particular
De constantia and the
Politica, provided the definitive statement of a political ideology that found its inspiration in a number of mostly Latin texts and foregrounded themes of power, self-inspection, discipline, toleration, and moderation. âLipsius proclaimed the modern state, based on order and power, from amid the ruins caused by the religious warsâ, Oestreich wrote. âThe spirit it embodied and its exceedingly practical orientation derived from the Neostoic philosophy of
the state, which was itself eminently practicalâ.
12 As well as helping to give shape to this ideology, Lipsius was also a prominent propagandist for it, and Oestreich stressed his role as a popular teacher, especially during his period in Leiden; his seven hundred correspondents, scattered all over Western Europe; and the fact that his books were sixteenth-century bestsellers, going rapidly through many editions and being translated into all the major European languages.
13 At the heart of Oestreichâs account lies a reading of the
Politica, whose contents are summarised in the third chapter of
Neostoicism. His epitome gives particular attention to the fourth book, on actual constitutional practice,
14 with its discussions of religious uniformity, the rise and fall of governments, and âthe troublesome question of
prudentia mixta or âreason of stateââ,
15 as well as to the fifth book, on military affairs, above all to its account of discipline.
16 Indeed, Oestreich considered this book central to the interpretation of the
Politica, for in his view, âThe Leiden professor saw military force (
vis) as the real foundation of the state.â
17 Oestreichâs claims for the historical significance of Lipsiusâs project were not small. In his view, the new emphasis on discipline on the part of the writers who contributed to the Netherlands movement played a key role in the military revolution that transformed first European warfare and then the internal organisation of the European states themselves. Prince Maurice of Orange had been one of Lipsiusâs students in Leiden in 1583â84, Oestreich observed, and he âalways referred to Lipsius as his teacher.â
18 Neostoicism was credited with being one of the major forces behind the consolidation of absolutist ideology, to the extent that it might be said to mark the moment when the national security state came to supplant the free city republic as the focus of political theoristsâ attention and loyalties.
19 Max Weber had argued for the importance of a Protestant ethic associated above all with Calvinism for understanding the increasing intensification of processes of rationalisation in early modern Europe that helped to stabilise early capitalist relations of production,
20 and Otto Hintze had gone on to suggest that there was an affinity between Calvinism and modern
raison dâĂ©tat arguments.
21 Oestreich offered a variation on the theme, suggesting that it might have been Neostoic ideology that had helped to spread an ethic of duty that bordered on asceticism, and that in the context of the early modern absolutist monarchies, furthermore, it made more sense to ascribe significant social and economic effects to this secular ideology than to any religious doctrine.
22 Oestreichâs presentation of Lipsius and his interpretation of the political content of Neostoicism has been a very influential one, and his work continues to be cited down to the present (recently, for example, in Charles Taylorâs large book on the history of the possibility of a secular society).
23 His position, however, is an increasingly awkward one. In particular, his critics are not
persuaded that his argument about Lipsiusâs political thought has much to do with Stoicism at all, that his grander historical claims are sound, or that the historiographical tradition within which he was working was free from the taint of National Socialist ideology.
In the introduction to his recent edition and translation of the
Politica, Jan Waszink expresses scepticism about the contribution of Stoic philosophy to Lipsiusâs argument. In this work, he notes, important Neostoic themes such as the reconciliation of Christian and Stoic doctrine or the desirability of suppressing the emotions do not make any noteworthy appearance; â[t]he Neostoic key virtue of
Constantia is given no particular prominenceâ; and Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius are âentirely absentâ.
24 Indeed, Waszink canvasses the mischievous suggestion that Lipsiusâs book might reasonably be considered an anti-Stoic argument, for a central claim of Stoic political theory was the identification of what was honourable (
honestum) with what was useful (
utile), which is one that Lipsius seems to deny. At the start of the famous discussion of âmixed prudenceâ in 4.13, he asks whether it is âallowed that I mix it [prudence] a little, and add a bit of the sediment of deceit?â, and he answers that it is (â
ego putoâ), âin spite of the disapproval of some Zenos, who
only approve that straight road which leads with virtue to honourâ and who âdo not think it permissible that
Reason, given by the...