Medieval Philosophy
eBook - ePub

Medieval Philosophy

A Beginner's Guide

Sharon M. Kaye

Share book
  1. 208 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Medieval Philosophy

A Beginner's Guide

Sharon M. Kaye

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

An engaging and authoritative introduction to this hugely influential era in the history of philosophy. Why do good things happen to bad people? Can we prove whether God exists? What is the difference between right and wrong? Medieval Philosophers were centrally concerned with such questions: questions which are as relevant today as a thousand years ago when the likes of Anselm and Aquinas sought to resolve them. In this fast-paced, enlightening guide, Sharon M. Kaye takes us on a whistle-stop tour of medieval philosophy, revealing the debt it owes to Aristotle and Plato, and showing how medieval thought is still inspiring philosophers and thinkers today. With new translations of numerous key extracts, Kaye directly introduces the reader to the philosophers' writings and the criticisms levied against them. Including helpful textboxes throughout the book detailing key thinkers, this is an entertaining and comprehensive primer for students and general readers alike.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Medieval Philosophy an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Medieval Philosophy by Sharon M. Kaye in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Filosofía & Filosofía medieval y renacentista. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

1

The ancient legacy

The unexamined life is not worth living.
Socrates
Due to their divergent philosophies, Plato and Aristotle launched opposing ways of thinking about the world that were at odds throughout the middle ages. Although some philosophers maintained that the ideas of the two great ancient philosophers could ultimately be harmonised, there was no widespread agreement about how this could be accomplished. The conflict between Plato and Aristotle actually proved to be very fruitful, however, because it pushed each side to make the best arguments possible.
Argumentation is the way philosophy progresses and logic is the backbone of argumentation. In order to understand what our medieval authors were trying to accomplish we will need to be able to dissect the structure of their reasoning. We therefore begin this chapter with a survey of the basic principles of logic that Plato, Aristotle, and their successors bequeathed to the middle ages.
The Socratic method
The word ‘logic’ comes from the Greek word ‘logos’ meaning reason. We use the same word at the end of our scientific disciplines, such as ‘biology’ and ‘psychology’ to mean ‘the systematic study of —.’ Logic is systematic study. It stipulates the rules of thought itself. Logic started in ancient Greece and became a sophisticated tool in the hands of medieval philosophers.
SOCRATES c. 470–399 BC
Socrates is known as the founder of Western philosophy.
Although Socrates was a sculptor by trade, he preferred to spend his time hanging around the public square in Athens and engaging passers-by in conversation. For example, Socrates might try to provoke a lawyer into a debate about the nature of justice. Because he was good at arguing and had a lot of interesting ideas, Socrates became known as a ‘philosopher’ from the Greek words for ‘love of wisdom.’ He attracted a following of fans.
Socrates also made a lot of enemies, however, by questioning authority and challenging the status quo. Eventually he was tried, convicted, and executed for impiety and corrupting the youth.
Socrates is the first on record to develop and employ a method of systematic study. It is called the ‘elenchus,’ meaning cross-examination. Although Socrates did not write any books, his student Plato wrote many books about him. Appropriately enough, the elenchus first appears in a work called The Apology, in which Plato describes a court trial at which Socrates had to defend his own reputation.
During the trial, Socrates announces that God revealed to him that he is the wisest among men. Admitting that he himself did not at first believe the revelation, he proceeds to show how, and in what sense, he learned it to be true.
MY DEFENCE
After long consideration, I finally thought of a method of testing the question. I reflected that if I could find someone wiser than myself, then I might go to God with a refutation in my hand. I would say to God: ‘You said that I was the wisest, but here is someone who is wiser than I am!’
Accordingly, I went to a man who had a reputation for wisdom and the result was as follows: When I began to talk with him, it became evident that his supposed ‘wisdom’ consisted in the fact that he thought himself to be wise. When I tried to explain that thinking you are wise is not the same as being wise he grew to hate me. So I left him, saying to myself as I went away: ‘Well, even though neither of us is wise, I’m better off than he is. For he claims to know things that he doesn’t really know; whereas I neither know nor think that I know. In this way, I seem to have a slight advantage over him.’
Then I went to another man who had even higher philosophical pretensions and my conclusion was exactly the same. I made another enemy of him, and of many others besides him, as I went from one to another searching for a wise man.
