Logics and Languages
eBook - ePub

Logics and Languages

Max Cresswell

Compartir libro
  1. 284 páginas
  2. English
  3. ePUB (apto para móviles)
  4. Disponible en iOS y Android
eBook - ePub

Logics and Languages

Max Cresswell

Detalles del libro
Vista previa del libro
Índice
Citas

Información del libro

Originally published in 1973, this book shows that methods developed for the semantics of systems of formal logic can be successfully applied to problems about the semantics of natural languages; and, moreover, that such methods can take account of features of natural language which have often been thought incapable of formal treatment, such as vagueness, context dependence and metaphorical meaning.

Parts 1 and 2 set out a class of formal languages and their semantics. Parts 3 and 4 show that these formal languages are rich enought to be used in the precise description of natural languages.

Appendices describe some of the concepts discussed in the text.

Preguntas frecuentes

¿Cómo cancelo mi suscripción?
Simplemente, dirígete a la sección ajustes de la cuenta y haz clic en «Cancelar suscripción». Así de sencillo. Después de cancelar tu suscripción, esta permanecerá activa el tiempo restante que hayas pagado. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Cómo descargo los libros?
Por el momento, todos nuestros libros ePub adaptables a dispositivos móviles se pueden descargar a través de la aplicación. La mayor parte de nuestros PDF también se puede descargar y ya estamos trabajando para que el resto también sea descargable. Obtén más información aquí.
¿En qué se diferencian los planes de precios?
Ambos planes te permiten acceder por completo a la biblioteca y a todas las funciones de Perlego. Las únicas diferencias son el precio y el período de suscripción: con el plan anual ahorrarás en torno a un 30 % en comparación con 12 meses de un plan mensual.
¿Qué es Perlego?
Somos un servicio de suscripción de libros de texto en línea que te permite acceder a toda una biblioteca en línea por menos de lo que cuesta un libro al mes. Con más de un millón de libros sobre más de 1000 categorías, ¡tenemos todo lo que necesitas! Obtén más información aquí.
¿Perlego ofrece la función de texto a voz?
Busca el símbolo de lectura en voz alta en tu próximo libro para ver si puedes escucharlo. La herramienta de lectura en voz alta lee el texto en voz alta por ti, resaltando el texto a medida que se lee. Puedes pausarla, acelerarla y ralentizarla. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Es Logics and Languages un PDF/ePUB en línea?
Sí, puedes acceder a Logics and Languages de Max Cresswell en formato PDF o ePUB, así como a otros libros populares de Philosophie y Sprache in der Philosophie. Tenemos más de un millón de libros disponibles en nuestro catálogo para que explores.

Información

Editorial
Routledge
Año
2016
ISBN
9781134874118
Edición
1
Categoría
Philosophie

PART ONE
Propositional Languages

CHAPTER ONE
Syntax and Semantics of Propositional Languages

Our aim in this book will be to set out and discuss artificial languages which can exhibit many if not all of the semantical features of natural languages. Such an aim will necessitate a very general definition of a wide class of languages. Part I of the book will prepare the way by studying the general form of the languages of propositional logic, particularly the languages of intensional logic.

Syntax

By a propositional language ℒ we mean an ordered pair 〈Δ, S〉 where Δ = 〈Δ0, …, Δk〉 is a finite sequence of pairwise disjoint, possibly empty, finite sets, and S is the smallest set such that:
1.1 Δ0⊆S.
1.2 If δΔn (1 ⩽ nk) and α1…,αn ∈ S then 〈δ, α1…,αn〉 ∈ S.17
What the definition comes to is this. The union of all the sets in Δ, denoted by Δ+, is the set of symbols18 or words of and S is the set of sentences or (well-formed) formulae. Δ0 is the set of simple sentence symbols (for by 1.1 any member of Δ0 is a member of S, i.e., a sentence) and Δn (1 ≦ nk) is the set of n-place propositional functors. An n-place propositional functor is a symbol which when placed before n sentences forms another (complex) sentence. This is what 1.2 says. Those familiar with propositional logic, who may be finding all this rather too abstract, should think of the propositional calculus as a propositional language. Δ0 is the set of ‘propositional variables’, Δ1 contains one member, the symbol ~, Δ2 may contain the symbols ⊃, ∨, . , ≡ and perhaps a few others.19 In this case k = 2; and indeed most versions of the propositional calculus contain at most 2-place functors.
Other propositional logics (modal logics, e.g., with the symbols L and M, or □ and ◊ ; in Δ1) also fall under our definition. There is however one important restriction, that is that Δ0 is finite. In most propositional logics the simple sentence symbols are denumerably infinite and in some, e.g. PC itself, it is crucial that this should be so. There are not too complicated ways of achieving an infinite number of simple sentence symbols out of a finite alphabet (e.g. p, p′, p″, p‴, p″″ etc.) but they take us a little beyond the definition we have given.
The only restriction we have placed on the members of Δ+ is that they be finite and have no common members. This does not rule out the possibility that a complex sentence might also be a symbol. Suppose for instance that Δ0 = {α} and Δ1 = {δ, 〈δ, α〉}. Then Δ0 and Δ1 are disjoint but 〈δ, α〉 is both a functor and a complex sentence. Since this is undesirable for all sorts of reasons we shall say that a propositional language is grounded iff for no δΔn and α1, …, αn ∈ S is 〈δ, α1, …, αn〉 ∈ Δ+. We shall assume that all the propositional languages we discuss are grounded.
Apart from these restrictions the members of Δ+ may be anything we please. At first this may seem a little strange. Since we speak about them as symbols shouldn’t we say what symbols are ? And since we talk about functors making complex sentences out of simpler ones shouldn’t we say something about how the putting together is done? The answer is that, fortunately, for the semantical analysis of a language we do not, at this stage at least, have to answer these questions. When we actually use a language of course the members of Δ+ can’t be just any old things. E.g., suppose Big Ben is a member of Δ0 and Walter Scott a member of Δ1, then the sequence (ordered pair) whose first member is Walter Scott and whose second Big Ben is a sentence of our language, and it is a little difficult to see how such a language would be any good in practice. For languages actually in use the symbols can perhaps be regarded as classes of utterances.20 We shall have a little more to say on this problem later: for the moment we simply repeat that symbols can be anything we like and that sentences are set-theoretical entities (sequences) made up out of the symbols according to 1.1 and 1.2.
The rules 1.1 and 1.2 may be regarded as specifying the syntax of propositional languages, for they determine the class of grammatically well-formed sentences of these languages. Before we proceed to semantics we shall describe these rules in a slightly different way which will lend itself to fairly easy generalization when we come to more elaborate languages. In describing a propositional language we make use of the notion of a syntactic category.21 In propositional languages one of these is the category of sentence, while the others are all categories of functors.
A functor is a symbol which, occurring as the first member of a sequence of symbols of certain syntactical kinds, makes a sequence of the same or another syntactical kind. If δΔn then δ placed before n members of the category sentence forms another sequence of the category sentence.
In Chapter Five we shall use ‘F’ to denote a class of functors and use a subscript to indicate the kind of functor. We shall be using 0 to indicate the category of sentence. Since an n-place propositional functor forms a sentence, i.e. a thing of category 0, out of n other things of category 0 we can represent the class of n-place functors as
equation
Here the ordered n + 1-tuple of 0’s may be said to be the category index of n-place propositional functors. The first member of the n + 1-tuple tells us that what is formed by the functor is a thing of category 0 and the last n members tell us that this is formed out of n other things of catego...

Índice