A Brief History of Old Testament Criticism
eBook - ePub

A Brief History of Old Testament Criticism

Mark S. Gignilliat

Buch teilen
  1. 192 Seiten
  2. English
  3. ePUB (handyfreundlich)
  4. Über iOS und Android verfĂŒgbar
eBook - ePub

A Brief History of Old Testament Criticism

Mark S. Gignilliat

Angaben zum Buch
Buchvorschau
Inhaltsverzeichnis
Quellenangaben

Über dieses Buch

Mark Gignilliat discusses critical theologians and their theories of Old Testament interpretation in this concise overview, providing a working knowledge of the historical foundation of contemporary discussions on Old Testament interpretation.

Old Testament interpretation developed as theologians and scholars proposed critical theories over time. These figures contributed to a large, developing complex of ideas and trends that serves as the foundation of contemporary discussions on interpretation. Mark Gignilliat brings these figures and their theories together in A Brief History of Old Testament Criticism. His discussion is driven by influential thinkers such as Baruch Spinoza and the critical tradition, Johann Semler and historical criticism, Hermann Gunkel and romanticism, Gerhard von Rad and the tradition-historical approach, Brevard Childs and the canonical approach, and more.

This concise overview is ideal for classroom use as it provides a working knowledge of the major critical interpreters of the Old Testament, their approach to the subject matter, and the philosophical background of their approaches. Further reading lists direct readers to additional resources on specific theologians and theories. This book will serve as a companion to the forthcoming textbook Believing Criticism by Richard Schultz.

HĂ€ufig gestellte Fragen

Wie kann ich mein Abo kĂŒndigen?
Gehe einfach zum Kontobereich in den Einstellungen und klicke auf „Abo kĂŒndigen“ – ganz einfach. Nachdem du gekĂŒndigt hast, bleibt deine Mitgliedschaft fĂŒr den verbleibenden Abozeitraum, den du bereits bezahlt hast, aktiv. Mehr Informationen hier.
(Wie) Kann ich BĂŒcher herunterladen?
Derzeit stehen all unsere auf MobilgerĂ€te reagierenden ePub-BĂŒcher zum Download ĂŒber die App zur VerfĂŒgung. Die meisten unserer PDFs stehen ebenfalls zum Download bereit; wir arbeiten daran, auch die ĂŒbrigen PDFs zum Download anzubieten, bei denen dies aktuell noch nicht möglich ist. Weitere Informationen hier.
Welcher Unterschied besteht bei den Preisen zwischen den AboplÀnen?
Mit beiden AboplÀnen erhÀltst du vollen Zugang zur Bibliothek und allen Funktionen von Perlego. Die einzigen Unterschiede bestehen im Preis und dem Abozeitraum: Mit dem Jahresabo sparst du auf 12 Monate gerechnet im Vergleich zum Monatsabo rund 30 %.
Was ist Perlego?
Wir sind ein Online-Abodienst fĂŒr LehrbĂŒcher, bei dem du fĂŒr weniger als den Preis eines einzelnen Buches pro Monat Zugang zu einer ganzen Online-Bibliothek erhĂ€ltst. Mit ĂŒber 1 Million BĂŒchern zu ĂŒber 1.000 verschiedenen Themen haben wir bestimmt alles, was du brauchst! Weitere Informationen hier.
UnterstĂŒtzt Perlego Text-zu-Sprache?
Achte auf das Symbol zum Vorlesen in deinem nÀchsten Buch, um zu sehen, ob du es dir auch anhören kannst. Bei diesem Tool wird dir Text laut vorgelesen, wobei der Text beim Vorlesen auch grafisch hervorgehoben wird. Du kannst das Vorlesen jederzeit anhalten, beschleunigen und verlangsamen. Weitere Informationen hier.
Ist A Brief History of Old Testament Criticism als Online-PDF/ePub verfĂŒgbar?
Ja, du hast Zugang zu A Brief History of Old Testament Criticism von Mark S. Gignilliat im PDF- und/oder ePub-Format sowie zu anderen beliebten BĂŒchern aus Theology & Religion & Biblical Criticism & Interpretation. Aus unserem Katalog stehen dir ĂŒber 1 Million BĂŒcher zur VerfĂŒgung.

