Philosophy in the Condition of Modernism
eBook - ePub

Philosophy in the Condition of Modernism

Ana Falcato,Antonio Cardiello

Buch teilen
  1. English
  2. ePUB (handyfreundlich)
  3. Über iOS und Android verfĂŒgbar
eBook - ePub

Philosophy in the Condition of Modernism

Ana Falcato,Antonio Cardiello

Angaben zum Buch
Buchvorschau
Inhaltsverzeichnis
Quellenangaben

Über dieses Buch

Produced on the fringes of philosophy and literary criticism, this book is a pioneering study which aims to explicitly address and thematize what may be called a "critical philosophy in the condition of modernism". Its most important and original contribution to both disciplines is a self-conscious reflection on possible modes of writing philosophy today, and a systematic comparison with what happened in literary modernism at the beginning of the twentieth-century. The volume is divided into six sections, where internationally renowned scholars discuss such pressing topics as the role of an unreliable narrator in a major philosophical treatise, the different mediums of art-production and how these impact on our perception of the Work itself, the role of narrative in animal ethics and the filmic adaption of a Modernist classic.

HĂ€ufig gestellte Fragen

Wie kann ich mein Abo kĂŒndigen?
Gehe einfach zum Kontobereich in den Einstellungen und klicke auf „Abo kĂŒndigen“ – ganz einfach. Nachdem du gekĂŒndigt hast, bleibt deine Mitgliedschaft fĂŒr den verbleibenden Abozeitraum, den du bereits bezahlt hast, aktiv. Mehr Informationen hier.
(Wie) Kann ich BĂŒcher herunterladen?
Derzeit stehen all unsere auf MobilgerĂ€te reagierenden ePub-BĂŒcher zum Download ĂŒber die App zur VerfĂŒgung. Die meisten unserer PDFs stehen ebenfalls zum Download bereit; wir arbeiten daran, auch die ĂŒbrigen PDFs zum Download anzubieten, bei denen dies aktuell noch nicht möglich ist. Weitere Informationen hier.
Welcher Unterschied besteht bei den Preisen zwischen den AboplÀnen?
Mit beiden AboplÀnen erhÀltst du vollen Zugang zur Bibliothek und allen Funktionen von Perlego. Die einzigen Unterschiede bestehen im Preis und dem Abozeitraum: Mit dem Jahresabo sparst du auf 12 Monate gerechnet im Vergleich zum Monatsabo rund 30 %.
Was ist Perlego?
Wir sind ein Online-Abodienst fĂŒr LehrbĂŒcher, bei dem du fĂŒr weniger als den Preis eines einzelnen Buches pro Monat Zugang zu einer ganzen Online-Bibliothek erhĂ€ltst. Mit ĂŒber 1 Million BĂŒchern zu ĂŒber 1.000 verschiedenen Themen haben wir bestimmt alles, was du brauchst! Weitere Informationen hier.
UnterstĂŒtzt Perlego Text-zu-Sprache?
Achte auf das Symbol zum Vorlesen in deinem nÀchsten Buch, um zu sehen, ob du es dir auch anhören kannst. Bei diesem Tool wird dir Text laut vorgelesen, wobei der Text beim Vorlesen auch grafisch hervorgehoben wird. Du kannst das Vorlesen jederzeit anhalten, beschleunigen und verlangsamen. Weitere Informationen hier.
Ist Philosophy in the Condition of Modernism als Online-PDF/ePub verfĂŒgbar?
Ja, du hast Zugang zu Philosophy in the Condition of Modernism von Ana Falcato,Antonio Cardiello im PDF- und/oder ePub-Format sowie zu anderen beliebten BĂŒchern aus Philosophy & Aesthetics in Philosophy. Aus unserem Katalog stehen dir ĂŒber 1 Million BĂŒcher zur VerfĂŒgung.

