Wittgenstein
eBook - ePub

Wittgenstein

Meaning and Mind (Volume 3 of an Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations), Part 1: Essays

P. M. S. Hacker

  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Wittgenstein

Meaning and Mind (Volume 3 of an Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations), Part 1: Essays

P. M. S. Hacker

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Wittgenstein: Meaning and Mind is the third volume of a four-volume analytical commentary on Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations, consisting of two parts. Part 1 is a sequence of fifteen essays that examine in detail all the major topics discussed in Philosophical Investigations §§243-427. These include the private language arguments, privacy, private ostensive definition, the nature of the mind, the inner and the outer, behaviour and behaviourism, thought, imagination, the self, consciousness, and criteria. Published in 1990 to widespread acclaim as a scholarly tour de force, the first edition of this volume of essays provides a comprehensive survey of these themes, the history of their treatment in early modern and modern philosophy, the development of Wittgenstein's ideas on these subjects from 1929 onwards, and an elaborate analysis of his definitive arguments in the Investigations.

The new second edition has been thoroughly revised by the author and features four new essays. These include a survey of the evolution of the private language arguments in Wittgenstein's oeuvre and their role within the developing argument of the Investigations, a comprehensive essay on private ownership of experience and its pitfalls, a detailed examination and defence of Wittgenstein's repudiation of subjective knowledge of one's experience, and an overview of the achievement and importance of the private language arguments. Revised essays examine new objections to Wittgenstein's arguments – which are found wanting– and incorporate new materials from the Nachlass that were not known to exist in 1990. All references have been adjusted to the revised fourth edition of the Investigations, but previous pagination in the first and second editions has been retained in parentheses.

These revisions bring the book up to the high standard of the extensively revised editions of Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning (Blackwell, 2005) and Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar and Necessity (Wiley Blackwell, 2009). They ensure that this survey of Wittgenstein's private language arguments and of his accounts of thought, imagination, consciousness, the self, and criteria will remain the essential reference work on the Investigations for the foreseeable future.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Wittgenstein an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Wittgenstein by P. M. S. Hacker in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Filosofía & Filosofía moderna. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2019
ISBN
9781118951828
Edition
2

