Thinking Catherine Malabou
eBook - ePub

Thinking Catherine Malabou

Passionate Detachments

Thomas Wormald, Isabell Dahms

Compartir libro
  1. 272 páginas
  2. English
  3. ePUB (apto para móviles)
  4. Disponible en iOS y Android
eBook - ePub

Thinking Catherine Malabou

Passionate Detachments

Thomas Wormald, Isabell Dahms

Detalles del libro
Vista previa del libro
Índice
Citas

Información del libro

This volume contributes to the growing body of literature exploring the work of contemporary French philosopher Catherine Malabou. Through its fifteen contributions, including two previously untranslated essays by Malabou, the volume explores the various ways in which Malabou's thought both performs and furnishes resources for the negotiation of philosophy's attachment and detachment from itself and other disciplines. What kind of interaction can philosophy have with either science or politics without conquering them? How does one carry out philosophy while subverting it, changing it, directing it on or opening it up to different pathways? The chapters explore the detachment of Malabou from her own philosophical training in deconstruction, the theme of habit and the question of new attachments, detachments through the relation of Malabou's thought and science, and the detachments that transpire through philosophy's confrontation with politics. In order to have a future, philosophy must detach from its own tradition and passionately confront questions of race, gender, and colonialism.

Preguntas frecuentes

¿Cómo cancelo mi suscripción?
Simplemente, dirígete a la sección ajustes de la cuenta y haz clic en «Cancelar suscripción». Así de sencillo. Después de cancelar tu suscripción, esta permanecerá activa el tiempo restante que hayas pagado. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Cómo descargo los libros?
Por el momento, todos nuestros libros ePub adaptables a dispositivos móviles se pueden descargar a través de la aplicación. La mayor parte de nuestros PDF también se puede descargar y ya estamos trabajando para que el resto también sea descargable. Obtén más información aquí.
¿En qué se diferencian los planes de precios?
Ambos planes te permiten acceder por completo a la biblioteca y a todas las funciones de Perlego. Las únicas diferencias son el precio y el período de suscripción: con el plan anual ahorrarás en torno a un 30 % en comparación con 12 meses de un plan mensual.
¿Qué es Perlego?
Somos un servicio de suscripción de libros de texto en línea que te permite acceder a toda una biblioteca en línea por menos de lo que cuesta un libro al mes. Con más de un millón de libros sobre más de 1000 categorías, ¡tenemos todo lo que necesitas! Obtén más información aquí.
¿Perlego ofrece la función de texto a voz?
Busca el símbolo de lectura en voz alta en tu próximo libro para ver si puedes escucharlo. La herramienta de lectura en voz alta lee el texto en voz alta por ti, resaltando el texto a medida que se lee. Puedes pausarla, acelerarla y ralentizarla. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Es Thinking Catherine Malabou un PDF/ePUB en línea?
Sí, puedes acceder a Thinking Catherine Malabou de Thomas Wormald, Isabell Dahms en formato PDF o ePUB, así como a otros libros populares de Philosophy y Deconstruction in Philosophy. Tenemos más de un millón de libros disponibles en nuestro catálogo para que explores.

Información

Año
2018
ISBN
9781786606938
Edición
1
Categoría
Philosophy

Section 1

Detaching from Derrida?