The truth I learned, O people of Athens, is this: only God is wise. God’s revelation to me was meant to be humbling. He was using me as an illustration, as if to say: ‘the wisest person is the one who, like Socrates, knows that his “wisdom” is in truth worth nothing.’
As demonstrated in this passage, the elenchus is a powerful way to refute your opponent. It is therefore useful, not just in court, but in any philosophical debate.
We can appreciate the structure of the argument more clearly if we rewrite it in schematic form as follows:
To Prove: Socrates is the wisest person.
1. Suppose Socrates is not the wisest person.
2. If Socrates is not the wisest person, then other people must be wiser.
3. All the other people claim to know things they don’t really know.
4. It would be absurd for a wise person to claim to know things he or she doesn’t really know.
5. Therefore, Socrates is the wisest person.
Notice that if you accept steps (1) through (4), then you can’t deny step (5). In the middle ages, this method of argumentation came to be called ‘reductio ad absurdum,’ which is Latin for ‘reduction to an absurdity.’ It is still widely used today. The goal is not to show that your opponent is silly or laughable, but rather to show that his view implies something that cannot possibly be true. In philosophy, the word ‘absurdity’ refers to an impossibility or contradiction.
Validity
Although Socrates typically preferred to use the elenchus method in his arguments, Plato’s student Aristotle realized that there are a number of other equally compelling ways to make one’s case. In the following passage from a work called Prior Analytics, Aristotle develops a general criterion for classifying and evaluating different kinds of arguments.
LOGIC BASICS
A ‘premise’ is a statement affirming or denying one thing with respect to another. It must be universal, particular, or indefinite. By ‘universal’ I mean the statement that something belongs to all or none of something else; by ‘particular’ I mean the statement that something belongs to some, or not to some, or not to all of something else.
A ‘syllogism’ is an argument in which, certain things being stated (the premises), something other than what is stated (the conclusion) follows of necessity from their being so. That is, the premises produce the conclusion: no further term is required from without in order to make the conclusion necessary.
First, take a ‘universal negative’ premise using the terms A and B. If no B is A, neither can any A be B. For if some A (say C) were B, it would not be true that no B is A; for C is a B.
Next, consider a “universal positive.” If every B is A, then some A is B. If no A were B, then no B could be A. But we assumed that every B is A.
Now take a ‘particular positive’ syllogism with the terms A and B. If some B is A, then some of the As must be B. If none were, then no B would be A.
Finally, if some B is not A, then there is no necessity that some of the As should not be B; e.g. let B stand for animal and A for human being. Not every animal is a human being; but every human being is an animal. This is a ‘particular negative’ syllogism.
In this groundbreaking exposition Aristotle defines the crucial concept of ‘syllogism,’ which medieval philosophers later called ‘deductive validity,’ from the Latin verbs deducere, meaning ‘to lead down,’ and valere, meaning ‘to be strong or successful.’ The conclusion of a deductively valid argument follows from its premises with necessity.
The necessity of a deductively valid inference is evident in the four types of arguments Aristotle discusses. We should examine them in closer detail.
1. Universal Negative
No apple (A) is a banana (B).
This sentence says that the set of apples does not intersect with the set of bananas.
As the diagram shows, the sentence clearly supports the further inference Aristotle draws, that if no A is B, then no B is A.
2. Universal Positive
Every bug (B) is an annoyance (A).
This sentence says that the set of bugs is a subset of the set of annoyances.
As the diagram shows, the sentence clearly supports the further inference Aristotle draws, that if every B is an A, then some A is a B.
3. Particular Positive
Some boy (B) is an African (A).
This sentence says that at least one boy is a member of the set of Africans.
We don’t know from the sentence whether B intersects with A or is a subset of A. These two possibilities are represented with dotted circles on the diagram. All we know for sure, as Aristotle infers, is that if some B is A, then some A must be B.
4. Particular Negative
Some animal (B) is not a human being (A).
This sentence says that the set of animals is not a subset of the set of human beings.
As Aristotle notes, the sentence does not support the inference that some of the As are not Bs. As the dotted circles on the diagram show, we can’t tell from the sentence whether A is a subset of B, or whether it intersects, or whether it does not intersect at all.
This failure of inference makes a crucial point. When Aristotle defines ‘syllogism’ in the above passage he says that the premises must produce the conclusion in such a way that ‘no further term is required from without in order to make the conclusion necessary.’ Obviously, we all know that the set of human beings is a subset of the set of animals. But logic does not allow us to import information from the outside to arrive at a conclusion. This would be like saying 2 + 2 = 5 because we can always add a 1 from somewhere ...

Table of contents