Information

© The Author(s) 2018
Ana Falcato and Antonio Cardiello (eds.)Philosophy in the Condition of Modernism https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-77078-9_1
Begin Abstract

1. Introduction: Philosophy and Literary Modernism—An Old Problem Finally Made New

Ana Falcato1 and Antonio Cardiello1
(1)
Institute of Philosophy of Nova (IFILNOVA), New University of Lisbon, Lisbon, Portugal
Ana Falcato (Corresponding author)
Antonio Cardiello

Keywords

Recounting mythsDemystificationT.S. EliotHans-Georg GadamerStanley CavellModernism and language
End Abstract
Although approximately two-and-a-half-thousand years separate the birth of philosophy and the emergence of literary modernism in the last decade of the nineteenth century, these forms of spiritual creation face overlapping problems, however opposite their methods. Both philosophical works and modernist literary texts are characterised by reflexive density, which is typically made a self-standing topic and which thus allows for meta-reflection—a feature with a highly relevant linguistic impact, as we shall see in what follows. As such, the works of philosophy and the texts of modernism share what Michael Levenson has aptly termed ‘forms of creative violence’ (Levenson 1999: 2).
To take an example of ‘creative violence’ from one of the most radical methods of inquiry developed by twentieth-century philosophy , i.e. hermeneutics, in The Beginning of Philosophy , Hans-Georg Gadamer exercises a certain ‘interpretive violence’ against the famous passage from Metaphysics A, where Aristotle discusses the methodological shift opened by the causal paradigm deployed by the Presocratics, referring to Thales as the first philosopher to propose an entirely new explanatory tool to account for the origins of the universe. Gadamer writes:
Basically, our discussion is trying to show that we are standing here at the origin of doxography. [
] For example, when Aristotle begins to speak in the Metaphysics of the first conception of cause and says that Thales proposed this and that Thales was the first thinker who did not simply recount myths but also made use of evidence, 1 then we must understand that by ‘cause’ he meant matter. (2000: 80)
Strictly speaking, Aristotle is not discussing the myths recounted by the poets and cosmologists whose work precedes the Milesians, but rather unfolding the specificity which comes from the attempt to explain the whole universe as stemming from a single cause. And yet, the hermeneutic freedom exercised by Gadamer himself will remind the attentive reader of the opposite theoretical hypothesis suggested by T.S. Eliot , who, when he reviewed Joyce’s Ulysses for The Dial in November 1923, wrote the following:
Mr. Joyce’s parallel use of the Odyssey has a great importance. It has the importance of a scientific discovery. No one else has built a novel upon such a foundation before: it has never before been necessary. If [Ulysses] is not a novel , that is simply because the novel is a form which will no longer serve; it is because the novel , instead of being a form, was simply the expression of an age which had not sufficiently lost all form to feel the need of something stricter. [
] Instead of the narrative method, we may now use the mythical method. 2 (Eliot 1975: 178)
Comparing these two remarkable passages, we seem warranted to conclude that both the philosophical method and the modernist method represent radical breaks with a given tradition. 3 And at the same time, one can detect a form of arrogance in any attempt at categorization that speaks of a philosophical method alongside a modernist method. Regarding the latter, and in reference to the last excerpt quoted above, it is certainly worth bearing in mind that in this passage, Eliot is only reviewing one work from a vast list that scholars now consider the modernist canon. The cultural impact of Ulysses and its immediate standing as a hallmark of modernism certainly remains indisputable—just as Joyce had predicted—but equally indispensable to the constitution of something like a modernist canon are: Mrs. Dalloway, To the Lighthouse, The Waste Land and The Cantos. This observation about different forms of radical rupture, which do not ask to be systematized and ultimately cannot bear systematization, leads to a second strand of reflection on the intertwinement of modernism and philosophy , this time strictly derived from the field of philosophical criticism. In a book that is highly relevant to the present study, Modernism and the Language of Philosophy (2006), Anat Matar develops a historic-philosophical hypothesis for justifying the emergence of literary modernism in the last quarter of the nineteenth century, which she encapsulates in the following statement:
I see modernism as emerging from a unity of two philosophical insights, which matured in the nineteenth-century. The growing awareness of the loss of (or, alternatively, liberation from) the transcendent, stabilizing factor that enabled realist metaphysics led to novel conceptions of philosophy and of language alike. (2006: 7)
Matar’s methodology is strictly philosophical, and it aims at identifying, from within the evolution of modern philosophy itself, the conditions for the possibility of literary modernism as a radical artistic breakthrough. Besides making a conciliatory effort to bring together the analytic and the so-called continental traditions in philosophy , the author conceives of the anti-dogmatic obsession with language which typically characterizes modernist works as the logical consequence of a general disbelief in the existence of a metaphysical reality which transcends the subject and the very language she uses to describe the world as she perceives it. Matar does not content herself with diagnosis, however. A careful analysis draws her to the conclusion that the modernists replaced one dogmatism with another, by which she means that the most prestigious modernist artists swapped a linguistic for an essentialist form of dogmatism, whereas, she claims, only a thorough reflection on the ludic, performative and non-static character of human language can make room for a modernist overcoming of modernism .
