Philippa Foot's Moral Thought
eBook - ePub

Philippa Foot's Moral Thought

John Hacker-Wright

Share book
  1. 176 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Philippa Foot's Moral Thought

John Hacker-Wright

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Philippa Foot (1920-2010) is widely regarded as one of the most important Anglophone moral philosophers of the 20th century. She pioneered a distinctive approach to philosophical treatment of ethics using the tools of analytic philosophy. She defended the objectivity of moral judgment and took controversial positions on abortion and euthanasia. She was also a leading figure behind the revival of Aristotelian virtue ethics in contemporary philosophy. This book represents the first comprehensive and accessible introduction to Foot's work. It offers a complete chronological and thematic overview, emphasising the role Foot played in the development of contemporary virtue ethics. It situates her thought in the context of the historical development of analytic moral philosophy and discusses the various objections to her views. Foot's writings take the form of essays that take up small problems within moral philosophy. Yet John Hacker-Wright argues that there is nevertheless a coherent, systematic moral perspective throughout Foot's work that she does not make fully explicit. This is the ideal introduction for students seeking a synthetic grasp of Foot's moral vision.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Philippa Foot's Moral Thought an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Philippa Foot's Moral Thought by John Hacker-Wright in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Ethics & Moral Philosophy. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2013
ISBN
9781441157386
CHAPTER ONE
Naturalism and analytic moral philosophy from Moore to Hare
“Looking back . . . one may be surprised and a little sad, that this particular conflict, about ‘fact and value’, has occupied so much of our time. We seem to have rushed on to the field without waiting to map the territory supposedly in dispute, ready to die for some thesis about commendation or approval, about pro-attitudes or evaluation before anyone had done much detailed work on the specific, and very different, concepts involved.” (TE 12)
In this chapter, I will discuss the philosophical context of Philippa Foot’s early writings. In her early work, she argues that moral judgments characterize persons or actions as good, bad, right, or wrong in view of the impact of the person’s dispositions or actions on human well-being. In taking this approach, Foot advocates a form of naturalism, which is the view that moral judgments describe facts about the world that we observe through our senses. In Foot’s view, moral judgments are a distinctive class of judgments because of their subject matter, and that subject matter is the world described by the natural sciences. Foot’s naturalism conflicts with the view that was dominant at the time—noncogntivism. For noncognitivists, moral judgments are distinguished from other judgments, not by their subject matter, but because they stand in an essential connection to attitudes of approval or disapproval and in that they are used in distinctive ways, for example, to bring about similar attitudes in others. These views, for which I will use the standard name “noncognitivism,” in turn emerged from a response to the moral philosophy of G. E. Moore. Moore argued stridently against all forms of naturalism. Yet, like Foot, he thought that moral judgments are about a distinct subject matter. For Moore, moral judgments are about what will bring about the most good, using the word “good” in a distinctive sense. As Moore is often read, “good” in this special sense designates a nonnatural property belonging to a Platonic realm that, though, separate from the natural world, still somehow pertains to whatever we call “good.” As we will see, although Moore’s argument against naturalism was widely accepted by philosophers in the early to mid-twentieth century, his non-naturalism was seen as abhorrent because it invoked a mysterious non-natural property standing in an equally mysterious relation to the natural world.1 Noncognitivism is an attempt to avoid the alleged problems of naturalism without the supposed mysteries of Moore’s non-naturalism.
Moore: Analysis against naturalism
Foot claims that G. E. Moore’s moral philosophy set the stage for her early work (TE 1). Indeed, Moore’s 1903 Principia Ethica is widely viewed as the starting point for all analytic moral philosophy.2 Moore’s Principia is consequential for all subsequent analytic moral philosophy in two ways. First, methodologically, Moore establishes the possibility of treating questions of metaethics independently of normative issues.3 Much moral philosophy through the 50 years after Principia appeared focuses on metaethics—specifically on the question of the relation of facts and value. This agenda is not only the result of Moore’s methodological innovation of separating metaethical issues from normative ethics, but also reflects the influence of his arguments within metaethics. Second, Moore’s moral philosophy is consequential in that he made an argument against naturalism in ethics that many moral philosophers regard as conclusive. As we will see in what follows, Foot’s moral philosophy is influenced by both of these aspects of Moore’s views.
Moral philosophy before Moore had certainly offered views on metaethical issues; yet, Moore’s approach to moral philosophy is pioneering in that it treats questions concerning the meaning of “good” separately from questions about which things are good. By separating the questions “What does ‘good’ mean?” and “Which things are good?” Moore launched analytic moral philosophy and, for better or worse, split the enterprise of moral philosophy into two sub-disciplines. As we will see, the separation of metaethics and normative ethics leads some to believe that metaethics could be pursued with neutrality toward the various values one might hold, and because of this apparent neutrality, some philosophers take metaethics to be a more scientific enterprise than normative ethics. For Moore, unlike those influenced by him, the task of figuring out the meaning of “good” was “of the last [i.e., highest] importance” because failure to sort out such matters had been the “cause of the acceptance of false principles . . .”4 For him, then, metaethics is no neutral theoretical science, but is itself an endeavor with practical consequences.