Introduction to Part I: Essays

Volume 1 of this Analytical Commentary: Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning (1st edition 1980, 2nd edition 2005) laid the groundwork for understanding the trajectory of Wittgenstein’s thought in his second great masterwork. It explained and gave due prominence to the Augustinian conception of language as informing a multitude of philosophical theories about the nature of language, all of which Wittgenstein aimed to undermine. Conceiving of the essential function of words as naming and of the essential function of sentences as describing stands in the way of an unprejudiced view of the manifold techniques of using words and of the diverse functions of sentences in the stream of human life. These misconceptions give rise to philosophical mythologies of the so called name‐relation, logically proper names, sentence‐radicals and semantic mood operators, of the idea of a truth‐conditional theory of meaning for a natural language, of the notions of determinacy of sense and of the general propositional form. The Augustinian conception of language generates misguided pictures of the relation between language and reality, sentence and fact, proposition and truth‐maker, and of ostensive definition as forging a connection between word and world. This in turn contributes to the pervasive illusion that grammar is answerable to reality, or that it reflects, and must reflect, the essential structure of the world. Against this backdrop of Wittgenstein’s demythologizing, his radical conception of the nature, scope and limits of philosophy was displayed. He held philosophy to be therapeutic and descriptive, not theoretical and hypothetico‐deductive. It destroys idols, but does not replace them. It is a quest for an overview of a segment of logical grammar – of the conceptual network of our language – that gives rise to conceptual questions. The purpose of that quest is the solution or dissolution of the questions. Achievement in philosophy consists in the resolution of philosophical questions, not in the acquisition of new empirical or putatively metaphysical information that provides answers to them. Understanding is indeed attained; but it consists in arriving at a clear vision of what is known and familiar, namely the common grammatical, conceptual, connections of our language. Philosophy contains no theories on the model of the sciences. In its questions, methods and results, philosophy is wholly distinct from science. No scientific discovery can resolve the a priori questions of philosophy, any more than a discovery in physics can resolve an a priori question in mathematics.
Once this had been explained and clarified, it was possible to put Wittgenstein’s discussion of understanding into the right perspective. Meaning, explanation of what a word or utterance means, and understanding constitute a triad of key concepts in philosophical investigations into language and the nature of linguistic representation. Reversing the direction of fit between these concepts that was (and still is) presupposed by the prevailing philosophical tradition, Wittgenstein elaborated the consequences of the grammatical propositions that meaning is what is given by an explanation of meaning, and that it is what is understood when the meaning of an utterance is understood. Understanding (which is akin to an ability, rather than being a mental state) and the criteria of understanding assume a dominant role in his description of the network of grammar in this domain. Clarification of the internal relations between meaning, understanding and explanation also illuminates their complex connections with truth, evidence, justification, definition, rules of use, grammatical propositions and so forth. This network of conceptual connections is put to use in elaborating an anthropological, ethnocentric conception of language as opposed to the calculus conception of language that Wittgenstein had embraced in the Tractatus.
Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar and Necessity, Volume 2 of the Analytical Commentary (1st edition 1985, 2nd edition 2009) examined the complexities and problematic interpretation of Investigations §§185 – 242. Wittgenstein’s conception of a rule needed much clarification, especially against the backdrop of the ideas of syntactic and semantic rules advanced by logicians, theoretical linguists and philosophers throughout the twentieth century, and especially in the last thirty years of the century. His animadversion to hidden rules of depth‐grammar (prominent in the Tractatus and among contemporary linguistic theorists) needed explaining. His insistence that one cannot follow a rule without knowing and understanding the rule one is following, that a rule is a reason for doing something and not a mere regularity, that rules do not compel but justify, needed elucidation. His insight that, in order for one to be following a rule, the rule and its consideration need not enter into one’s action, required clarification: all that is necessary is that one cite it, or would cite it if challenged, ex post actu, as a reason for acting in accordance with the rule. Wittgenstein’s elucidation of following a rule and of the connection between rules and practices had to be made clear in order to explain how an internal relation between rule and what accords with it is forged. This led naturally to an examination of Wittgenstein investigations into the internal relations in general, into the nature of logical, mathematical and grammatical internal relations, as well as to his demystification of necessity and demolition of metaphysics.
Volume 3, Wittgenstein: Meaning and Mind (1st edition 1990) is here presented in an extensively revised 2nd edition, which brings it to the same level as that of the previous two revised volumes. It takes the Commentary forward from §243 to §427. These sections are no less controversial than the preceding ones. To be sure, the rocky ground already traversed should have taught one much. But, as one plunges into the tropical undergrowth of the private language arguments, it is all too easy to lose one’s bearings. The path is overgrown with prevalent misinterpretations and misunderstandings, and dark distorting shadows are cast across it by the disposition to extract theories from Wittgenstein’s descriptions and grammatical statements. Following in his footsteps is not made easier by his ever increasing tendency to dart down a side‐path in order to show one a bog here and quicksands there.
The first task is to clarify the position of these arguments in the overall structure of the book. Why is the question of the possibility of a private language raised at this point? In what ways and to what extent do the private language arguments presuppose Wittgenstein’s previous arguments and conclusions? In particular, how is the discussion of the possibility of a private language related to the antecedent investigation of rules and following rules?
No less pressing is the need to clarify exactly what a private language is supposed to be, and how that misconceived idea relates to the tradition of Western philosophy and reflection on the nature of public language. More specifically, given that all human languages are public languages, why should anyone be interested in a language that is of necessity intelligible only to its speaker? Wittgenstein’s purpose in examining the idea of a private language has itself occasioned much dispute. Was he trying to demonstrate the essential social nature of language, to show that it is not merely an empirical truth that only a social creature can speak a language but that it is an a priori truth? Or was he trying to refute a bizarre form of scepticism about knowing what one means by one’s words and whether words have any meaning? Or is his purpose much deeper?
If the subject is disputed, so too is the conclusion. Is he arguing that there can be no private ostensive definitions, or rather that there can be private ostensive definitions but only in the context of a shared public language? How can he argue that there can be no ‘private’ language, given that the form of words ‘a “private” language’ is as meaningless as ‘a square circle’? Moreover, how can a philosopher who repudiates theses and proofs in philosophy go on to try to prove that there cannot be a private language?
The tactical moves in Wittgenstein’s argument are equally subject to divergent interpretation. The mistaken idea that he relies on some version of the verification principle continues to be advanced by critics. The equally misguided idea that he was advancing a form of logical behaviourism is still common. And the supposition that he was defending a form of anti‐realist, assertion‐conditions semantics as opposed to realist, truth‐conditional semantics is still being advanced. These misinterpretations need to be eradicated.
As one moves beyond the private language arguments of §§243 – 315, further, quite different problems arise. How could anyone suggest that ‘thinking’ is not an activity verb? Is thinking not a paradigm of a mental activity? How can anyone assert that thinking is not an incorporeal process? And how can Wittgenstein say that although I can say what I think, I cannot know what I think? This seems absurd. Similar alarm is raised by his discussion of the imagination. Does one really not see one’s mental images with one’s mind’s eye? Is a mental image of red not a red mental image? Does Wittgenstein really hold that one cannot compare one’s mental image with reality?
By this stage in the book it is clear that Wittgenstein has moved deep into the domain of philosophy of psychology. But what determines his curious choice of subjects? There is no discussion of the emotions, no investigation of pleasure or happiness, no analysis of perception or of the causal theory of perception. Why not? Thought and imagination are examined at some length, with radical results, followed by a brief investigation of the first‐person pronoun and consciousness. Here he goes so far as to intimate that ‘I’ is not a referring expression – a claim that is bound to set philosophers’ teeth on edge, and that consciousness is not in the least mysterious – a suggestion that will seem astonishing to philosophers in the twenty‐first century who hold the hard problem of consciousness to be the greatest mystery in the universe.
Wittgenstein is here grappling with philosophical problems that are, for the most part, as old as philosophy itself. His results, at first glance, seem astonishing – indeed shocking. They go against the grain. They seem to challenge common sense. Wittgenstein appears to traduce the whole philosophical tradition. It was indeed his purpose to challenge received ways of thought. If one wants to solve philosophical questions, one must change one’s way of thinking, no matter how difficult that may be. One must cease thinking of such statements as ‘It visually seems to me that things are thus‐and‐so’ as the unchallengeable given, as the most certain of all empirical propositions, as the foundations of empirical knowledge. One must relinquish the supposition that knowledge, belief and understanding are mental states that may be identical with states of the brain. One must abandon the supposition that ‘I’ is a super‐referring expression, like an arrow that cannot fail to hit its target. If one is not willing to change the way one thinks about such questions, then one should give up philosophy and declare that its great problems are unsolvable.
However, those who study Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations seriously must take seriously his avowal that he was destroying ‘houses of cards’ and ‘clearing up the ground of language on which they stood’ (PI §118). This commentary is written for those who are willing to follow Wittgenstein in his meandering journeys through the philosophical landscape. Its aim is to assist them in tracing his footsteps, to show them the direction of his thought, and to enable them, with the aid of his sketches, to find their own way and to fend for themselves in the jungles, deserts and mountains of philosophy.
P. M. S. Hacker
Oxford
October 2017