The Future of Deconstruction after Malabou

Chapter 1

Is Science the Subject of Philosophy? Miller, Badiou, and Derrida Respond1

Catherine Malabou
Translated by William Samson
I wish to make you aware of two reading experiences I have had. The first is that of reading Alain Badiou’s 1969 text, published in Cahiers pour l’analyse, titled “Mark and Lack,” where we can find the affirmation that gave rise to my title: “Science is the subject of philosophy.”2 This chapter is a response to Jacques Alain Miller’s “Suture: Elements of the Logic of the Signifier,”3 published a few years prior to Badiou’s essay in the same journal. Despite their specific and very dated context—their questions about science had to confront, in that time, both psychoanalysis and Marxism—they contain very important elements for thinking the relations between science and philosophy today, and they have import that, in my opinion, goes well beyond their time.
The second discovery is altogether different. While, for other reasons, I was recently rereading Derrida’s “Passions: An Oblique Offering,”4 I was struck by the coincidence—if not the similarity—of the analyses developed in that book with those developed by Badiou about the situation of philosophy. The word “situation” is being taken here in its proper sense, as venue, place, and orientation, all at the same time. This coincidence is more surprising given that the two thinkers have little in common with each other, as is attested to by the extreme difference in the points of departure of their respective discourses. Badiou undertakes the analysis of the relations between philosophy and mathematical logic, while Derrida concerns himself with the relations between philosophy and literature. Despite it all, their conclusions strangely and mutually echo each other.
In both cases, what I will call the law of the fault of philosophy (la loi du défaut de philosophie) emerges. For both thinkers, philosophy is in need of an answer. It wants to answer for everything, even, which is the problem, for that which does not respond. What does not respond, for Badiou, is science. For Derrida, literature. Examining these two types of nonresponses more closely will constitute my subject, which is precisely the question of the subject. There is no subject of science, says Badiou; there is no subject of literature, says Derrida. This double absence of subject constitutes precisely, for them, the subject of philosophy, which is supposed to respond in their place by wrongly characterizing this absence as a lack. A lack which it is possible not to fill, but at least to make speak.
* * *
Let us start with Miller. He undertakes to show that science, and in particular mathematical logic, proceeds from a denial of lack, and sutures closed all that could leave the place of the other of science (which is to say, the subject-function) empty. By definition, science is “objective” and admits no lacuna or void, no desire nor gap. This constitutes the “suture” or foreclosure that Miller, with the help of Lacan, intends to deconstruct. To this end, Miller begins with a reading of Frege’s The Foundations of Arithmetic, where he defends the idea that zero, in mathematics, is precisely not a void or a lack.5 Miller will then demonstrate that zero in reality marks the place of the subject’s foreclosure.
In The Foundations of Arithmetic, Frege defines number. A number refers to no particular thing. It does, however, have an object. What is the difference between a thing—that empirical X—and an object? The difference between four balls as things and what the number 4 measures? What do things become once they are numbered and numerable, in other words? They become units. Because of this, they obey particular syntactic determinations, which are ordered by a fundamental rule or structure, which Frege outlines in the following way: Numbers are extensions of concepts. The number 4, for example, is the extension of the concept “four.” The two are equinumerical. “The number which belongs to the concept F,” says Frege, “is the extension of the concept ‘equinumerical to the concept F.’ ”6
What does “concept” mean here? “Concept” signifies self-identity. Saying that a number is an extension of a concept signifies that a number is identical to its concept, that it is identical to itself. In other words, as Miller rightly says, all numbers presuppose “the concept of identity to a concept.”7 This rule of identity to a concept is valid for all numbers. “The concept of identity to a concept” works for every number. This is the rule of unity: being self-identical means to “be one.” There is thus some “one” in all numbers. “This one [that of the singular unit] … is common to all numbers in so far as they are first constituted as units.”8
The object is the thing become one (self-identical), and thus numberable. “That definition, pivotal to his concept,” continues Miller, “is one that Frege borrows from Leibniz. It is contained in this statement: eadem sunt quorum unum potest substitui alteri salva veritate. Those things are identical of which one can be substituted for the other salva veritate without loss of truth.”9 Numbers are substitutable for one another insofar as in them, at any time, the self-identical repeats itself, that is, the “one” of the unit. We can thus “pass” from one number to another without losing truth, since identity is preserved.
But the problem then arises of knowing how one “progresses” from one number to another. How the number can “pass from the repetition of the 1 of the identical to its ordered succession: 1, 2, 3, 4, 5?” The answer is for that to occur, “the zero has to appear.”10 And Miller here makes reference to the very influential Fregian analysis of zero.