In Moore’s view, moral philosophers before him had overlooked a crucial question. While treating the question “Which types of conduct are good?” they had overlooked the question of the meaning of the word “good” in general. Hence, they tended to generalize, from the meaning of the word in the context of “good conduct” to all contexts, with disastrous results. Without asking what “good” means generally, they identified “good” with one of the salient properties of good conduct, for example, producing pleasure. Moore thinks that this is analogous to the mistake one makes when identifying the meaning of “yellow” with reflecting light waves of a certain wavelength.5 For though it may well be that all yellow things reflect light of certain wavelengths, that is not what “yellow” means. Likewise, though all good actions may produce pleasure, “producing pleasure” is not the meaning of “good.” Moore therefore proposes to ask—what is the meaning of the word “good” itself?
His answer to this question is—“good” cannot be defined. By this, Moore means to say that that “good” cannot be shown to be synonymous with concepts that identify other properties, either natural or supernatural. “Good,” like “yellow,” is a simple notion.6 This claim certainly suggests that Moore identifies “good” as a distinctive non-natural property, but one must determine first how one establishes the sweeping negative conclusion that no definition of “good” is adequate. To establish this conclusion, he uses what is now called the “open question argument.” This argument points out the difference between asking “That may be pleasant, but is it pleasant?’ which is nonsense, and “That may be pleasant, but it is good?’ which is clearly meaningful. One who defines “good” as “pleasant” commits himself to viewing these concepts as substitutable. Yet, the open question argument shows that they are not substitutable. The two questions just quoted differ in meaning. With the open question argument, then, Moore believes he has found a way to reject any proposed definition of the good, whether it invokes natural or supernatural properties. For one who identifies goodness with preserving the survival of the species, Moore can point out that it makes sense to ask of any species-preserving action, “That may preserve the species, but is it good?’ Likewise, for one who identifies goodness with conforming to the will of God, Moore says that it makes sense to ask of any case, “That may be an act in conformity with the will of God, but is it good?” The answer to one of these questions may always be “yes, it is good,” so that being species-preserving or conforming to God’s will is a reliable method of tracking what is good, but Moore’s point stands, he thinks, by the mere fact that these questions are meaningful. They show that “good” means something different from the names of these qualities.
Anyone who defines “good” commits what Moore misleadingly calls the “naturalistic fallacy.” This name is misleading in two ways—first, even those who define “good” in supernatural terms commit the naturalistic fallacy, so it is not truly a naturalistic fallacy. Second, it is not, strictly speaking, a fallacy, as William Frankena showed in a justly famous paper. The perception of the openness of a question on any given run at the open question argument depends on a prior conviction that there are two distinct properties rather than one. In other words, anyone who is fully convinced that “good” means “producing pleasure” will find the question “That may be pleasant, but is it good?” to be nonsensical. Hence, the argument begs the question. There is only an error—a fallacy if you like—if two distinct properties are conflated, but that is precisely what is at issue. Yet, many readers of Moore share his conviction that the questions are indeed open. Further, as Stephen Darwall has pointed out, the apparent openness of the question may stem not so much from the necessary falsehood of any attempt at defining the good, but from the fact that goodness has a connection with action, which the proposed definitions do not have. Because we are self-reflective agents, Darwall argues, we can stand back and examine any proposed value; we can ask, ought we to value that?7 And this ability gives the open question argument its force. Although Frankena is correct that the naturalistic fallacy is not a fallacy, this is compatible with Darwall’s point that the open question argument has some force against naturalism. Still, it should be noted that in the 36 years between the publication of Principia Ethica and Frankena’s article, Moore’s argument against naturalism was widely perceived as knock-down.
As mentioned above, Moore appears to commit himself to the view that “good,” in the sense that is at issue in moral judgments, refers to a non-natural property. This property is not perceivable by the senses or by its causal effects on the natural world; instead, it would be detected by intellectual intuition. Indeed, this is the interpretation of Moore that Foot adopts (TE 2). To many philosophers following Moore, this view involves two objectionable claims. First, the idea that there are some properties that are not part of the natural world is at odds with the prevailing empiricist epistemology. After all, to say that there is a property apart from the natural world is to say that there is something that does not have any causal interactions with the natural world, and so could not be understood in terms of empirically funded scientific laws. Second, the appeal to intuition seems to ignore the fact that people have different intuitions about what is good. Admitting those disagreements, it is not clear that there could be a method for resolving moral disputes rationally. Parties to a disagreement would seem to be left with thumping their chests and appealing to their separate intuitions.