1
BENEDICT SPINOZA
(1632–1677)

Modernity’s Changing Tide and
the Dislocation of Scripture from Revelation

BENEDICT DE SPINOZA IS A WATERSHED FIGURE IN THE HISTORY OF BIBLICAL interpretation. His approach to biblical studies was not born in a vacuum. Nor was his approach to biblical studies the first to raise critical questions about the Bible. Nevertheless, Spinoza is a significant figure because of his bold and bald articulation of the matter. Others before him had taken a critical approach to the historical character of Scripture and its claims — Thomas Hobbes and Isaac La PeyrĂ©re, for example. Spinoza, however, speaks directly without much clearing of his throat. The Swiss-Calvinist theologian Johann Heinrich Heidegger (1633–1698) recognized the erosion initiated by Hobbes and La PeyrĂ©re, “but no one,” he writes, “struck at the foundations of the entire Pentateuch more shamelessly than Spinoza.”1 In essence, Spinoza’s approach to biblical interpretation brought together the following assumptions: (1) The Bible is a product of human history and evolution and is to be read in the light of its natural history, and (2) philosophy and theology must be understood as two distinct disciplines. The former discipline has to do with truth, and the latter with morality. For Spinoza, “the natural light of reason” became the primary lens for reading the Bible and negotiating its claims.
When Spinoza first published his work advancing these ideas, he did so anonymously. The book’s innocuous title was Tractatus Theologico-Politicus (1670).2 The book’s content was not so benign. The Tractatus met with immediate hostility and was formally banned in 1674.3 Even before then, it was an illegal text whose publication was hindered.4 In 1670, for example, the government ordered a raid on the bookshops of Leiden in a search-and-destroy mission against the Tractatus.5 Before the publication of the Tractatus, his local Jewish community expelled him because of the kind of ideas presented in this volume. It is an understatement, therefore, to say that Spinoza’s ideas and work created a stir.
It is important to come to terms with Spinoza because his work sets a trajectory for the modern-critical approach to Old Testament exegesis. With Spinoza, the search for the text’s meaning becomes equated with the search for the text’s ostensive historical referent, setting, and immediate intention. Moreover, his Old Testament interpretation is set within the framework of Cartesian modes of knowing, rejection of miracles, and denial of the supernatural.6 As one can imagine, these modern intellectual instincts changed the rules of the interpretive game. Before turning our attention to Spinoza’s work, we will explore a brief account of his life and intellectual/social context.

Crossing the Rubicon: Spinoza’s Cultural and Intellectual Setting

Spinoza was born on November 24, 1632, in Amsterdam, “the most beautiful city of Europe.”7 His parents, Michael de Espinoza and Hanna Debora, were Portuguese Jews who likely resettled in Amsterdam because of the Portuguese Inquisition. The Jewish community in Amsterdam during this time was composed of three subgroups, each with its own synagogue and governing board.8 In 1639 these three independent boards became one and were called the Talmud Torah.9 Before this unification, however, both Benedict’s father, Michael, and his uncle, Abraham, served on the governing board of their particular community (Beth Jacob). It is worth mentioning that only five people at a time served on these governing boards; it was an elite group. After the union of the three groups, Michael served on the Talmud Torah’s board from 1649–1650.10 The Espinoza family was respected and valued in Amsterdam’s Jewish community. In time, Spinoza’s rejection of the ideas and values of his community would bring shame on the Spinoza name.
There is debate among the sources regarding Spinoza’s formal education and how he came into conflict with his Jewish community. He is often portrayed as a young scholar who debated with his rabbi on the finer points of biblical and Talmudic interpretation in the higher level medras-sim (classes) of his rabbinic school. This is doubtful.11 Spinoza’s name does not appear on the class rolls kept during this time. This indicates a situation common to many young men of Spinoza’s era. He probably joined his father’s business while still an adolescent, precluding further education. In any case, it is unlikely Spinoza pursued formal, rabbinic education past the age of fourteen.12 These events in no way cast aspersions on his gifted intellect. He had a masterful knowledge of the Hebrew language, along with specialized knowledge of the Scriptures and rabbinical sources.13 Still, Spinoza’s intellectual curiosity was left nearly unfettered once his formal, rabbinic training ceased.14
Spinoza continued as a merchant in his father’s business for many years. His business engagements with Protestant thinkers in the Netherlands may have exposed him to broader intellectual trends than the Talmud Torah community would have allowed. He also may have studied for a period at the University of Leiden (1656–1658), though the evidence for this is thin.15 At any rate, Spinoza began to find the dogma of Judaism problematic and pursued other intellectual options.16 He describes the immediate cause of his intellectual pursuit in his first published work, Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect. He says his pursuits were born out of his experience that “all the things which regularly occur in ordinary life are empty and futile 
”17 One can suppose Spinoza’s business life left him intellectually bored while the traditional teachings of his rabbinic community became increasingly provincial and outdated. By his early twenties, his philosophical interests had turned decidedly secular.18 His most influential tutor in this newfound intellectual freedom was RenĂ© Descartes.19
Spinoza’s continued repudiation of rabbinic teaching and authority led to an inevitable conflict. Israel describes the situation: “Ruined financially, Spinoza had now definitively made up his mind to cross the Rubicon — discarding respectability, social standing, and commerce and devoting himself wholeheartedly to philosophy.”20 The perfect storm came together in July 1656 as Spinoza’s financial difficulties, which left him unable to pay a promissory tax, coincided with his adoption of new and offensive ideas.21 A ban or cherem was placed against Spinoza and read out loud in the synagogue before the community.22 Nadler writes, “There is no other excommunication document of the period marked by the vitriol directed at Spinoza when he was expelled from the congregation.”23 The cause of this hostility was most likely the controversial ideas Spinoza was embracing. As soon as four years after the ban, Spinoza’s controversial ideas began to appear in published form. Some of the notions his religious community found most offensive were the mortality of the soul, the denial of the Mosaic authorship of the Pentateuch, the rejection of the revelatory character of the Torah, and the dismissal of Israel’s status as the elect of God.24 Though religious apathy may have been tolerated in the Talmud Torah community, such heretical ideas as Spinoza’s were a threat to the very fabric of their existence. After the ban, Baruch took the Christian name Benedictus. He no longer identified with his Jewish roots.
Our engagement with Spinoza is not meant to give a full biographical treatment.25 To do so would take us too far afield. Our interest in Spinoza has to do primarily with his ideas and how they influenced biblical studies. But it is important to understand, even if somewhat minimally, the community values Spinoza was reacting against and the intellectual currents of the day that influenced his thought. Modernity’s most cherished claims — autonomous intellectual pursuits, dismissal of dogmatic tradition, naturalism, and affirmation of the Cartesian “I” (I think therefore I am) — were advanced by Spinoza’s philosophical and hermeneutical outlook. Because of these intellectual commitments, Spinoza inevitably clashed with his religious community, which valued divine revelation as the highest source of metaphysical and ethical knowledge.