Abbreviations

1. Wittgenstein’s published works

The following abbreviations, listed in alphabetical order, are used to refer to Wittgenstein’s published works.
BB The Blue and Brown Books (Blackwell, Oxford, 1958).
BlB Occasionally used to refer to the Blue Book.
BrB Occasionally used to refer to the Brown Book.
BT The Big Typescript, ed. and tr. C. G. Luckhardt and M. A. E. Aue (Blackwell, Oxford, 2005).
C On Certainty, ed. G. E. M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright, tr. D Paul and G. E. M. Ansco...

Table of contents

Citation styles for Wittgenstein

APA 6 Citation

Hacker, P. (2019). Wittgenstein (2nd ed.). Wiley. Retrieved from https://www.perlego.com/book/990819/wittgenstein-meaning-and-mind-volume-3-of-an-analytical-commentary-on-the-philosophical-investigations-part-1-essays-pdf (Original work published 2019)

Chicago Citation

Hacker, P. (2019) 2019. Wittgenstein. 2nd ed. Wiley. https://www.perlego.com/book/990819/wittgenstein-meaning-and-mind-volume-3-of-an-analytical-commentary-on-the-philosophical-investigations-part-1-essays-pdf.

Harvard Citation

Hacker, P. (2019) Wittgenstein. 2nd edn. Wiley. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/990819/wittgenstein-meaning-and-mind-volume-3-of-an-analytical-commentary-on-the-philosophical-investigations-part-1-essays-pdf (Accessed: 14 October 2022).

MLA 7 Citation

Hacker, P. Wittgenstein. 2nd ed. Wiley, 2019. Web. 14 Oct. 2022.