Although this damning assessment of Moore is widely shared, it is not clear that it is based on a charitable interpretation of Moore’s claims. As Robert Shaver argues, it is possible to read Moore as denying that goodness is a natural concept, but not denying that it is a natural property.8 That is, the concept of goodness describes a feature of the natural world that is not accessible to the natural sciences. Goodness cannot be analyzed in terms of any one natural property, according to Moore, but that does not mean that goodness is not natural. This interpretation of Moore’s view turns on distinguishing an analytic connection between goodness and a natural property, on the one hand, and a constitutive connection between goodness and natural properties, on the other hand. In this view, any natural property constitutive of goodness in a given case may not always be sufficient to make something good, and such a property may not be the only property that makes something good. Hence, in Shaver’s interpretation, non-naturalism rejects the idea that moral matters can be settled scientifically, but does not posit a property or class of properties that is metaphysically irreconcilable with a commitment to scientific naturalism.
As for the epistemological problems with Moore’s view, Shaver argues that although Moore leaves himself open to these charges, these problems are not inherent to Moore’s position. The non-naturalist can appeal to precisely the same justifications that naturalists appeal to—most importantly, systematizing common sense moral judgments.9 That is, the non-naturalist’s appeals to intuition are not necessarily infallible, and for any intuitively plausible instance of something that is deemed good, we can ask whether that claim can be squared with other intuitions about what is good. Overall, then, Moore’s non-naturalism is probably more defensible than has been generally acknowledged by those who rejected it, including Foot.
Ayer and Stevenson: Emotivism
In the widely received version of Moore’s views, goodness is a property of things, albeit a property of a special kind. It is like “yellow” in being simple and indefinable. Yet, unlike yellow, it is not accessible through our senses. For those who find Moore’s open question argument compelling, but who cannot accept the implications of his non-naturalism, the only solution appears to be this alternative response—to deny that goodness names any sort of property at all. They propose that we should seek to explain moral judgments by identifying a characteristic function they perform, rather than a specific class of property that they designate. Much moral philosophy understands moral judgments to have a descriptive function. In such a view, some moral judgments describe a thing as featuring the property of goodness. Yet, clearly not all meaningful language describes the world; for example, we use language to express feelings (e.g., “How wonderful!”) and to command (e.g., “Open the door!”). These other functions of language do not ascribe properties. In the former case, the words express a positive feeling or attitude toward something. Similarly, the latter does not ascribe a property, but rather, commands someone to do something. By exploiting these disparate functions of language, some moral philosophers hope to avoid problems with descriptive theories of moral judgment, such as the difficulties with Moore’s view under its standard interpretation.
For these moral philosophers, working around 30 years after Moore’s Principia, moral language serves a purpose that combines an expressive and a commanding function. A. J. Ayer’s 1936 Language, Truth and Logic contained an early, though brief exposition of this view of moral judgments. He writes:
. . . if I say to someone, ‘You acted wrongly in stealing that money,’ I am not stating anything more than if I had simply said, ‘You stole that money.’ In adding that this action is wrong I am not making any further statement about it. I am simply evincing my moral disapproval of it.10
We see in this passage that there is, in Ayer’s view, a descriptive component to a moral judgment (in this case—“you stole the money”). However, such a descriptive statement is clearly not a moral judgment. What distinguishes a moral judgment from an ordinary descriptive statement is the expression of an attitude toward the descriptive content. Further, at least some moral judgments convey commands. According to Ayer, the sentence, “It is your duty to tell the truth” is equivalent to “Tell the truth!”11 The view expounded in Ayer’s treatise came to be known as emotivism because it defined moral judgments in terms of a function of expressing feelings or attitudes. Note that the moral language does not describe feelings that the speaker has; it expresses them. Contrast—“I approve of x” with “hooray for x!” The former describes my attitude; the latter expresses it.
C. L. Stevenson, in his 1944 Ethics and Language and a number of papers that appeared between 1937 and 1962, developed the idea in Ayer’s brief discussion of emotivism into a complete metaethical theory. For Stevenson, moral terms are used in two central ways. In the first use, terms like “good” are used to say “I approve of x. Do so as well.” Stevenson is careful to point out that this translation of “good” is at best crude, and for reasons to be discussed, he came to think of all such translations as seriously misleading.12 Nevertheless, the translation captures, according to Stevenson, something of what he calls the emotive meaning of moral terms, which he defines as, “the power that the word acquires, on account of its history in emotional situations, to evoke or directly express attitudes, as distinct from describing or designating them.”13 So, in Stevenson’s view, “good” is, in part, supposed to express my positive attitude toward something. Unfortunately, “I approve of x” does not quite capture that. Instead, it expresses my belief that I have a positive attitude toward something, and thus the two claims must have quite a different meaning, as Stevenson later came to realize. After all, “I approve of x” is a descriptive claim about my psychology, and there is a specific type of evidence that would support or undermine that claim. This is quite unlike an utterance that actually expresses my approval of x, such as “Hooray for x!” Since that exclamation is purely expressive, we cannot gather evidence for or against it. For utterances that express attitudes, the whole idea of evidence seems out of place. Likewise, the second part of the translation, “do so as well,” suggests that saying “x is good” has an imperatival function, but Stevenson was wary of this claim even as he stated it. After all, an actual command to adopt an attitude is likely to backfire. Something subtler is going on with “good,” as Stevenson readily admitted. To say that something is good, then, suggests to another that she adopt the speaker’s positive attitude as well, and it is to exert a causal, rather than rational effect on its hearer. In exuding my posi...

Table of contents