Wood Stoves and the Autonomous I: Descartes’s Early Influence on Spinoza

As mentioned above, Descartes was Spinoza’s early teacher par excellence. As an aside, it is worth noting that Spinoza’s philosophical system, “Spinozism,” was the product of his own first-rate mind and should not be understood as “Descartes regurgitated.” Jonathan Israel’s discipline-defining work Radical Enlightenment identifies Spinoza as the major figure in the making of modernity. Nevertheless, Descartes’s lasting influence on Spinoza is not questioned. Descartes’s Meditations on First Philosophy (1641), Principles of Philosophy (1644), and the well-known Discourse on Method (1637) provided for Spinoza the philosophical grammar he needed to engage the dogmatism of his Jewish community and the larger Calvinist world he inhabited.26 In many ways, Spinoza was more radical than Descartes because of his application of a Cartesian epistemology to the study of the Bible.27 A brief overview of Descártese theory of knowledge will help situate Spinoza’s epistemological instincts.
From a “stove-heated room” in Germany, as the story goes, a twenty-three-year-old Descartes decided to rework the entirety of the Aristotelian philosophical tradition handed down to him in the schools — a system of thought already castigated by the medieval nominalists who preceded him.28 Descártese philosophical efforts were ambitious as he attempted to provide a secure foundation for knowledge. Where does authority reside in the sciences, and how is knowledge received? When everything else can be called into question, what is the unquestionable premise or foundation of reality and knowledge (e.g., metaphysics)? The unambiguous answer Descartes gives to this question is as follows: Whatever reality is or whatever I am, I can be certain that I am a thinking self. Our thinking, our ordering of knowledge—whether it corresponds to reality or not—is the foundation for metaphysical claims about reality and knowledge. This philosophical idea lead to Descartes’s famous Cogito: I think therefore I am (cogito ergo sum).
In Descártese Meditations on First Philosophy he raises the question, “What am I?” This question for Descartes is really about the broader and more important issue he is exploring, namely, “Of what can we be assured?” Before raising this question, Descartes reveals his willingness to tear down the edifice of knowledge handed down to him as he calls into question everything previously assumed.29 Doubt creeps in at every level of metaphysical and physical inquiry.30 Nothing he knows from tradition, culture, previous teachers, or religion can be taken for granted. Everything needs reconceptualization. So the question “What am I?” is predicated on Descartes’s posture of doubt in relation to the world surrounding him and in relation to his own received knowledge.
“What am I?” could be answered in many different ways: I feel; I live; I breathe; I hear; I see. For Descartes, however, even the body itself and its sensory experiences can be doubted because it is a part of the material world surrounding us.31 Our sensory experiences and feelings must also come under the umbrella of doubt.32 Descartes illustrates the preceding with the experience of being near fire. Typically one describes being near fire with sensory descriptors. I see flames. I hear crackling. I feel heat. Though these experiences may be real and true experiences, Descartes is willing to grant to those skeptical of such sensory experiences — or of the claim that these experiences correspond to reality or assure us of their reality — that it is possible we are dreaming or that the experienced phenomenon is false. But what is not false, for Descartes, is the perception associated with our feelings. Even if the experience itself is not true, our thinking about it is. Listen to Descartes describe the situation in Meditations: “Let it be so [that we are dreaming]; still it is at least quite certain that it seems to me that I see light, that I hear noise, and that I feel heat. That cannot be false; properly speaking it is what is ...

Inhaltsverzeichnis