Chance, Calculation and Life
eBook - ePub

Chance, Calculation and Life

Thierry Gaudin, Marie-Christine Maurel, Jean-Charles Pomerol, Thierry Gaudin, Marie-Christine Maurel, Jean-Charles Pomerol

Buch teilen
  1. English
  2. ePUB (handyfreundlich)
  3. Über iOS und Android verfĂŒgbar
eBook - ePub

Chance, Calculation and Life

Thierry Gaudin, Marie-Christine Maurel, Jean-Charles Pomerol, Thierry Gaudin, Marie-Christine Maurel, Jean-Charles Pomerol

Angaben zum Buch
Buchvorschau
Inhaltsverzeichnis
Quellenangaben

Über dieses Buch

Chance, Calculation and Life brings together 16 original papers from the colloquium of the same name, organized by the International Cultural Center of Cerisy in 2019.

From mathematics to the humanities and biology, there are many concepts and questions related to chance. What are the different types of chance? Does chance correspond to a lack of knowledge about the causes of events, or is there a truly intrinsic and irreducible chance? Does chance preside over our decisions? Does it govern evolution? Is it at the origin of life? What part do chance and necessity play in biology?

This book answers these fundamental questions by bringing together the clear and richly documented contributions of mathematicians, physicists, biologists and philosophers who make this book an incomparable tool for work and reflection.

HĂ€ufig gestellte Fragen

Wie kann ich mein Abo kĂŒndigen?
Gehe einfach zum Kontobereich in den Einstellungen und klicke auf „Abo kĂŒndigen“ – ganz einfach. Nachdem du gekĂŒndigt hast, bleibt deine Mitgliedschaft fĂŒr den verbleibenden Abozeitraum, den du bereits bezahlt hast, aktiv. Mehr Informationen hier.
(Wie) Kann ich BĂŒcher herunterladen?
Derzeit stehen all unsere auf MobilgerĂ€te reagierenden ePub-BĂŒcher zum Download ĂŒber die App zur VerfĂŒgung. Die meisten unserer PDFs stehen ebenfalls zum Download bereit; wir arbeiten daran, auch die ĂŒbrigen PDFs zum Download anzubieten, bei denen dies aktuell noch nicht möglich ist. Weitere Informationen hier.
Welcher Unterschied besteht bei den Preisen zwischen den AboplÀnen?
Mit beiden AboplÀnen erhÀltst du vollen Zugang zur Bibliothek und allen Funktionen von Perlego. Die einzigen Unterschiede bestehen im Preis und dem Abozeitraum: Mit dem Jahresabo sparst du auf 12 Monate gerechnet im Vergleich zum Monatsabo rund 30 %.
Was ist Perlego?
Wir sind ein Online-Abodienst fĂŒr LehrbĂŒcher, bei dem du fĂŒr weniger als den Preis eines einzelnen Buches pro Monat Zugang zu einer ganzen Online-Bibliothek erhĂ€ltst. Mit ĂŒber 1 Million BĂŒchern zu ĂŒber 1.000 verschiedenen Themen haben wir bestimmt alles, was du brauchst! Weitere Informationen hier.
UnterstĂŒtzt Perlego Text-zu-Sprache?
Achte auf das Symbol zum Vorlesen in deinem nÀchsten Buch, um zu sehen, ob du es dir auch anhören kannst. Bei diesem Tool wird dir Text laut vorgelesen, wobei der Text beim Vorlesen auch grafisch hervorgehoben wird. Du kannst das Vorlesen jederzeit anhalten, beschleunigen und verlangsamen. Weitere Informationen hier.
Ist Chance, Calculation and Life als Online-PDF/ePub verfĂŒgbar?
Ja, du hast Zugang zu Chance, Calculation and Life von Thierry Gaudin, Marie-Christine Maurel, Jean-Charles Pomerol, Thierry Gaudin, Marie-Christine Maurel, Jean-Charles Pomerol im PDF- und/oder ePub-Format sowie zu anderen beliebten BĂŒchern aus Informatique & Informatique client-serveur. Aus unserem Katalog stehen dir ĂŒber 1 Million BĂŒcher zur VerfĂŒgung.

Information

Jahr
2021
ISBN
9781119823957

PART 1
Randomness in all of its Aspects

1
Classical, Quantum and Biological Randomness as Relative Unpredictability

We propose the thesis that randomness is unpredictability with respect to an intended theory and measurement. From this point of view, we briefly discuss various forms of randomness that physics, mathematics and computer science have proposed. Computer science allows us to discuss unpredictability in an abstract, yet very expressive way, which yields useful hierarchies of randomness and may help to relate its various forms in natural sciences. Finally, we discuss biological randomness – its peculiar nature and role in ontogenesis and in evolutionary dynamics (phylogenesis). Randomness in biology is positive as it contributes to organisms’ and populations’ structural stability by adaptation and diversity.