A second—and arguably better-known—platform for dialogue between philosophy and modernism can be found in the texts of Stanley Cavell (cf. 1969, 1971) and is fundamentally indebted to both an assessment of the Wittgensteinian notion of ‘criteria ’ and a highly original interdisciplinary borrowing of key concepts introduced by the American art critic Michael Fried , originally applied to the evolution of modern European painting . 4 Cavell discusses and refines these concepts, suggesting that they are instrumental in working out an unconventional mode of writing and practicing philosophy . In a crucial passage from ‘A Matter of Meaning It’, included in the volume Must We Mean What We Say? , Cavell writes the following about the philosophical puzzle facing modernist artist and modern art critics alike:
The task of the modernist artist , as of the contemporary critic, is to find what it is his art finally depends upon; it doesn’t matter that we haven’t a priori criteria for defining a painting , what matters is that we realize that the criteria are something we must discover, discover in the continuity of painting itself. But my point now is that to discover this we need to discover what objects we accept as paintings, and why we so accept them. (2002: 219)
An implicit message in this proposal of a permanent upgrading of the standing criteria which allow a modern viewer to recognize an artwork as such concerns the fact that pretty much the same can happen to the philosophical text itself. Stanley Cavell ’s texts are systematic disruptions of the common understanding held by a philosophical community concerning what an essay or dissertation in the discipline can reasonably be. Thus, the dynamic that inheres in linguistic playfulness, and which according to Matar is the untrodden path that makes the de-dogmatization of modernism possible, finds in the work of Stanley Cavell a highly significant instantiation—and this at two distinct levels. On the one hand, as the above passage shows, he clearly refuses to accept formal criteria which would bind together all modern artworks; on the other hand, his prose embodies the very denial of criteria , as applied to philosophy , for which he stands when discussing modern art .
A further way to instantiate Matar’s claims about the de-dogmatization of contemporary philosophy —a path she clearly doesn’t take—was immediately pointed out when the book was first critically assessed. In a review of Modernism and the Language of Philosophy , published by Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, Fabrice Pataut wrote the following: ‘One fruitful way to open the dialogue Matar wishes to establish would be to consider acts of thought pertaining to the domain of fiction ’ (2006).
This clearly addresses Matar’s failure to weigh the historical and conceptual relations between modernism and philosophy , but it is not a critique one could possibly level at Stanley Cavell ’s oeuvre, which includes books of essays and monographs that critically assess the works of writers like Shakespeare, Kierkegaard, Beckett, Thoreau, Emerson, Ibsen and J.M. Coetzee . And in ways that often run parallel to the Cavellian approach to the two fields of inquiry, the present book also fully addresses this demand for companionship between fiction and philosophical analysis.
Our aim is thus to provide a timely contribution to the vast debate between two traditionally rival disciplines—a debate that is already firmly rooted in much academic philosophy as it is currently practiced—and to make that re-gathering both explicit and self -conscious. Following the cry for novelty and rupture with the weary tradition of realism , which has defined modernism since its inception (and, in the case of contemporary philosophy , in a way that is further complicated by the presence of a split between two traditions), this book also challenges settled modes of writing and practicing philosophy and criticism. Acknowledging already-trodden paths that have this reconciliatory aim in mind, along with aspects that went amiss in such efforts and were rightfully pointed out—like Pataut’s main critique of Matar’s book—this volume not only incorporates a generous dialogue with poets and novelists but recognizes and adapts the general point that Michael Fried has been making for over forty years in the field of art criticism . For our present purposes, the key figure whose vital importance and standing presence neither philosophy nor criticism can justifiably ignore is the reader herself. Not, of course, in the trivial sense that ‘the text is there to be read’, but rather in the sophisticated and self -reflective sense that the text must find the means of acknowledging the reader’s presence to it, from the inside.
Doing justice to recent critiques of the unnecessary technicality of philosophical vocabulary—a critique explicitly addressed to all authors who aspire to publish in the most prestigious scientific journals in the discipline—the essays collected here combine analytic rigour with the omission of needless technical jargon. The appeal to the critical, sharp eye of the reader begins with style itself, which imposes its own demands (which are far from being strictly cognitive). However, given the still-common use of technical jargon, validated as a scientific language , this book i...

Inhaltsverzeichnis