Why is the “engendering of the zero”11 necessary for Frege? At this point, we’ve posited the self-identity of the concept of number, and thus of the number itself. That’s to say that “non-identity with itself is contradictory to the very dimension of truth.” How then to designate nonidentity? “To its concept, we assign the zero,” says Miller, reading Frege. Nothing falls under the concept “nonidentical with itself” if not, Miller continues, a void or a gap. Zero is the name of that nothing. Yet Frege defines zero as a number, to which he assigns the cardinal 1. This is where the “suture” comes from, from that eclipse of the zero by the one.
The non–self-identical answers fully, for Frege, to the principle by which, for any object, it must be possible to say under what concept it must be subsumed. Yet zero can be subsumed under the concept of non-self-identity as “identical to zero.” Thus, zero is identical to its concept, the concept of non-self-identity. Let there be a concept “identical to zero.” One and only one object, zero, is subsumed under that concept. “One” is thus by definition the cardinal number that belongs to that concept. Zero is “one” in the sense of self-identity. Now, in trying to make the number 1 appear, it must be shown that something can immediately follow zero in the series of natural numbers. “Zero,” Miller says, following Frege, “is the number assigned to the non-self-identical. This number is 1 [marked zero]. It follows that 1 follows immediately from 0 in the series of natural numbers.”12 And from there we can deduce the set of numbers, following the structure of “following from,” with the restriction that no number can follow itself in the natural series of numbers beginning with zero. Inscribing zero as a point of departure for the series of numbers makes it possible that the rule n + 1: 0 (self-identity of the concept “not identical to itself”) is followed by 1, which itself is followed by 2, then by 3, and so on.
Examining the Fregean argument, Miller concludes that the zero is at the same time summoned and dismissed. “That which in the real is pure and simple absence finds itself through the fact of number (through the instance of truth) noted 0 and counted for 1.”13 The word “suture” signifies (1) the uniting, by use of thread, of divided parts after an accident or surgical intervention and (2) the immobile articulation characterized by two jointed surfaces united by fibrous tissue, like those which from the cranium, the apparent line constituting the conjunction of two parts. The suture is thus always at the same time a division and conjunction. In every case, the seam, the conjunction, remains visible.
What is really sutured in Frege’s discourse in particular and in formal scientific language in general? Miller responds: the subject-function. “To designate it I choose the name of suture. Suture names the relation of the subject to the chain of its discourse.”14 The appearance-disappearance of the zero in the series of numbers figures the appearance-disappearance of the subject in the chain of its discourse.
Frege affirms, however, multiple times that logic does not follow from a subjective act, which is always psychological. Yet it is precisely this which appears to Miller as a denial. According to Frege, the subject counts for nothing. From this, it follows that suturing the zero can be read as suturing the subject. Indeed, for Miller, only the subject-function can subtend the operations of abstraction, of unification, and of progression. There is, therefore, identity only for a subject. It is the subject that produces the primary unity; it is impossible to think self-identity outside of the subject, since the subject-function is the identity-function. We’ve known since Descartes that a subject is, by definition, a power identical to itself. The subject is the form of identity. At the same time, like the zero, the subject is never self-identical. Like the zero, it receives its identity from a lack, it misses itself. The relationship of the zero to the chain of numbers is the same as the relationship of the subject to the chain of discourse. Like the zero, the subject is both present and absent at once. “It figures [in the chain] as the element which is lacking, in the form of a stand-in. For, while there lacking, it is not purely and simply absent.”15 Lacan shows that, in the same way that the zero is excluded from the beginning from the chain of numbers, the subject is excluded from the field of the Other, which is what comes to bar the subject. The subject displaces this bar onto the A, “a displacement whose effect is the emergence of signification signified to the subject.”16 Yet “untouched by the exchange of the bar, this exteriority of the subject to the Other is maintained, which institutes the unconscious.”17 The summation of the subject in the field of the other calls for its annulment.18 The subject, in this way, is always alienated from and by the very process of its signification.
Regarding Frege, we have spoken of (1) unity and (2) the role of 0 in succession, its status as number, and finally of its eclipse by the 1. This structure of appearance-disappearance, of suture, would be the point, emergent or derived, of a more originary logic which Miller, with Lacan’s help, proposes to name the “logic of the signifier”—a logic that proposes to “make itself known as a logic at the origin of logic,”19 which retraces the steps of logic, a “retroaction,”20 or a repression. “What is it that functions in the series of whole natural numbers to which we can assign their progression? And the answer, which I shall give at once before establishing it: in the process of the constitution of the series, in the genesis of progression, the function of the subject, miscognized, is operative.”21 Zero is the placeholder of the subject, which is itself, insofar as...

Índice