1.1. Introduction

Randomness is everywhere, for better or for worse: vagaries of weather, day-today fluctuations in the stock market, random motions of molecules or random genetic mutations are just a few examples. Random numbers have been used for more than 4,000 years, but they have never been in such high demand than they have in our time. What is the origin of randomness in nature and how does it relate to the only access we have to phenomena, that is, through measurement? How does randomness in nature relate to randomness in sequences of numbers? The theoretical and mathematical analysis of randomness is far from obvious. Moreover, as we will show, it depends on (and is relative to) the particular theory that is being worked on, the intended theoretical framework for the phenomena under investigation.

1.1.1. Brief historical overview

Democritus (460–370 BCE) determined the causes of things to necessity and chance alike, justifying, for example, the fact that atoms’ disorderly motion can produce an orderly cosmos. However, the first philosopher to think about randomness was most likely Epicurus (341–270 BCE), who argued that “randomness is objective, it is the proper nature of events”.
For centuries, though, randomness has only been mathematically analyzed in games and gambling. Luca Pacioli (in Summa de aritmetica, geometria, proporzioni et proporzionalita, 1494) studied how stakes had to be divided among gamblers, particularly in the difficult case when the game stops before the end. It is worth noting that Pacioli, a top Renaissance mathematician, also invented modern bookkeeping techniques (Double Entry): human activities, from gambling to financial investments, were considered as the locus for chance. As a matter of fact, early Renaissance Florence was the place of the invention of banks, paper currency and (risky) financial investments and loans1.
Cardano (in De Ludo Aleae (The Game of Dice), 1525) developed Pacioli’s analysis further. His book was only published in 1663, so Fermat and Pascal independently and more rigorously rediscovered the “laws of chance” for interrupted games in a famous exchange of letters in 1654. Pascal clarified the independence of history in the games of chance, against common sense: dice do not remember the previous drawings. Probabilities were generally considered as a tool for facing the lack of knowledge in human activities: in contrast to God, we cannot predict the future nor master the consequences of our (risky) actions. For the thinkers of the scientific revolution, randomness is not in nature, which is a perfect “Cartesian Mechanism”: science is meant to discover the gears of its wonderful and exact mechanics. At most, as suggested by Spinoza, two independent, well-determined trajectories may meet (a walking man and a falling tile) and produce a random event. This may be considered a weak form of “epistemic” randomness, as the union of the two systems, if known, may yield a well-determined and predictable system and encounter.
Galileo, while still studying randomness, but only for dice (Sopra le scoperte de i dadi, 1612), was the first to relate measurement and probabilities (1632). For him, in physical measurement, errors are unavoidable, yet small errors are the most probable. Moreover, errors distribute symmetrically around the mean value, whose reliability increases with the number of measurements.
Almost two centuries later, Laplace brought Pascal’s early insights to the modern rigor of probability theory (1998). He stressed the role of limited knowledge of phenomena in making predictions by equations: only a daemon with complete knowledge of all the forces in the Universe could “embrace in a single formula the movements of the greatest bodies of the universe and those of the tiniest atom; for such an intellect nothing would be uncertain and the future just like the past would be present before its eyes”. The connection between incomplete knowledge of natural phenomena and randomness is made, yet no analysis of the possible “reasons” for randomness is proposed: probability theory gives a formal calculus of randomness, with no commitment on the nature of randomness. Defining randomness proved to be a hugely difficult problem which has only received acceptable answers in the last 100 years or so.

1.1.2. Preliminary remarks

Randomness is a tricky concept which can come in many flavors (Downey and Hirschfeldt 2010). Informally, randomness means unpredictability, with a lack of patterns or correlations. Why is randomness so difficult to understand and model? An intuitive understanding comes from the myriad of misconceptions and logical fallacies related to randomness, like the gambler’s fallacy. In spite of the work of mathematicians since the Renaissance, there is the belief that after a coin has landed on tails 10 consecutive times, there are more chances that the coin will land on heads on the next flip. Similarly, common sense argues that there are “due” numbers in the lottery (since all numbers eventually appear, those that have not come up yet are “due”, and thus more likely to come up soon). Each proposed definition of randomness seems to be doomed to be falsified by some more or less clever counter-example.
Even intuitively, the quality of randomness varies: tossing a coin may seem to produce a sequence of zeroes and ones which is less random than the randomness produced by Brownian motion. This is one of the reasons why users of randomness, like casinos, lotteries, polling firms, elections and clinical evaluations, are hard pressed to “prove” that their choices are “really” random. A new challenge is emerging, namely, to “prove randomness”.
For physical systems, the randomness of a process needs to be differentiated from that of its outcome. Random (stochastic) processes have been extensively studied in probability theory, ergodic theory and information theory. Process or genesis randomness refers to such processes. On one hand, a “random” sequence does not necessarily need to be the output of a random process (e.g. a mathematically defined “random” sequence) and, conversely, a random process (e.g. a quantum random generator) is expected, but not guaranteed, to produce a “random output”. Outcome (or product) randomness provides a prima facie reason for the randomness of the process generating that outcome (Eagle 2005, p. 762), but, as argued in Frigg (2004, p. 431), process and outcome randomness are not extensionally equivalent. Process randomness has no mathematical formalization and...

Inhaltsverzeichnis